POLARIZATION, FRACTIONALIZATION AND CONFLICT(*) Autores: Joan Esteban. IAE (CSIC) Debraj Ray. NYU and IAE (CSIC)(**) P. T. N.o 7/07 (*) We are thankful to Marta Reynal-Querol and Gerald Schneider for useful comments. Esteban gratefully acknowledges support from the Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, the Polarization and Conflict project CIT-2-CT-2004-506084 funded by the European Commission-DG Research Sixth Framework Programme, Barcelona Economics (XREA) and the CICYT grant no. SEJ2006-00369. Ray gratefully acknowledges funding under National Science Foundation grant no. 0241070. (*) [email protected] and [email protected] N.B.: Las opiniones expresadas en este trabajo son de la exclusiva responsabilidad de los autores, pudiendo no coincidir con las del Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Desde el año 1998, la colección de Papeles de Trabajo del Instituto de Estudios Fiscales está disponible en versión electrónica, en la dirección: >http://www.minhac.es/ief/principal.htm. Edita: Instituto de Estudios Fiscales N.I.P.O.: 602-07-012-X I.S.S.N.: 1578-0252 Depósito Legal: M-23772-2001 INDEX 1. INTRODUCTION 2. POLARIZATION AND FRACTIONALIZATION 3. A MODEL OF WAR AND PEACE 3. 3.1. Conflict 3. 3.2. Peace 4. POLARIZATION, FRACTIONALIZATION, CONFLICT AND THE 4. POLITICAL SYSTEM (G=2) 5. POLARIZATION, CONFLICT AND THE POLITICAL RULES WITH 4. SEVERAL GROUPS 6. CONCLUSIONS REFERENCES SÍNTESIS. Principales implicaciones de política económica — 3 — RESUMEN Este trabajo proporciona una marco teórico para analizar los determinantes del conflicto y de su intensidad. Específicamente estudiamos el papel de la polarización y la fraccionalización social, condicionadas al sistema político vigente. Los resultados alcanzados son los siguientes: (i) los índices de fraccionalización y de polarización tienden a moverse en direcciones opuestas, (ii) el que estalle un conflicto depende críticamente del sistema político vigente, (iii) las causas del estallido de un conflicto y las de su intensidad también se mueven en direcciones opuestas. (iv) la relación entre polarización (o fracionalización) y conflicto es no­ monotónica y (v) la intensidad de un conflicto depende positivamente del grado de polarización. La relación entre política fiscal, distribución de la renta, polarización y cohesión social es bien conocida. Nuestros resultados implican que situaciones con un moderado grado de desigualdad pueden conducir al conflicto social, mientras que situaciones extremadamente polarizadas puede ser compatibles con la paz. JEL: D 31, D72 y D74. Palabras clave: Distribución de la Renta, Polarización, Conflicto, Cohesión Social. — 5 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales 1. INTRODUCTION A recent upsurge of empirical studies on the causes of conflict attempts to connect various features of the distribution of the relevant characteristic (typically ethnicity or religion) to conflict. The distributional indices differ(polarization, fractionalization or Lorenz-domination) and so do the various specifications of “conflict” (onset, incidence or intensity). Overall, the results are far from clear, and combined with the mixture of alternative indices and notions of “conflict” it is not surprising that the reader may come away thoroughly perplexed. The aim of this paper is to provide a theoretical framework that permits us to distinguish between the occurrence of conflict and its severity and that clarifies the role of polarization and fractionalization in each of these cases. Our analysis brings together strands from three of our previous contributions: on polarization (Esteban and Ray, 1994, and Duclos, Esteban and Ray, 2004), on conflict and distribution (Esteban and Ray, 1999) and on the viability of political systems (Esteban and Ray, 2001). Interest in the connections between inequality and conflict is not new, of course. Political scientists have been much concerned with these issues; see, for instance, the prominent contributions by Brockett (1992), Midlarski (1988), Muller and Seligson (1987), and Muller, Seligson and Fu (1989). Midlarski (1988) and Muller, Seligson and Fu (1989) had already voiced their reservations with respect to the standard notions of inequality as an appropriate tool for conflict analysis. To go even further back, Nagel (1974) had argued that the relationship between inequality and conflict should be non-linear. Indeed, as Lichbach’s (1989) survey concludes, the empirical studies on the relationship between inequality and conflict-and these typically posit a linear relationship-have only come up with ambiguous results. In the area of economics, the analysis of the link between distribution and conflict was largely inspired by a desire to study pathways between inequality and growth1. Certainly the possibility that inequality is a determinant of social conflict and –via this route– impedes growth is a contender for one of the more important pathways. The most recent round of interest in this connection was triggered by the contribution of Easterly and Levine (1997) who shifted the emphasis to ethnic fractionalization rather than economic inequality, but continued to emphasize the “reduced-form” connections with growth. Among the more relevant contributions to this literature are the papers by Alesina et al. (2003), Collier (1998, 2001), Collier and Hoeffler (2004), Fearon and Laitin (2003), Hegre et al. (2001), La Porta et al. (1999), Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005), Reynal-Querol (2002a) and Schneider and Wiesehomeier (2006a). 1 See Bénabou (1996) for a deep and comprehensive survey. — 7 — But the empirical results are ambiguous, if not controversial. If the pathway between fractionalization and growth runs through conflict, it is empirically hard to spot. By and large, it is fair to say that most of the literature fails to find any significant evidence of ethnic fractionalization as a determinant of conflict. This negative finding is underlined by Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005) who obtain, instead, a significant relationship between ethnic polarization and the incidence of conflict. (As we shall see below, the two variables are often at odds with each other.) While formally not using a measure of polarization, Collier and Hoeffler (2004) also argue that the contested dominance of one large group rather than fractionalization increases the probability of civil conflict. The Montalvo-Reynal-Querol result has recently been reassessed by Schneider and Wiesehomeier (2006a) using a different data set and focusing on onset, rather than incidence, of conflict. They argue that fractionalization is a better predictor of conflict than polarization. Without necessarily taking sides on the empirical merits of these papers, our purpose is to provide a simple theoretical framework that might help in ordering the various definitions, and in providing some explanations for the seemingly confusing evidence. To do this, we follow Esteban and Ray (2001)2. We first model the behaviour of players in case of conflict as a game and compute the equilibrium payoffs to all players. The status quo against which groups might rebel is characterized by a set of political institutions that channel the different opposing societal interests and turn them into a collective decision. Examples of such institutions are majoritarian or proportional democracies, dictatorships, oligarchies… We abstractly represent these institutions as alternative functions mapping the share of the population supporting each interest group into collective decisions. We take political institutions as given and hence disregard any potential endogeneity3. Groups will rebel against the ruling political institutions whenever the outcome is worse than what they can obtain through conflict. It is imperative to note that we distinguish between the intensity of conflict, conditional on conflict breaking out, and the likelihood that conflict actually occurs. The point that we make is very simple. When society is highly polarized, there may actually be a wider range of status-quo allocations that groups are willing to accept. This is because the potential cost of rebellion is extremely 2 This line is also adopted in Reynal-Querol (2002b). The point was already made by Lipset and Rokkan (1967) that political systems might be endogenous, influenced by the particular social structure of the country. Why then societies fail to adapt their institutions to the change of the environment so as to always prevent domestic conflict? A number of arguments have been put forward by Powell (2004) –incomplete information–, Fearon (1995), Powell (2006) and Leventoglu and Slantchev (2006) –inability to credibly commit–, and Esteban and Ray (2006c) –empty core– to explain the break out of conflict. We shall not pursue this line of enquire here and will take the political system as given. 3 — 8 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales high, and this cost of conflict serves as the guarantor of peace. Put another way, if conflict is very costly as it will be in highly polarized societies, it is easier to find an agreement that is Pareto superior to the conflict regime. At the same time, if conflict were to occur for some reason, its intensity would be higher in polarized societies. It follows that the intensity of conflict (conditional on its occurrence) and the likelihood of conflict may move in opposite directions with respect to changing polarization. In particular, when the cost of conflict is low, the parties will more easily reject proposals that slightly depart from what they can get through conflict. In the spirit of the fractionalization vs polarization controversy this argument can be summarized as follows. Highly fractionalized societies might be more prone to the onset of conflict, but its intensity will be moderate. In highly polarized societies, the occurrence of open conflict should be rare but its intensity very severe. In this paper we develop this argument and show that: (i) measures of fractionalization and polarization tend to run in opposite directions, (ii) the onset of conflict critically depends on the political system in place, (iii) the occurrence of conflict and the intensity of conflict also tend to move in opposite directions, (iv) the relationship between polarization or fractionalization and conflict is non-monotonic and (v) the intensity of conflict depends positively on the degree of polarization4. Our paper is organized as follows. We start by comparing the indices of fractionalization and polarization. Section 3 develops a simple model of conflict based on the general class studied in Esteban and Ray (1999). In order to present the ideas in the sharpest form, in Section 4 we start our study of the occurrence and intensity of conflict focusing on the case of two opposing groups only. This case permits a very neat understanding of the causes of intensity of conflict and the causes of its occurrence. However, as we shall see, in the case of two groups the notions of fractionalization and polarization are undistinguishable from each other. In section 5 we generalize the results to the case of an arbitrary number of groups and examine the different performance of the indices of polarization and fractionalization. Section 6 concludes. 2. POLARIZATION AND FRACTIONALIZATION We begin by defining the indices of fractionalization and polarization. The index of fractionalization F is intended to capture the degree to which a society is split into distinct groups. The measure has been widely used in studies 4 This discussion can also shed some light on the controversy on the stabilizing or destabilizing effects of “polarity”; a classic the international relations literature. See Waltz (1964) and Deutsch and Singer (1964), for instance. — 9 — that attempt to link ethnolinguistic diversity to conflict, public goods provision, or growth (see, e.g., Collier and Hoeffler (1998), Fearon and Laitin (2003), Easterly and Levine (1997) and Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999). Let ni be the share of the population belonging to group i, i 1, ,G . The fractionalization index is defined as the probability that two randomly chosen individuals belong to different groups. The probability that an individual of group i is chosen is ni . Hence that probability that if chosen she is matched with someone from another group is ni 1 ni . It follows that the probability that any two individuals belong to different groups is F ¦ ni (1 ni ) 1 ¦ ni2 (1) F is a strictly concave function of each population share. From this strict concavity we can derive the following properties of F. a) Any transfer of population from a group to a smaller one increases F. b) For a given number of groups, G, F is maximized at the uniform population distribution over these groups. c) Over the set of uniform distributions F increases with the number of groups; and d) The split of any group with population n into two new groups with n’ and n”, n’ + n” = n, increases F. Polarization is conceptualized in Esteban and Ray (1994) as the sum of inter­ personal “antagonisms”. Antagonism results from the interplay of the sense of group identification (group size) and the sense of alienation with respect to members of other groups (inter-group distance, bij ).5 Esteban and Ray’s polarization measure6 P can be written as i P(V,b) i ¦¦ ni1Vn jbij i jzi , (2) where b is the matrix of inter-group distances and V is a positive parameter that captures the extent of group identification. Esteban and Ray (see also 5 Alternative notions of polarization not based on the identity/alienation framework have been proposed by Wang and Tsui (2000), Reynal-Querol (2002c), and Zhang and Kanbur (2001). Another alternative and –considerably cruder– specification of polarization which also does not include a proxy for intra-group homogeneity in the absence of information is the concept of dominance that Collier (2001) introduced. It qualifies societies as “dominated” if the largest group contains between 45 and 90% of the overall population. 6 Esteban and Ray (1994) examine the main properties of this measure. The interested reader can also see Duclos, Esteban and Ray (2004) for a measure of polarization for continuous distributions. — 10 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales Duclos et al. (2004) derive restrictions on V that bound it both above and below. The exact form of these restrictions is not particularly important here, though we record for use below that V must be less than 2. A situation of particular relevance is the special case in which individuals in each group feel equally alien towards all groups other than their own. That is, bij bi for all j z i . In this case P reduces to P(V,b) ¦ ni1V 1 ni bi . (3) i Observe that if we set V 1 and bi 1 for all i we obtain the measure of polarization introduced by Reynal-Querol (2002c); a special case of (2). This specific measure of polarization was later used in Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005) to test the relationship between polarization and conflict. It is also true that we can formally set V 0 in (3), as well as bi 1 for all i, to arrive at the measure of fractionalization (1). We emphasize that this is a formal and not a conceptual connection: for (3) to be a measure of polarization it is necessary that V be strictly positive, and –depending on the exact character­ rization– perhaps more than that7. Nevertheless, it is useful to record that P (1,1) RQ and P (0,1) F , (4) where the entry 1 stands for the matrix of all 1’s. In order to simplify the computations, in this paper we shall work with the special class of polarization indices, P 1,1 , that is P { P (1,1) ¦ ni2 (1 ni ) . (5) i In order to examine the properties of P we start by observing that P is the 2 sum of the function p n n 1 n evaluated at the different ni . But now p . is convex or concave as n ! 1 3 . Therefore, we have the following properties for P. Properties of P a’) A transfer of population from a group to a smaller one increases P if both groups are larger than 1/3. If the two groups are smaller than 1/3 the equalization of populations will bring P down. b’) For any given number of groups, P is maximized when the population is concentrated on two equally sized groups only. c’) Over the set of uniform distributions P decreases with the number of groups, provided that there are at least two groups to begin with; and 7 For instance, Duclos, Esteban and Ray (2004) argue that s is at least 0.25. — 11 — d’) The split of a group with population n into two groups with n’ and n”, n’ + n” = n, increases P if and only if n 2/3. The contrast between the two sets of properties clearly shows that the two measures behave quite differently from each other, except when there are just two groups. The difference is clear: fractionalization is maximal when each individual is different from the rest while polarization is maximal when there are only two types of individuals. The reader is referred to Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005) for further discussion on the difference between these two measures. This completes our discussion of the indices. We now turn to a model of conflict and peace. 3. A MODEL OF WAR AND PEACE 3.1. Conflict We start with conflict as our first building block. In modeling conflict we follow Esteban and Ray (1999). We concentrate on a special case studied in that paper: the class of conflict games called contests. Assume that there are G alternatives, i 1, ,G . Individuals differ in the alternative they like the most and are indifferent over the other available alternatives. Individuals in a specific group i are all alike, in that they like alternative i the best, and the difference in valuation between their most preferred alternative and any other is the common value bi . Let ni denote the relative size of group i. Note that the alternatives here are public goods because their valuation by the individuals is independent of the number of beneficiaries. Therefore, we can think of alternatives as different kinds of public goods to be financed by the public budget. By a political system we shall refer to a particular way of choosing among the different alternatives. By conflict we mean a challenge to such a system, which is costly. Specifically, we take the following view. Conflict entails resource contributions ri (to be determined presently) from every member of group i, so that the overall contribution of group i is niri In the absence of a political rule, the particular alternative that will eventually come about is seen by the players as probabilistic. The probability that alternative i will be established is assumed to be equal to the resources niri expended by group relative to the total resources R expended. In short, the probability of success pi is just. pi niri nr { ii, R n jr j ¦ j — 12 — (6) Instituto de Estudios Fiscales where R is the sum of all the group contributions. In the sequel, we shall take this very R to be a measure of the overall intensity of conflict (or wastage) in the society. To understand how contributions are determined, suppose that there is a utility cost of spending ri ; call it c ri . Take this function to be of the constant­ elasticity form ri1D c(ri ) , with D ! 0 . (7) 1 D Given the resources expended by the others, ri , the expected utility of an individual of group i when spending ri is E(ui (ri )) pibi c(ri ) niri ri1 D bi . 1 D n jr j ¦ (8) j Expected utility is clearly concave in ri and hence the utility maximizing level of expenditure can be characterized by the first order condition: § · ¨ ¸ ni ¨ ni niri ¸ 1 pi bi riD . 1 bi (9) R n jrj ¨ n jrj ¸ ¨ ¸ j j © ¹ An equilibrium of the conflict game is a vector r such that (9) is satisfied for all i 1, ,G . ¦ ¦ There is always an equilibrium of the conflict game. Esteban and Ray (1999) demonstrate, furthermore, that if D t 1 then such an equilibrium must be unique. In order to simplify the computations we shall focus on the case of symmetric valuations, with bi 1 for all i, and D 1. Multiplying both sides of (9) by ni we obtain R 2 § ni · ¨ ¸ 1 pi pi , ©R¹ And transposing terms, we conclude that pi ni 2 ni 2 R 2 . (10) (11) The equilibrium value of R has to be such that the sum of the probabilities given by (11) adds up to unity, that is — 13 — ni 2 ¦ pi ¦ n 2 R 2 i i 1. (12) i The LHS of (12) is strictly decreasing in R. Using (10), it is immediate that when R goes to zero the LHS tends to G ! 1 and that when R tends to infinity the LHS tends to zero. Therefore a solution to (12) always exists and it is unique. Substituting the equilibrium R into (11) yields the equilibrium probabilities. In order to obtain a useful expression for equilibrium payoffs we multiply both sides of (9) by ri to see that 2 1 pi 1 pi 2 1 2 ri { c(ri ) . 2 (13) Using (13) in (8) yields pi (pi 1) . 2 For the case of two groups, G 2 , setting n1 equilibrium values are easy to compute: E(ui (ri )) p R E(u1(r1 )) (14) n and p1 p , the n, (15) n(1 n) , and n(n 1) and E(u2 (r2 )) 2 (16) (1 n)2 n . 2 (17) The equilibrium payoffs to conflict for player i will be simply denoted ui . 3.2. Peace In the previous subsection we have examined the equilibrium outcome of a conflict game under the assumption that conflict actually takes place. Now we are in a position to compare a conflictual situation with that of peace. Under peace, individuals must accept the payoff that the ruling political system allocates to them. As mentioned before, the political allocation can be interpreted as the share of the public budget allocated to the production of the type of public good most preferred by each group. We define a policy to be a vector J of shares, with J L denoting the share of group i. Hence, we can interpret J as a “compromise policy” composed of a convex linear combination over the available alternative types of public goods. Formally, we shall have peace whenever ui d J L for all i 1, ,G . — 14 — (18) Instituto de Estudios Fiscales It is trivial but nevertheless useful to observe that whether we have conflict or peace critically depends on what the ruling political system delivers to the different contending groups. A political system is a particular way of mapping the population shares supporting each alternative into policies. We shall examine here various political systems and check for their ability to guarantee peace. Specifically, we shall study dictatorship, fixed shares, majoritarian rule and proportional rule. Our first example of a political system is a dictatorship. This will be the case when the alternative preferred by some group i is brought into effect, irrespective of the number of individuals for whom this is the best choice. If group i is the dictator, then J i 1 and J j 0 for all j z i . The second case is fixed shares, which generalizes a dictatorship. The policy consists of a vector J assigning a share to each group independent of its population size. There are many instances of such a political system. Various political bodies have fixed proportional representations of the different opposing interests (often rural vs urban). There are also cases where the chairs of the two chambers have to alternate between the different ethnic or religious groups in the country8. The majoritarian rule generates the policies that earn the support of a majority of citizens. For the case of G 2 this is very easy to define: J L 1 if and only if ni ! 1/29. For G ! 2 the characterization of the policies resulting from a majoritarian rule is more intricate as it involves the formation of a majoritarian coalition. In some special environments there is a well-defined pivotal group (the median voter) who can impose its preferred policy to the rest of the majoritarian coalition. This is not the case here and hence most of what we can say will be restricted to the two-group case. Finally, the proportional rule produces the policy that assigns to each group a share equal to its population size: J i ni . Parliamentary representations satisfy 8 This was the first constitutional arrangement for the Lebanon after independence. The constitution established that the president had to be a Christian. The faster population growth rate among the Muslim population made this provision untenable and possibly contributed to the outbreak of the civil war. Another example is the EU “rotating presidency” across the member countries with a frequency that is independent of their population. 9 This is a extremely stylized representation of the majoritarian rule. Real world majoritarian democracies do not work like this. A number of written and/or unwritten rules protect minorities from the tyranny of the majority. This observation has led Lijphart (1977) to launch the concept of “consociational” policies that end up producing an outcome that approaches the proportionality rule. Lijphart has been a steady supporter of “consociational” constitutions for countries with deep ethnic cleavages. — 15 — this rule for most countries (not in the UK where each seat corresponds to one constituency). Although most decisions simply require a majority vote in the chamber, the resulting policies tend to give some weight to the minoritarian opposition. Multi-level government also contributes to give to the different groups an overall weight that brings them closer to their population share. In the next section we study the relationship between polarization, fractionalization and conflict under the different political systems for the case of two groups. In section 5 we generalize to G groups. 4. POLARIZATION, FRACTIONALIZATION, CONFLICT AND 4. THE POLITICAL SYSTEM G 2 We are interested here in two quite different aspects of conflict. In the first place, we want to characterize the relationship between the intensity conflict and polarization when conflict actually takes place. This relationship is independent of the political system. Secondly, we wish to identify the relationship between polarization and the occurrence of conflict (or peace!). Intensity of conflict We start by noting that for G 2 the measures F and P (and hence RQ) are proportional to each other. Furthermore, they all attain their maximum at n = 1/2. It follows that any comparative test of the performance of P (or RQ) relative to F as a predictor of conflict should focus on cases with G t 3 . We discuss this case in the next section. In view of (16), the level of conflict R is the square root of P and hence conflict intensity is an increasing function of polarization and of fractionalization10. 10 If we drop now the restriction that a = 1 but retain that b = 1, P(a,1) ceases to be proportional to F, but continues to behave like it. Indeed, P(a,1) is concave and attains its maximum at n = 1/2. Therefore, we will still have that increases in P(a,1) go with increases in the level of conflict R. Things are different when we allow for asymmetric inter-group distances. It can be readily verified that if b < 1 (>) both polarization and conflict are maximized at (two different) values nP,nR > 1/2 (<). Therefore, except for values of n within this interval, the level of conflict will be strictly increasing with polarization. The non­ monotonicity with respect to F and RQ will be for n in the interval (1/2,nR). — 16 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales Figure 1 R R 0 1/2 1 0 n 1/4 P In figure 1 we plot the intensity of conflict as a function of the population shares n (left figure) and of the corresponding level of polarization P (right figure). Intensity is maximal for n = ½, that is when polarization is also maximal with P = 1/4. Figure 2 u2 1 1 n'' 1 n' 0 n'' n' 1 u1 It will also be useful to record the equilibrium utility payoffs as given by (17) and which we represent in figure 2. These payoffs depend on the population distribution parameter n. The equilibrium utility for each player is the win probability p n minus the cost of the resources expended in conflict, equal for both types of players for G 2 . The win probabilities are points on the straight line between (0,1) and (1,0), the utility possibility frontier. Given n, from the corresponding point on the frontier we move inwards along a 45º line for a length equivalent to the utility loss caused by the spent resources. This gives us — 17 — a utility equilibrium pair. As we vary n we generate all the points of the equilibrium payoff curve. The maximum distance between the payoff curve and the frontier is at n = ½ where the conflict loss is maximal. So much for intensity. Let us now turn to the occurrence of conflict. This depends on the payoffs obtained in peace and these in turn depend on the political system. Dictatorship The first political system we examine is dictatorship. Will there ever be peace? The answer is no. The reason is simple. In equilibrium conflict, all players receive a strictly positive payoff because they could have opted for contributing nothing to conflict, thus guaranteeing for themselves a payoff of zero. Hence, for a non-dictator obtaining a peace payoff of zero is always dominated by the conflict payoff. Fixed shares We next examine the case of fixed shares J . The necessary and sufficient condition for conflict is that either n(1 n) (1 n)(2 n) ! J or ! 1 J . 2 2 (19) Figure 3 u2 1 1 n' ' 1 J 1 n' 0 n' ' n' 1 u1 The situation is captured in figure 3. Consider the peace share J and the corresponding utility payoff. For a population parameter like n’ the payoffs to conflict are dominated by the peace payoff for the two players. However, if we — 18 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales decrease sufficiently the population share of the first group–all the way down to n”, the second group would have a strong advantage over the first in conflict and thus prefers conflict to the peace payoff. To be more specific, let us rewrite the inequalities in (19) as n(1 n) n(1 n) ! J or n J. (20) 2 2 The LHS of the two inequalities is strictly increasing in n (one convex and the other concave). Therefore, there exist n’ and n” such that if n [n',n" ] there is peace and conflict otherwise. In figure 4 we depict the values of n for which, given J , we shall have peace. These are the values of n corresponding to the points on the equilibrium utility curve at which one of the two players is indifferent with respect to the peace payoff. Figure 4 n u2 1 1 n' 1 J 1 n' ' 0 n' J n'' 1 u1 Clearly, the interval of values of n for which there will be peace depends on the bias exhibited by the fixed-shares policy J . Let us take as a benchmark the case of equal treatment of the two groups of players with J = ½. From our previous analysis it follows that for very low polarization (i.e. for very low or very large n) there will be conflict, but its level will be low. As polarization increases the level of conflict will increase too. But, further increases in polarization will produce peace and bring the level of conflict down to zero. The overall relationship between polarization or fractionalization and conflict is therefore non-monotonic. We can address the complementary question of the range of policies J that would guarantee peace for given n. This range is given by the gap between the — 19 — two bounds: n(1-n). Hence the widest range for peaceful policies corresponds to n = 1/2. High polarization allows for a wider choice of peaceful fixed-share policies. The intuition for this result is straightforward. If there is conflict, higher polarization produces larger losses. Hence, it is only when the policy is very biased against one group that that group will decide to incur the heavy cost of conflict. With low polarization the costs are smaller and hence a lower bias in J might be enough to trigger conflict. Majority rule The case of majority rule is equivalent to letting the largest group become a dictator. By the same argument as before, we shall never have peace as the minoritarian group will always obtain a higher payoff under conflict than under peace. Hence, with majority rule we shall always have conflict11 and the level of conflict will positively depend on the degree of polarization. Proportional rule We start by noting that in the previous case of fix shares, in view of (20), when J is sufficiently close to the win probability of that group peace will not be challenged. Under our assumptions, p n and hence making J n would guarantee peace. This precisely is the proportional rule that gives each group a share equal to its population size, that is, J i ni . Therefore, for symmetric valuations we should never observe conflict under the proportionality rule12. The intuition for this result is that the proportionality rule gives to each group a weight that is close to their win probability under conflict. Hence, it never pays to challenge the peace allocation13. As we will see, this result is specific to the two-group case and does not extend to the case of a larger number of groups. Diagrammatically, we can see in figure 2 that the point (n,1-n) always dominates the conflict equilibrium payoffs. 11 Let us insist in that this statement is not meant to be empirically relevant as none of the existing majoritarian democracies permits the tyranny of the majority. From an empirical point of view the practical distinction between majoritarian and proportional democracies is far from clear. The use of the notion of “inclusiveness” of a political system as in ReynalQuerol (2005) might be more relevant. 12 This is no longer true for asymmetric valuations. The equilibrium p can be made arbitrarily close to unity by choosing b for one group sufficiently close to zero. 13 This result seems to substantiate Lijphart’s view that “consociational” systems, because they are essentially proportional, permit peaceful arrangement in ethnically divided societies. [see more in footnote 13]. — 20 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales Summing up In this section we have obtained two main results. The first one is that it does matter for conflict which political system is in place. Dictatorships and majoritarian systems never yield peace. Fixed shares may give peaceful outcomes for some parameter values. The proportional system always yields peace, at least whenever there are just two groups. The second result is that while the intensity of conflict is positively related to the degree of polarization, the incidence of conflict is not. Only in the fixed shares system does the incidence of conflict depend on the distribution of the population across the two groups. For the other three political systems the incidence of conflict is independent of the distribution (and hence of the degree of polarization). For the fixed shares system conflict is more likely at low levels of polarization and peace more likely at high levels. Therefore, if there is any relation between conflict and polarization this is non-monotonic. Our analysis also suggests that if one wishes to test for the occurrence of conflict, the political system appears to be a key variable, along with the degree of social polarization (or fractionalization). 5. POLARIZATION, CONFLICT AND POLITICAL RULES WITH 5. SEVERAL GROUPS We shall examine now whether our previous conclusions can be extended to the general case of several groups. Intensity of conflict We start with the relationship between polarization and the intensity of conflict, R. The relationship between the intensity of conflict and polarization has been extensively studied in Esteban and Ray (1999, section 6). Using Esteban and Ray (1999, expression 16) we can write R ¦ i ni 2 ni (1 ni )bi . pi (21) Comparing (21) with the measure of polarization P in (4) we can observe that, if pi ni , the level of conflict R would be equal to the index of polarization P 1,b . The n/p ratio is determined in equilibrium and will generally be different from unity. Therefore, how closely related P is to R critically depends on how much n/p varies across the different groups in equilibrium. It can be shown that the — 21 — case in which ni pi 1 for all i is specific to the symmetric case for G 2 or for uniform distributions over G ! 2 groups. Therefore, on these grounds alone, we should a priori expect a positive but incomplete association between polarization P 1,b [and hence P 1,1 RQ ] and the level of conflict R. However, the discussion that now follows suggests that there are pretty tight connections between the two. Drawing on the results in Esteban and Ray (1999) we can restate the following properties of R, implicitly determined in (12), to be contrasted with the properties of F and P presented in section 2. (i) A transfer of population from a group to a smaller one increases R if both groups are larger than 1/3. If the two groups are small enough the equalization of populations will bring R down. (ii) For any given G, R is maximized when the population is concentrated on two equally sized groups only. (iii) Over the set of uniform distributions R decreases with the number of groups G; and (iv) The split of a group with population n into two groups with n’ and n”, n’ + n” = n, increases R if and only if the group size is sufficiently large. If n is small, the split will decrease R. Do the properties of our theoretical model align with our intuition on the intensity of conflict? Consider conflict among three groups of varying size. Property (i) says that equalizing the size of the two largest groups will increase conflict while reducing the size of the second largest group at the benefit of the smallest will reduce conflict. Property (ii) appears to conform to the common intuition that conflict is worst when society is split into two equally sized groups. In the case considered by Property (iii) each group becomes progressively smaller, while its collective opponent (the rest of the groups) becomes larger. In this case the smaller groups will commit less resources into conflict. As for Property (iv), consider first the case of a monolithic society that gets split into two distinct groups. This must increase the intensity of conflict. The same has to be true even if the initial society was not monolithic, but had a small “dissident” group. But suppose now that after the first split the second sized group splits into two smaller groups. Then we would expect that conflict would come down because now the untouched group has become relatively larger than the others. The smaller groups may not be willing to contribute a lot of resources to conflict. In sum, the properties displayed by our conflict model do not seem to contradict our intuitions about conflict intensity. Let us now compare the properties of R and P. It is immediate that the two sets of properties describe movements in the same direction for the type of population — 22 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales changes considered. Hence, we should expect a strong positive relation between polarization and conflict intensity. [See a parametric illustration below]. How does the index of fractionalization F behave relative to R? Property (i) of R is not satisfied by F. Property (a) of F says that any equalization of sizes will increase F. In contrast, R may go either up or down depending on the size of the groups involved. Properties (ii) and (b) are aligned as long as there are two groups in conflict to start with. With more groups F is maximized at the uniform distribution while R continues to be maximal when the population is concentrated on two equally sized groups. Properties (iii) and (c) are exactly the opposite of each other. Finally, when we compare Properties (iv) and (d) we observe that any split always increases F, while R may either decrease or increase depending on the size of the broken group. We can thus conclude that we can expect a strong positive relationship between polarization and conflict, and a weak and (if anything) negative relationship between fractionalization and conflict, at least insofar as intensity is concerned. We now turn to an analysis of the incidence of conflict when there are more than two groups. Dictatorship and majoritarian rule Notice our arguments on the impossibility of peace under dictatorship or the majoritarian rule did not depend on the number of groups. In both cases, the excluded groups will obtain a lower payoff than what they can obtain under conflict. Fixed shares From (14) we have that there will be conflict whenever pi (1 pi ) ! J i for some i 1, ,G . 2 Using (11) in (22) we obtain that the condition for conflict is ui 1 ni2 §¨ ni2 ·¸ 1 ! Ji . 2 ni2 R 2 ¨© ni2 R 2 ¸¹ (22) (23) Consider any given vector of shares J and a particular group of size ni . Observe that the payoff ui can take values in (0,1) depending on R. Therefore, the condition for conflict is most likely to be satisfied when R is small and hence polarization is small too. To be precise, suppose that all the remaining groups have the same size, n j 1 ni , j z i . It can be readily verified from (12) that R is strictly G 1 — 23 — decreasing in G. It follows that there is a G sufficiently large so that a uniform distribution over the G-1 remaining groups would induce group i to prefer conflict. Note that as G becomes large polarization comes down and fractionalization goes up. Therefore we shall see conflict with low levels of polarization and high levels of fractionalization, but the intensity of conflict will be low. In the discussion above, observe that it is the untouched group, the group which has become larger relative to the others, is the one who prefers conflict to peace. Hence, even in this case, one might argue that it is not high fractionalization as such that precipitates conflict but the coexistence of one large group with numerous small groups. In fact, if we now equalize the size of all the groups, thus increasing F and decreasing P, no group would have an incentive to challenge the peace share and we would have peace with higher fractionalization. To sum up, for the egalitarian fixed shares policy, conflict will not occur in economies with high polarization/low fractionalization. For distributions displaying low polarization/high fractionalization, the relation between conflict and F or P will be non-linear. Conflict will be most likely for distributions with one large group and many small ones (and hence with relatively high fractionalization and low polarization). As the rule of fixed shares departs from egalitarianism, the occurrence of conflict will critically depend upon the bias introduced by the rule. Proportional rule Once again, from (14) we have that under the proportional rule there will be conflict whenever p i 1 ni ! for some i 1, ,G . 2 pi (24) In the previous section we have seen that for G 2 the proportional rule always guarantees peace. Does this property extend to G ! 2 ? A first observation is that for the distributions under which the equilibrium win probabilities are very close to the population shares condition (24) will not be satisfied and we shall observe peace. We shall only have conflict when pi is sufficiently larger than ni for some group i. Using (10) in (14), we can rewrite condition (24) as 2 · § ni 1 ¨1 ni ¸ ! 1. 2 2 2 2 ¨ 2 ni R © ni R ¸¹ The LHS of (25) can take values in (0, (25) 1 ), depending on R. Provided 2ni 1, 2ni we have already seen that there is a distribution of the population (for — 24 — G Instituto de Estudios Fiscales sufficiently large) so that group i will prefer conflict over peace. Esteban and Ray (2001) demonstrate that under these assumptions there always are distributions for which (25) is satisfied for one group. Here are two numerical examples: G 5 with one group being 1/3 of the population and the other four of size 1/6; and G 4 with one group of size 1/2 and the other three of size 1/614. As in the case of fixed coefficients conflict occurs in very skewed distributions by size. One large group together with a number of small sized groups is the type of distribution that would be more likely to generate open conflict. Because of the returns to scale in conflict, the win probability of the large group may amply exceed its population share. Furthermore, precisely because of the returns to scale the small groups will be deterred from expending much resources in such an uneven conflict and hence we shall observe a low conflict loss R. High win probabilities together with small aggregate losses make conflict preferable to peace as far as the large group is concerned. Therefore, we may conclude that with G ! 2 under the proportional rule we may have conflict. This will be associated with distributions with low polarization and high fractionalization. However, the relationship will be non-monotonic: additional increases in fractionalization may bring peace rather than further conflict. In order to illustrate this relationship consider the following parametric example. There are three groups with n1 = ½, n2 = O ½, and n3 = (1- O ½, 0 O ½. When O = 0 we have two groups with the same population and thus maximal polarization. When O = ½ we shall have the same first group facing two groups of half the size. F and P can be computed to be F(O) 1 O O2 , and 2 (26) 3 O O2 1 F P(O) . (27) 8 2 4 From (27) it is plain that when O changes fractionalization and polarization move in opposite directions: as we move away from the perfect bipolar distribution P comes down but F goes up. Using this parametrization for the distribution of the population in expression (12) we implicitly obtain the equilibrium intensity of conflict R as a function of O . Totally differentiating, we obtain that R decreases as O increases, i.e. as P 14 The case of India has been taken as a critical test for Lijphart’s claim that “consociational” systems –hence proportional– are guarantors of ethnic peace. Most of the debate, Lijphart (1996) and Wilkinson (2000), has focused on whether India was more “consociational” under Nerhu or more recently. Our analysis suggests that the change in population sizes of Hindus, Muslims and others that has actually taken place in India in 1961-2001 might also have a role in explaining the evolution of ethnic conflict. — 25 — decreases and as F increases. Conflict intensity goes from R(0) = 0.5 to R(1/2) = 0.211. This is depicted in figure 5. Whether there will be conflict or peace under the proportional rule depends on whether the untouched group –always with population ½– obtains a conflict equilibrium utility higher or lower than ½. In figure 5 we also depict u1 as a function of O . Not surprisingly, as O increases group 1 is facing smaller and smaller enemies. Hence, u1 increases with O . The large group obtains a higher utility from conflict the less polarized the distribution is. The equilibrium utility goes from u1 (0) = 0.375 to u1 (1/2) = 0.837. It follows that for low O the equilibrium utility of group 1 will be below the peace payoff and there will be peace. This corresponds to the highest levels of polarization and lowest of fractionalization. For O ! O0 [see figure 5] there will be conflict. Therefore, open conflict will be associated with low polarization and high fractionalization. Figure 5 ~ 5 6 u1 1 2 3 8 O 0 1 2 O We finally combine the intensity with the occurrence of conflict and derive the relationship between observable intensity of conflict and both fractionalization and polarization. This is depicted in figure 6. As we can see, in both cases the relation is nonmonotonic. For the case of fractionalization, there is peace until the threshold level F0 is reached. At this point, there is conflict and it attains its maximum intensity. For higher values of F we continue to have conflict but its intensity monotonically comes down. The relationship between P and observable intensity of conflict is the other side of the coin. Open conflict occurs at low levels of polarization. As polarization goes up the intensity of conflict raises until the threshold P0 is attained. For higher levels of polarization — 26 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales the costs of conflict are so high that we will observe peace. The two functions are depicted in figure 6. Figure 6 R R F0 F P0 P Summing up When we consider distributions with more than two groups it is still true that the occurrence of conflict critically depends on the particular political system in place. Dictatorship and the majoritarian rule can never bring peace, as we already observed for G 2 . But in general, both fixed shares and proportional rule fail to universally guarantee peaceful outcomes. We shall not see conflict neither for very low nor for very high levels of fractionalization15 and a similar (but inverse) pattern would be followed by polarization. Concerning the general relationship between polarization, fractionalization and conflict our results suggest that they will be significantly nonlinear. Under some political systems the occurrence of conflict is independent of the shape of the distribution while in other systems it does depend on the shape. Under the first class of political systems the intensity of conflict will be closely (positively) related to the degree of polarization (and negatively to fractionalization). Under the second class (fixed and proportional shares) we shall observe zero intensity at high and very low levels of polarization (and fractionalization). For the range of levels of 15 This seems to contradict the result obtained by our parametric example above. This is due to the very special change in the distribution that our parametrization allows for. Consider for instance our limit case with l = ½ (n1 = ½, n2 = ¼, n3 = ¼). Fractionalization is maximal and we still have conflict. However, if we now move to n1 = n2 = n3 = 1/3 –not allowed by our parametrization– fractionalization would be even higher but there would be no conflict. — 27 — polarization for which we shall have conflict, higher polarization will be positively related to higher intensity of conflict. As far as fractionalization is concerned there seems to be no regular relationship between its level and the intensity of conflict. All these results suggest that there may be more to be learned from empirical exercises that put all the evidence together and also attempt to control for the political system of each country16. 6. CONCLUSIONS We provide an analytical framework that permits an interpretation of recent empirical exercises attempting to identify a meaningful relationship between population distributions over opposing groups and emergence or intensity of conflict. Conflict breaks out when the payoffs delivered by the political system fall short of what one group can obtain by precipitating conflict. While the intensity of conflict clearly depends on the shape of the distribution, the occurrence of conflict also depends on the responsiveness of each political system to the popular support for each of the competing alternatives. When we combine occurrence with intensity, the relationship between conflict and polarization/fractionalization becomes significantly non-linear and contingent on the ruling political system. The rationale behind our result is quite straightforward. Conflict is costly. That is overall payoffs are less than what are achievable under peace. The costlier conflict is (if it actually takes place) the easier it becomes to assign payoffs to groups that Pareto dominate what they can obtain under conflict. Therefore, only the political systems with very unfair outcomes (such as dictatorship or majoritarian rule) will be always be challenged even when the cost of doing so is high. However, under “fairer” systems no group would be willing to pay too high a cost to obtain a different payoff. Therefore, it is only when conflict is nearly costless to one group (such as the case of one large group and a number of small opponents) that the outcome of the political system will be challenged, by that precisely that large group17. 16 Political scientists have been aware for long of the critical role played by the political institutions in preventing domestic conflict. The work of Lijphart (1977) is fundamental here. See also the recent controversy between Horowitz (2006) and Fraenkel and Grofman (2006) on the effectiveness of constitutional engineering. Our point is that in spite of this important line of literature, empirical tests on the determinants of conflict have very seldom controlled for the political system. An exception is the work by Reynal-Querol (2002b, 2005) and by Schneider and Wiesehomeier (2006b) who do study the relationship between political systems and domestic conflict. 17 Note the similarity of this point with the findings of Collier (2001) on the dominant ethnicity provoking civil war. One should qualify these points, however, by observing that small groups can provoke conflict when private goods are at stake. For more on this issue, see Esteban and Ray (2006b). — 28 — Instituto de Estudios Fiscales Highly polarized situations may well be fairly peaceful. This is what happened during the Cold War period, for instance. The cost of challenging the international status quo was so immense that even if one of the two sides considered the division of international power disproportionate it could not-or would not-trigger a world conflict. At the same time, when polarization is extremely low, there is little to fight about. Consequently, we would expect the overall degree of conflict to be maximal in societies with intermediate levels of polarization. What, then, are the hopes for the empirical exercises that try to identify a relationship between polarization/fractionalization and conflict? Two recommendations appear to emerge. First, there should be a serious attempt to account for the nonlinearity. For instance, in a parametric context, some progress may be possible by entering both polarization and its square on the right-hand-side of a regression18. But the prescription is simply this: the empirical specification needs to be more firmly grounded in theory, even if that theory is extremely simple. Second, we have seen that the incidence of conflict depends not only on the shape of the distribution but also critically on the ruling political system. Alternative political systems perform quite differently in guaranteeing peace. For the countries with political systems that always yield conflict we shall observe that the intensity of conflict is (roughly) positively related to polarization (and negatively) to fractionalization. However, in countries with political systems that may yield peace, the occurrence and intensity of conflict will typically have a highly non-linear relationship with polarization and/or fractionalization. It follows that the exercise critically demands that political systems be controlled for19. 18 On a similar issue arising in the empirical debate on inequality and growth (though for very different reasons), see Banerjee and Duflo (2003). 19 Reynal-Querol (2002b) has tested the relationship between type of political system (their degree of inclusiveness) and conflict. However, in Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005) the empirical test of whether polarization or fractionalization are the best predictors for conflict does not use the political systems as controls. Schneider and Wieserhomeier (2006b) also emphasize the critical role played by the political institutions in the occurrence of conflict. — 29 — REFERENCES ALESINA, A.; DEVLEESCHAUWER, A.; EASTERLY, W.; KURLAT, S. and WACZIARG, R. (2003): “Fractionalization.” Journal of Economic Growth 8 155-194. BANERJEE, A. and DUFLO, E. (2003): “Inequality and Growth: What Can the Data Say?” Journal of Economic Growth 8, 267-299. BÉNABOU, R. (1996): “Inequality and Growth,” NBER Macroeconomics Annual, B. Bernanke and J. Rotemberg eds. MIT Press, 11-4. COLLIER, P. (1998): “The Political Economy of Ethnicity.” Paper prepared for the Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics, Washington D.C., april 20-21, 1998. – (2001): “Implications of Ethnic Diversity.” Economic Policy 129-66. COLLIER, P. and HOEFFLER, A. (1998): “On economic causes of civil war.” Oxford Economic Papers 50 563-573. – (2004): “Greed and Grievance in Civil War”. Oxford Economic Papers 56 563-95. DEUTSCH, KARL WOLFGANG and DAVID SINGER, J. (1964): 'Multipolar Power Systems and International Stability', World Politics 16: 390-406. DUCLOS, J-Y; ESTEBAN, J.; and RAY, D. (2004): “Polarization: Concepts, Measurement, Estimation” Econometrica 72 1737-72. EASTERLY, W. and LEVINE, R. (1997): “Africa’s Growth Tragedy: Policies and Ethnic Divisions.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 1203-50. ESTEBAN, J. and RAY, D. (1994): “On the Measurement of Polarization.” Econometrica 62 819-51. – (1999): “Conflict and Distribution.” Journal of Economic Theory 87 379-415 – (2001): “Social Rules are not Immune to Conflict.” Economics of Governance 2 59-67. – (2006a): “A Model of Ethnic Conflict.” Unpublished manuscript. – 2006b): “On the Salience of Ethnic Conflict.” Unpublished manuscript. – (2006c): “War with Perfect Information.” Unpublished manuscript. Fearon, J.D. (1995): “Rationalist Explanations of War.” International Organization 49 379-414. FEARON, J.D. and LAITIN, D.D. (2003): “Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil War.” American Political Science Review 97 75-90. FRAENKEL, J. and GROFMAN, B. (2006): “Does the alternative vote foster moderation in ethnically divided societies? The case of Fiji.” Comparative Political Studies 39 623-651. — 31 — HEGRE, H.; ELLINGSON, T.; GATES, S. and GLEDITSCH, N.P. (2001): "Towards a Democratic Civil Peace? Democracy, Political Change, and Civil War, 1816­ 1992." American Political Science Review 95 33-48. HOROWITZ, D.L. (2006): “Strategy takes a holiday: Fraenkel and Grofman on the alternative vote.” Comparative Political Studies 39 652-662. LA PORTA, R.; LOPEZ DE SILANES, F.; SHLEIFER, A. and VISHINY, R. (1999): “The Quality of Government.” Journal of Law Economics and Organization 15 222-79. LEVENTOGLU, B. and SLANTCHEV, B.L. (2006): “The Armed Peace: A Punctuated Equilibrium Theory of War.” Unpublished manuscript. LIJPHART, A. (1977): Democracy in Plural Societies: A Comparative Exploration. New Haven: Yale University Press. – (1996): “The Puzzle of Indian Democracy: A Consociational Interpretation.” American Political Science Review 90 258-268. LIPSET, SEYMOUR; ROKKAN, STEIN. (1967): Party Systems and Voter Alignments. Cross-National Perspectives. New York: The Free Press. MONTALVO, J.G. and REYNAL-QUEROL, M. (2005): “Ethnic Polarization, Potential Conflict, and Civil Wars.” American Economic Review 95 796-815. NAGEL, J. (1974): "Inequality and Discontent: A non-linear hypothesis", World Politics 26 453-472. POWELL, R. (2004): “Bargaining and Learning While Fighting.” American Journal of Political Science 48 344-361. – (2006): “War as a Commitment Problem.” International Organization 60 169-203. REYNAL-QUEROL, M. (2002a): “Ethnicity, Political Systems, and Civil Wars.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 46 29-54. – (2002b): “Political Systems, Stability and Civil Wars.” Defense and Peace. – (2002c): “A Contribution on the Measurement of Religious Diversity.” PRPES Working Paper No.4, Wheatherhead Center for International Affairs, Harvard University. – (2005): “Does Democracy Preempt Civil Wars?.” European Journal of Political Economy 21 445-465. SCHNEIDER, G. and WIESEHOMEIER, N. (2006a): “Ethnic Polarization, Potential Conflict, and Civil Wars: Comment.” Unpublished Manuscript. – (2006b, this issue): “Rules that Matter. Political Institutions and the Polarization-Conflict Nexus.” Unpublished Manuscript. WALTZ, K.N. (1964): “The Stability of a Bipolar World.” Daeadlus 93 881-909. WILKINSON, S.A. (2000): “India, Consociational Theory, and Ethnic Violence.” Asian Survey 40 767-791 — 32 — SÍNTESIS PRINCIPALES IMPLICACIONES DE POLÍTICA ECONÓMICA Explícita o implícitamente se justifica la necesidad de la redistribución de la renta con el argumento de que una excesiva desigualdad amenaza la cohesión social y puede provocar situaciones de conflicto abierto. Este es el argumento central del reciente trabajo de Acemoglu y Robinson (2000) –véase también su reciente libro– sobre la extensión del derecho de voto en muchos países industrializados a finales del siglo XIX. Dar derecho de voto a los trabajadores industriales era la forma de garantizar la irreversibilidad de un nivel de redistribución de renta que desalentase las tentaciones revolucionarias. Otro ejemplo del mismo razonamiento [quizás más cercano a temas relevantes para España] es el trabajo de Lebreton y Weber (2003) y Haimanko, Lebreton y Weber (2005) en el que estudian el diseño de transferencias interregionales que eviten secesiones en un estado. De hecho, este tema no es más que otra forma de plantear el clásico dilema en Economía Pública entre los objetivos de eficiencia y equidad. Los incentivos que demanda la mera eficiencia pueden ser incompatibles con la mínima equidad necesaria para garantizar la paz social. Esta cuestión está también en el centro del actual debate sobre las causas de los frecuentes conflictos étnicos, religiosos y nacionalistas que parecen caracterizar el mundo contemporáneo tras el colapso de la URSS. Si los conflictos ocurren y tienen altos costes económicos ha de ser cierto que los mecanismos políticos no han permitido establecer el grado de redistribución que hubiese impedido el conflicto. El tema del presente trabajo es precisamente el estudio de la relación entre la distribución de la población, el sistema político vigente y la existencia de conflicto. Tal como se argumenta en Esteban y Ray (1994 y 1999), es la polarización, más que la desigualdad, la que conduce al conflicto. En Esteban y Ray (1999) se presenta un modelo de conflicto en el que se demuestra que el nivel de conflicto de equilibrio crece con el grado de polarización. Sin embargo, ello es cierto en el caso de que efectivamente haya conflicto. Situémonos en el momento en el que hay que decidir si se acepta el status quo o se desencadena una situación de conflicto. El hecho de saber que el conflicto va a ser muy intenso y costoso hace que para todos los grupos participantes el conflicto sea poco atractivo y que, por tanto, la decisión óptima sea la paz. Al contrario, cuando las ganancias esperadas de un conflicto son pequeñas, el coste del conflicto será también pequeño, por lo que puede resultar que el balance neto de un conflicto sea positivo. De este argumento se sigue que la relación entre desigualdad/conflicto será no-lineal. Los politólogos siempre han estado interesados en la relación entre desigualdad y conflicto: Brockett (1992), Midlarski (1988), Muller y Seligson (1987), y Muller, Seligson y Fu (1989). Midlarski (1988) y Muller, Seligson y Fu (1989) ya han manifestado sus reservas respecto a las nociones estándar de desigualdad como — 33 — instrumento útil para el análisis del conflicto. Mucho antes, Nagel (1974) ya argumentó que la relación entre desigualdad y conflicto tenía que ser no-lineal. Con todo, tal como concluye el survey de Lichbach (1989), el resultado de todas estas contribuciones es completamente ambiguo. En el área de la Economía, el interés es mucho más reciente, pero los resultados no son mejores. La relación entre desigualdad y conflicto ha sido estudiada desde la perspectiva del desarrollo económico [ver Bénabou (1996) para un detallado survey]. Tras la contribución de Easterly y Levine (1997) –quien puso énfasis en la “fraccionalización” (en vez de la desigualdad)– han habido contribuciones relevantes por parte de Alesina et al. (2003), Collier (1998, 2001), Collier y Hoeffler (2004), Fearon y Laitin (2003), Hegre et al. (2001), La Porta et al. (1999), Montalvo and Reynal-Querol (2005), Reynal-Querol (2002) y Schneider y Wiesehomeier (2006). Donde los resultados empíricos son más esperanzadores es en el papel de la polarización en el conflicto, tal como se desprende del trabajo de Montalvo y ReynalQuerol (2005). Pero aún en esta cuestión existen dudas y ambigüedades. ¿Cuándo puede decirse que una sociedad está en conflicto? ¿Hemos de medir la eclosión de un conflicto o la frecuencia con la que un país se encuentra en conflicto?. El objetivo de esta investigación es proporcionar un marco analítico que permite desarrollar un estudio ordenado del efecto de la desigualdad y/o polarización sobre el conflicto. Para ello, construimos un modelo de conflicto y computamos los pagos de equilibrio que reciben los jugadores. El status quo contra el que los grupos sociales pueden rebelarse está caracterizado por un conjunto de instituciones políticas que canalizan los distintos intereses contrapuestos hacia una decisión colectiva. La democracia proporcional o mayoritaria, la oligarquía o la dictadura son ejemplos de instituciones políticas. Habrá paz social siempre que las instituciones políticas proporcionen a todos los grupos sociales un pago no inferior al que pueden obtener provocando una situación de conflicto. Con este marco analítico demostramos los siguientes puntos: (i) las medidas de fraccionalización y de polarización tienden a ir en direcciones opuestas; (ii) el que pueda o no estallar un conflicto depende críticamente del sistema político vigente; (iii) el que haya conflicto y su intensidad tienden a moverse en direcciones opuestas; (iv) la relación del conflicto tanto con polarización como con fraccionalización es no-monotónica; y (v) la intensidad del conflicto depende positivamente del nivel de polarización. Las implicaciones de este trabajo son relevantes respecto a la reciente literatura que intenta establecer empíricamente un nexo entre desigualdad o polarización y conflicto social. La relación entre política fiscal, distribución de la renta, polarización y cohesión social es bien conocida. Las distorsiones creadas por los impuestos redistributivos son el coste necesario para moderar la conflictividad social potencial. Esta visión está basada en la visión de que la única fuente relevante de conflictos sociales deriva de las desigualdades económicas entre “clases”. Cuanto mayor es la desigualdad más probable es que se registre conflictividad social. Por lo tanto, según esta visión, un grado suficiente de igualdad garantiza la paz y cohesión social. Este argumento presentas dos problemas. En primer lugar, hay motivos para sospechar que la relación entre conflicto y tanto desigualdad como polarización es no­ — 34 — lineal. Ello implica que situaciones con un moderado grado de desigualdad pueden conducir al conflicto social, mientras que situaciones extremadamente polarizadas puede ser compatibles con la paz social. En segundo lugar, y siguiendo con el punto de vista de la política presupuestaria y fiscal, este trabajo sugiere que en la distribución de los recursos públicos es preciso tener presente otras dimensiones, aparte de las clases sociales definidas por nivel de renta. Los recientes argumentos sobre “balanzas fiscales” territoriales indican un incremento de la sensibilidad en esta dimensión. Pero tampoco hay que descartar otras dimensiones, como la religiosa o la étnica que pueden estar actualmente latentes. En síntesis, la visión subyacente a la Economía Pública de la segunda mitad del siglo XX ha estado dominada por la necesidad de moderar las desigualdades generadas por el mercado con el fin de evitar un conflicto entre clases sociales. El actual estado del bienestar ha sido la respuesta europea a este reto y ha alejado completamente el riesgo de una revolución social. Sin embargo, observamos que en la actualidad las fracturas sociales se fundamentan en motivos nacionalistas, religiosos o étnicos, frente a los cuales aún aplicamos de forma inercial los razonamientos del siglo pasado. La política redistributiva no debería perder de vista la distribución de recursos sociales – especialmente los de la administración– teniendo también en cuenta las nuevas características relevantes. Tal como se razona –y se demuestra– en este trabajo, el que en estas nuevas dimensiones las desigualdades no sean muy grandes no es indicativo de que no puedan ser pronto una fuente de conflicto abierto. REFERENCIAS ACEMOGLU, D. and ROBINSON, J.A. (2000): "Why Did The West Extend The Franchise? Democracy, Inequality, And Growth In Historical Perspective," The Quarterly Journal of Economics 115, 1167-1199. ALESINA, A.; DEVLEESCHAUWER, A.; EASTERLY, W.; KURLAT, S. and WACZIARG, R. (2003): “Fractionalization.” Journal of Economic Growth 8, 155-194. BÉNABOU, R. (1996): “Inequality and Growth,” NBER Macroeconomics Annual, B. Bernanke and J. Rotemberg eds. MIT Press, 11-74. COLLIER, P. (1998): “The Political Economy of Ethnicity.” Paper prepared for the Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics, Washington D.C., april 20-21, 1998. – (2001): “Implications of Ethnic Diversity.” Economic Policy 129-66. COLLIER, P. and HOEFFLER, A. (1998): “On economic causes of civil war.” Oxford Economic Papers 50, 563–573. – (2004): “Greed and Grievance in Civil War”. Oxford Economic Papers 56, 563-95. EASTERLY, W. and LEVINE, R. (1997): “Africa’s Growth Tragedy: Policies and Ethnic Divisions.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112, 1203-50. — 35 — ESTEBAN, J. and RAY, D. (1994): “On the Measurement of Polarization.” Econometrica 62, 819-51. – (1999): “Conflict and Distribution.” Journal of Economic Theory 87, 379-415 FEARON, J.D. and LAITIN, D.D. (2003): “Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil War.” American Political Science Review 97, 75-90. FRAENKEL, J. and GROFMAN, B. (2006): “Does the alternative vote foster moderation in ethnically divided societies? The case of Fiji.” Comparative Political Studies 39, 623-651. HAIMANKO O.; LEBRETON, M. and WEBER, S. (2005): "Transfers in a Polarized Country Bridging the Gap between Efficiency and Stability", Journal of Public Economics 89, 1277-1303 HEGRE, H.; ELLINGSON, T.; GATES, S. and GLEDITSCH, N.P. (2001): "Towards a Democratic Civil Peace? Democracy, Political Change, and Civil War, 1816-1992." American Political Science Review 95, 33-48. LA PORTA, R.; LOPEZ DE SILANES, F.; SHLEIFER, A. and VISHINY, R. (1999): “The Quality of Government.” Journal of Law Economics and Organization 15, 222-79. LEBRETON M. and S. WEBER, S. (2003): "The Art of Making Everybody Happy: How to Prevent a Secession", IMF Staff Papers 50, 403-435. MONTALVO, J.G. and REYNAL-QUEROL, M. (2005): “Ethnic Polarization, Potential Conflict, and Civil Wars.” American Economic Review 95, 796-815. REYNAL-QUEROL, M. (2000): “Ethnicity, Political Systems, and Civil Wars.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 46, 29-54. – (2005): “Does Democracy Preempt Civil Wars?.” European Journal of Political Economy 21, 445-465. SCHNEIDER, G. and WIESEHOMEIER, N. (2006): “Ethnic Polarization, Potential Conflict, and Civil Wars, Comment.” Unpublished Manuscript. — 36 — NORMAS DE PUBLICACIÓN DE PAPELES DE TRABAJO DEL INSTITUTO DE ESTUDIOS FISCALES Esta colección de Papeles de Trabajo tiene como objetivo ofrecer un vehículo de expresión a todas aquellas personas interasadas en los temas de Economía Pública. Las normas para la presentación y selección de originales son las siguientes: 1. Todos los originales que se presenten estarán sometidos a evaluación y podrán ser directamente aceptados para su publicación, aceptados sujetos a revisión, o rechazados. 2. Los trabajos deberán enviarse por duplicado a la Subdirección de Estudios Tributarios. Instituto de Estudios Fiscales. Avda. Cardenal Herrera Oria, 378. 28035 Madrid. 3. La extensión máxima de texto escrito, incluidos apéndices y referencias bibliográfícas será de 7000 palabras. 4. Los originales deberán presentarse mecanografiados a doble espacio. En la primera página deberá aparecer el título del trabajo, el nombre del autor(es) y la institución a la que pertenece, así como su dirección postal y electrónica. Además, en la primera página aparecerá también un abstract de no más de 125 palabras, los códigos JEL y las palabras clave. 5. Los epígrafes irán numerados secuencialmente siguiendo la numeración arábiga. Las notas al texto irán numeradas correlativamente y aparecerán al pie de la correspondiente página. Las fórmulas matemáticas se numerarán secuencialmente ajustadas al margen derecho de las mismas. La bibliografía aparecerá al final del trabajo, bajo la inscripción “Referencias” por orden alfabético de autores y, en cada una, ajustándose al siguiente orden: autor(es), año de publicación (distinguiendo a, b, c si hay varias correspondientes al mismo autor(es) y año), título del artículo o libro, título de la revista en cursiva, número de la revista y páginas. 6. En caso de que aparezcan tablas y gráficos, éstos podrán incorporarse directamente al texto o, alternativamente, presentarse todos juntos y debidamente numerados al final del trabajo, antes de la bibliografía. 7. En cualquier caso, se deberá adjuntar un disquete con el trabajo en formato word. Siempre que el documento presente tablas y/o gráficos, éstos deberán aparecer en ficheros independientes. Asimismo, en caso de que los gráficos procedan de tablas creadas en excel, estas deberán incorporarse en el disquete debidamente identificadas. Junto al original del Papel de Trabajo se entregará también un resumen de un máximo de dos folios que contenga las principales implicaciones de política económica que se deriven de la investigación realizada. — 37 — PUBLISHING GUIDELINES OF WORKING PAPERS AT THE INSTITUTE FOR FISCAL STUDIES This serie of Papeles de Trabajo (working papers) aims to provide those having an interest in Public Economics with a vehicle to publicize their ideas. The rules gover­ ning submission and selection of papers are the following: 1. The manuscripts submitted will all be assessed and may be directly accepted for publication, accepted with subjections for revision or rejected. 2. The papers shall be sent in duplicate to Subdirección General de Estudios Tributarios (The Deputy Direction of Tax Studies), Instituto de Estudios Fiscales (Institute for Fiscal Studies), Avenida del Cardenal Herrera Oria, nº 378, Madrid 28035. 3. The maximum length of the text including appendices and bibliography will be no more than 7000 words. 4. The originals should be double spaced. The first page of the manuscript should contain the following information: (1) the title; (2) the name and the institutional affi­ liation of the author(s); (3) an abstract of no more than 125 words; (4) JEL codes and keywords; (5) the postal and e-mail address of the corresponding author. 5. Sections will be numbered in sequence with arabic numerals. Footnotes will be numbered correlatively and will appear at the foot of the corresponding page. Mathematical formulae will be numbered on the right margin of the page in sequence. Bibliographical references will appear at the end of the paper under the heading “References” in alphabetical order of authors. Each reference will have to include in this order the following terms of references: author(s), publishing date (with an a, b or c in case there are several references to the same author(s) and year), title of the article or book, name of the journal in italics, number of the issue and pages. 6. If tables and graphs are necessary, they may be included directly in the text or alternatively presented altogether and duly numbered at the end of the paper, before the bibliography. 7. In any case, a floppy disk will be enclosed in Word format. Whenever the document provides tables and/or graphs, they must be contained in separate files. Furthermore, if graphs are drawn from tables within the Excell package, these must be included in the floppy disk and duly identified. Together with the original copy of the working paper a brief two-page summary highlighting the main policy implications derived from the research is also requested. — 38 — ÚLTIMOS PAPELES DE TRABAJO EDITADOS POR EL INSTITUTO DE ESTUDIOS FISCALES 2004 01/04 Una propuesta para la regulación de precios en el sector del agua: el caso español. Autores: M.a Ángeles García Valiñas y Manuel Antonio Muñiz Pérez. 02/04 Eficiencia en educación secundaria e inputs no controlables: sensibilidad de los resultados ante modelos alternativos. Autores: José Manuel Cordero Ferrera, Francisco Pedraja Chaparro y Javier Salinas Jiménez. 03/04 Los efectos de la política fiscal sobre el ahorro privado: evidencia para la OCDE. Autores: Montserrat Ferre Carracedo, Agustín García García y Julián Ramajo Hernández. 04/04 ¿Qué ha sucedido con la estabilidad del empleo en España? Un análisis desagregado con datos de la EPA: 1987-2003. Autores: José María Arranz y Carlos García-Serrano. 05/04 La seguridad del empleo en España: evidencia con datos de la EPA (1987-2003). Autores: José María Arranz y Carlos García-Serrano. 06/04 La ley de Wagner: un análisis sintético. Autor: Manuel Jaén García. 07/04 La vivienda y la reforma fiscal de 1998: un ejercicio de simulación. Autor: Miguel Ángel López García. 08/04 Modelo dual de IRPF y equidad: un nuevo enfoque teórico y su aplicación al caso español. Autor: Fidel Picos Sánchez. 09/04 Public expenditure dynamics in Spain: a simplified model of its determinants. Autores: Manuel Jaén García y Luis Palma Martos. 10/04 Simulación sobre los hogares españoles de la reforma del IRPF de 2003. Efectos sobre la oferta laboral, recaudación, distribución y bienestar. Autores: Juan Manuel Castañer Carrasco, Desiderio Romero Jordán y José Félix Sanz Sanz. 11/04 Financiación de las Haciendas regionales españolas y experiencia comparada. Autor: David Cantarero Prieto. 12/04 Multidimensional indices of housing deprivation with application to Spain. Autores: Luis Ayala y Carolina Navarro. 13/04 Multiple ocurrence of welfare recipiency: determinants and policy implications. Autores: Luis Ayala y Magdalena Rodríguez. 14/04 Imposición efectiva sobre las rentas laborales en la reforma del impuesto sobre la renta personal (IRPF) de 2003 en España. Autoras: María Pazos Morán y Teresa Pérez Barrasa. 15/04 Factores determinantes de la distribución personal de la renta: un estudio empírico a partir del PHOGUE. Autores: Marta Pascual y José María Sarabia. 16/04 Política familiar, imposición efectiva e incentivos al trabajo en la reforma de la imposición sobre la renta personal (IRPF) de 2003 en España. Autoras: María Pazos Morán y Teresa Pérez Barrasa. 17/04 Efectos del déficit público: evidencia empírica mediante un modelo de panel dinámico para los países de la Unión Europea. Autor: César Pérez López. — 39 — 18/04 Inequality, poverty and mobility: Choosing income or consumption as welfare indicators. Autores: Carlos Gradín, Olga Cantó y Coral del Río. 19/04 Tendencias internacionales en la financiación del gasto sanitario. Autora: Rosa María Urbanos Garrido. 20/04 El ejercicio de la capacidad normativa de las CCAA en los tributos cedidos: una primera evaluación a través de los tipos impositivos efectivos en el IRPF. Autores: José María Durán y Alejandro Esteller. 21/04 Explaining. budgetary indiscipline: evidence from spanish municipalities. Autores: Ignacio Lago-Peñas y Santiago Lago-Peñas. 22/04 Local governmets' asymmetric reactions to grants: looking for the reasons. Autor: Santiago Lago-Peñas. 23/04 Un pacto de estabilidad para el control del endeudamiento autonómico. Autor: Roberto Fernández Llera 24/04 Una medida de la calidad del producto de la atención primaria aplicable a los análisis DEA de eficiencia. Autora: Mariola Pinillos García. 25/04 Distribución de la renta, crecimiento y política fiscal. Autor: Miguel Ángel Galindo Martín. 26/04 Políticas de inspección óptimas y cumplimiento fiscal. Autores: Inés Macho Stadler y David Pérez Castrillo. 27/04 ¿Por qué ahorra la gente en planes de pensiones individuales? Autores: Félix Domínguez Barrero y Julio López-Laborda. 28/04 La reforma del Impuesto sobre Actividades Económicas: una valoración con microdatos de la ciudad de Zaragoza. Autores: Julio López-Laborda, M.ª Carmen Trueba Cortés y Anabel Zárate Marco. 29/04 Is an inequality-neutral flat tax reform really neutral? Autores: Juan Prieto-Rodríguez, Juan Gabriel Rodríguez y Rafael Salas. 30/04 El equilibrio presupuestario: las restricciones sobre el déficit. Autora: Belén Fernández Castro. 2005 01/05 Efectividad de la política de cooperación en innovación: evidencia empírica española. Autores:Joost Heijs, Liliana Herrera, Mikel Buesa, Javier Sáiz Briones y Patricia Valadez. 02/05 A probabilistic nonparametric estimator. Autores: Juan Gabriel Rodríguez y Rafael Salas. 03/05 Efectos redistributivos del sistema de pensiones de la seguridad social y factores determinantes de la elección de la edad de jubilación. Un análisis por comunidades autónomas. Autores: Alfonso Utrilla de la Hoz y Yolanda Ubago Martínez. 14/05 La relación entre los niveles de precios y los niveles de renta y productividad en los países de la zona euro: implicaciones de la convergencia real sobre los diferenciales de inflación. Autora: Ana R. Martínez Cañete. 05/05 La Reforma de la Regulación en el contexto autonómico. Autor: Jaime Vallés Giménez. — 40 — 06/05 Desigualdad y bienestar en la distribución intraterritorial de la renta, 1973-2000. Autores: Luis Ayala Cañón, Antonio Jurado Málaga y Francisco Pedraja Chaparro. 07/05 Precios inmobiliarios, renta y tipos de interés en España. Autor: Miguel Ángel López García. 08/05 Un análisis con microdatos de la normativa de control del endeudamiento local. Autores: Jaime Vallés Giménez, Pedro Pascual Arzoz y Fermín Cabasés Hita. 09/05 Macroeconomics effects of an indirect taxation reform under imperfect competition. Autor: Ramón J. Torregrosa. 10/05 Análisis de incidencia del gasto público en educación superior: nuevas aproximaciones. Autora: María Gil Izquierdo. 11/05 Feminización de la pobreza: un análisis dinámico. Autora: María Martínez Izquierdo. 12/05 Efectos del impuesto sobre las ventas minoristas de determinados hidrocarburos en la economía extremeña: un análisis mediante modelos de equilibrio general aplicado. Autores: Francisco Javier de Miguel Vélez, Manuel Alejandro Cardenete Flores y Jesús Pérez Mayo. 13/05 La tarifa lineal de Pareto en el contexto de la reforma del IRPF. Autores: Luis José Imedio Olmedo, Encarnación Macarena Parrado Gallardo y María Dolores Sarrión Gavilán. 14/05 Modelling tax decentralisation and regional growth. Autores: Ramiro Gil-Serrate y Julio López-Laborda. 15/05 Interactions inequality-polarization: characterization results. Autores: Juan Prieto-Rodríguez, Juan Gabriel Rodríguez y Rafael Salas. 16/05 Políticas de competencia impositiva y crecimiento: el caso irlandés. Autores: Santiago Díaz de Sarralde, Carlos Garcimartín y Luis Rivas. 17/05 Optimal provision of public inputs in a second-best scenario. Autores: Diego Martínez López y A. Jesús Sánchez Fuentes. 18/05 Nuevas estimaciones del pleno empleo de las regiones españolas. Autores: Javier Capó Parrilla y Francisco Gómez García. 19/05 US deficit sustainability revisited: a multiple structural change approach. Autores: Óscar Bajo-Rubio. Carmen Díaz-Roldán y Vicente Esteve. 20/05 Aproximación a los pesos de calidad de vida de los “Años de Vida Ajustados por Calidad” mediante el estado de salud autopercibido. Autores: Anna García-Altés, Jaime Pinilla y Salvador Peiró. 21/05 Redistribución y progresividad en el Impuesto sobre Sucesiones y Donaciones: una aplicación al caso de Aragón. Autor: Miguel Ángel Barberán Lahuerta. 22/05 Estimación de los rendimientos y la depreciación del capital humano para las regiones del sur de España. Autora: Inés P. Murillo. 23/05 El doble dividendo de la imposición ambiental. Una puesta al día. Autor: Miguel Enrique Rodríguez Méndez. 24/05 Testing for long-run purchasing power parity in the post bretton woods era: evidence from old and new tests. Autor: Julián Ramajo Hernández y Montserrat Ferré Cariacedo. — 41 — 25/05 Análisis de los factores determinantes de las desigualdades internacionales en las emisiones de CO2 per cápita aplicando el enfoque distributivo: una metodología de descomposición por factores de Kaya. Autores: Juan Antonio Duro Moreno y Emilio Padilla Rosa. 26/05 Planificación fiscal con el impuesto dual sobre la renta. Autores: Félix Domínguez Barrero y Julio López Laborda. 27/05 El coste recaudatorio de las reducciones por aportaciones a planes de pensiones y las deducciones por inversión en vivienda en el IRPF 2002. Autores: Carmen Marcos García, Alfredo Moreno Sáez, Teresa Pérez Barrasa y César Pérez López. 28/05 La muestra de declarantes IEF-AEAT 2002 y la simulación de reformas fiscales: descripción y aplicación práctica. Autores: Alfredo Moreno, Fidel Picos, Santiago Díaz de Sarralde, María Antiqueira y Lucía Torrejón. 2006 01/06 Capital gains taxation and progressivity. Autor: Julio López Laborda. 02/06 Pigou’s dividend versus Ramsey’s dividend in the double dividend literature. Autores: Eduardo L. Giménez y Miguel Rodríguez. 03/06 Assessing tax reforms. Critical comments and proposal: the level and distance effects. Autores: Santiago Díaz de Sarralde Míguez y Jesús Ruiz-Huerta Carbonell. 04/06 Incidencia y tipos efectivos del impuesto sobre el patrimonio e impuesto sobre sucesiones y donaciones. Autora: Laura de Pablos Escobar. 05/06 Descentralización fiscal y crecimiento económico en las regiones españolas. Autores: Patricio Pérez González y David Cantarero Prieto. 16/06 Efectos de la corrupción sobre la productividad: un estudio empírico para los países de la OCDE. Autores: Javier Salinas Jiménez y M.ª del Mar Salinas Jiménez. 07/06 Simulación de las implicaciones del equilibrio presupuestario sobre la política de inversión de las comunidades autónomas. Autores: Jaime Vallés Giménez y Anabel Zárate Marco. 18/06 The composition of public spending and the nationalization of party sistems in western Europe. Autores: Ignacio Lago-Peñas y Santiago Lago.Peñas. 09/06 Factores explicativos de la actividad reguladora de las Comunidades Autónomas (1989-2001). Autores: Julio López Laborda y Jaime Vallés Giménez. 10/06 Disciplina credititicia de las Comunidades Autónomas. Autor: Roberto Fernández Llera. 11/06 Are the tax mix and the fiscal pressure converging in the European Union?. Autor: Francisco J. Delgado Rivero. 12/06 Redistribución, inequidad vertical y horizontal en el impuesto sobre la renta de las personas físicas (1982-1998). Autora: Irene Perrote. — 42 — 13/06 Análisis económico del rendimiento en la prueba de conocimientos y destrezas imprescindibles de la Comunidad de Madrid. Autores: David Trillo del Pozo, Marta Pérez Garrido y José Marcos Crespo. 14/06 Análisis de los procesos privatizadores de empresas públicas en el ámbito internacional. Motivaciones: moda política versus necesidad económica. Autores: Almudena Guarnido Rueda, Manuel Jaén García e Ignacio Amate Fortes. 15/06 Privatización y liberalización del sector telefónico español. Autores: Almudena Guarnido Rueda, Manuel Jaén García e Ignacio Amate Fortes. 16/06 Un análisis taxonómico de las políticas para PYME en Europa: objetivos, instrumentos y empresas beneficiarias. Autor: Antonio Fonfría Mesa. 17/06 Modelo de red de cooperación en los parques tecnológicos: un estudio comparado. Autora: Beatriz González Vázquez. 18/06 Explorando la demanda de carburantes de los hogares españoles: un análisis de sensibilidad. Autores: Santiago Álvarez García, Marta Jorge García-Inés y Desiderio Romero Jordán. 19/06 Cross-country income mobility comparisons under panel attrition: the relevance of weighting schemes. Autores: Luis Ayala, Carolina Navarro y Mercedes Sastre. 20/06 Financiación Autonómica: algunos escenarios de reforma de los espacios fiscales. Autores: Ana Herrero Alcalde, Santiago Díaz de Sarralde, Javier Loscos Fernández, María Antiqueira y José Manuel Tránchez. 21/06 Child nutrition and multiple equilibria in the human capital transition function. Autores: Berta Rivera, Luis Currais y Paolo Rungo. 22/06 Actitudes de los españoles hacia la hacienda pública. Autor: José Luis Sáez Lozano. 23/06 Progresividad y redistribución a través del IRPF español: un análisis de bienestar social para el periodo 1982-1998. Autores: Jorge Onrubia Fernández, María del Carmen Rodado Ruiz, Santiago Díaz de Sarralde y César Pérez López. 24/06 Análisis descriptivo del gasto sanitario español: evolución, desglose, comparativa internacional y relación con la renta. Autor: Manuel García Goñi. 25/06 El tratamiento de las fuentes de renta en el IRPF y su influencia en la desigualdad y la redistribución. Autores: Luis Ayala Cañón, Jorge Onrubia Fernández y María del Carmen Rodado Ruiz. 26/06 La reforma del IRPF de 2007: una evaluación de sus efectos. Autores: Santiago Díaz de Sarralde Míguez, Fidel Picos Sánchez, Alfredo Moreno Sáez, Lucía Torrejón Sanz y María Antiqueira Pérez. 27/06 Proyección del cuadro macroeconómico y de las cuentas de los sectores institucionales mediante un modelo de equilibrio. Autores: Ana María Abad, Ángel Cuevas y Enrique M. Quilis. 28/06 Análisis de la propuesta del tesoro Británico “Fiscal Stabilisation and EMU” y de sus implicaciones para la política económica en la Unión Europea. Autor: Juan E. Castañeda Fernández. — 43 — 29/06 Choosing to be different (or not): personal income taxes at the subnational level in Canada and Spain. Autores: Violeta Ruiz Almendral y François Vaillancourt. 30/06 A projection model of the contributory pension expenditure of the Spanish social security system: 2004-2050. Autores: Joan Gil, Miguel Ángel Lopez-García, Jorge Onrubia, Concepció Patxot y Guadalupe Souto. 2007 11/07 Efectos macroeconómicos de las políticas fiscales en la UE. Autores: Oriol Roca Sagalés y Alfredo M. Pereira. 12/07 Deficit sustainability and inflation in EMU: an analysis from the fiscal theory of the price level. Autores: Oscar Bajo Rubio, Carmen Díaz Roldán y Vicente Esteve. 13/07 Contraste empírico del modelo monetario de tipos de cambio: cointegración y ajuste no lineal. Autor: Julián Ramajo Hernández. 14/07 An empirical analysis of capital taxation: equity vs. tax compiance. Autores: José M.ª Durán Cabré y Alejandro Esteller Moré. 15/07 Education and health in the OECD: a macroeconomic approach. Autoras: Cecilia Albert y María A. Davia. 16/07 Understanding the effect of education on health across European countries. Autoras: Cecilia Albert y María A. Davia. 17/07 Polarization, fractionalization and conflict. Autores: Joan Esteban y Debraj Ray. — 44 —