The Importance of the Highest Good in Kant's Ethics Author(s): John R. Silber Source: Ethics, Vol. 73, No. 3 (Apr., 1963), pp. 179-197 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2379698 . Accessed: 20/10/2013 19:26 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE IMPORTANCE OF THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS' JOHN R. SILBER he must have been touched obvious reason of all. As his first reason Beck notes that a commentary is "not LI. dedicatedto H. J. Paton, that so absolutely indispensable"(p. vii) for exacting master of Kantian studies, his this Critiqueas for others. The second A Commentary on Kant'sCritiqueof Prac- Critique,he suggests, "hasfew of the stytical Reason, Lewis White Beck has fit- listic difficulties and philosophical obtingly and handsomelyhonoredPaton by scurities of the other Critiques"(p. vii). so doing. Beck's Commentaryis one of The second reason for the neglect of the few genuinely important books on the Critiqueof Practical Reason lies in Kant's ethics and the best book on the "the understandable preference that subject to appearsince Paton's Categori- many readers have for the Foundations cal Imperativein 1946. It will be read of the Metaphysicsof Morals" (p. vii). thoughtfully and perennially by those After studying the Foundationsreaders who wish to master Kant's thought, and supposethat they have an understanding it cannot be ignored by anyone who of Kant's ethics and neglect the larger, wishes to avoid the risks of error and more complex work. Furthermore,Beck of belated discovery of what is already suggests that "the absenceof a commenknown. Although one may (and I think tary is a sign, in part an effect but permust) object to some of Beck's interpre- haps in part also a cause, of the neglect tations, much of the materialin this book of the Critique" (p. vii). is simply the last word on the subject. Now there is obviously one other reaWithout retracting any of the high son-and to my mind the compellingone praise just given, I wish to consider in -for the reluctance of philosophers to this discussion,first, some of the limita- write a commentary on the second Critions inherent in any commentary on tique.The second Critiquedoes not occuKant's second Critique;second, some of py the position of unique importancefor the particular strengths and weaknesses the understandingof Kant's ethics that of this one; and, third, at considerable the first Critiquehas for the understandlength the Commentary's one major fault ing of Kant's metaphysics.The best pos-the absence of a view of the wholesible commentaryon the Critiqueof Pracand a suggestionfor its correction.2 tical Reason (and Beck's may very well be it) could not possibly provide a definiI tive account of Kant's ethics either in In the Foreword to his Commentary, whole or in part. The concept of obligaBeck remarks on what seems to be the tion and the structureof imperativesare strangelack of commentarieson the Cri- most extensively discussed, not in the tique of Practical Reason. By way of ex- second Critique,but in the Foundations; planation he offers two reasons and sug- the idea of respect is expounded most gests a third while overlookingthe most effectively (according to Kant himself) ALTHOUGH AL~ with uncommondaringwhenhe 179 This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 180 ETHICS in Book I of the ReligionwithintheLimits by-line commentary. For example, his of ReasonAlone; the conceptsof freedom persistenteffortsto make sense of Kant's and will were developed gradually by charts and diagrams are generally reKant, and he did not offerany systematic warding;especiallyso is his extendeddisdiscussion of them prior to the Religion cussion of Kant's bafflingTable of Cateand the Metaphysicsof Morals.Even the gories of Freedom. And Beck nearly alone concept that receives its greatest ways succeeds in supplying the historielaboration in the second Critique-the cal information to clarify passages that concept of the good, including the high- would otherwise remain obscure. Alest good-is considered at great length though chaptersi and iv are replete with in the final third of the first Critique,in examples of Beck's historical thoroughthe third Critique,in the Metaphysicsof ness, his detective work on how the secMorals,in the Religion,in the Anthropol- ond Critique got its name is particularly ogy, and in several essays. The second impressive.Beck's Commentary is definiCritique is of such limited value as a tive in placing the Critique of Practical single source of information on Kant's Reason in the contexts of Kant's philoethics that scholars have not been so sophical developmentand his relation to much concernedto comment on it as to his critics and disciples. Beck has thus make use of it in the systematic discus- made good use of all the possibilities sion of Kant's ethical theory; they have availableto him within the genreof comquite properlyquestioned the value of a mentary, and in an Index of Passages commentary restricted to the second Cited the fruits of his labor are made Critiquealone. While Beck's Commentary readily available to the reader. is doubtlesslythe best on the subject and Were Beck's book merely a commendefinitive with regardto many points in tary on Kant's second Critique, I should the Critiqueof Practical Reason, it does insist that all of the limitations on its not provide a definitive account of the significance and usefulness to which I basic doctrinesof Kantian ethics, granted have referredapply. In fairnessto Beck, that it throws valuable light on many of however, it must be noted that a large them. Beck's Commentaryis not so im- part of his Commentaryis devoted to sysportant for Kantian studies as the com- tematic discussionof issuesin Kant's ethmentarieson the first Critiqueby Vaihin- ics. Thus, for example,he begins chapter ger, Kemp Smith, and Paton. This is not xi by saying: "Discussions of freedom because Beck has shortcomingseither as are so frequent in Kant's works that the a Kant scholar or philosopher but be- full compass of the concept and its atcause the secondCritiquecan never occu- tendant problems cannot well be surpy the position of authority for Kant's veyed in a running commentaryon pasethics that the first Critiqueoccupies for sages taken seriatim" (p. 176). There his epistemology and metaphysics. This follows an extensive discussion of the factor, I submit, is the basic reason for concepts of freedom and will in which the "neglect" of the second Critiqueby Beck makes excellent use of his vast commentators. knowledge of almost everything Kant has written or that has been written II about him. And this more or less systemIt cannot be denied, however, that atic approach is also followed in chapBeck makes a convincing case for line- ters xii through xiv in the discussion of This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS the problemof moral incentives, and the dialectic and postulates of pure practical reason. These systematically developed parts of the Commentary are, I think, the ones of greatest interest and value for those already familiarwith Kant's writings. Beck is at his philosophical and scholarlybest when he rangesover all of Kant's writings in searchof the likeliest interpretationsof his views. I do not agree, however, with all of Beck's interpretations. I think his account of the concepts of freedom and will, for example, is daring and imaginative but not sufficientlythoroughor comprehensiveto bring all of Kant's diverse sayings about these conceptsinto systematic order. Beck gives me the impression of having just come upon, rather than havingthoroughlyworkedout, some exciting new ideas on freedom and will. While Beck speaksof a "free,i.e. autonomous, Wille" which determines a "free, i.e. spontaneous, Willkiir" (pp. 198 and 202), Kant says, "Der Wille ... kann weder frei noch unfrei genannt werden. ... Nur die Willkur also kann frei ge- nannt werden."3Severalobjectionsmust be raised against Beck's interpretation. It will not do to say that Wille, which does not act, is autonomous.It is neither autonomousnor heteronomous.Wille is that aspect or function of will that supplies the law of the will itself. Wille is creative by supplying the law; choice in accordancewith that law, however, not the provision of the law, is autonomous. Hence, it is the will in action-Willkiirthat is either autonomous or heteronomous. Wille, as practical reason, is free only in the sensethat reason,as judgment and imagination,is free:it has spontaneity.4 We are on safe groundand have better textual support when we hold that Willkiir may be either autonomous or heteronomous(both being modes or free- 181 dom) depending upon whether Willkiir acts in accordancewith the law of Wille. It can be misleading, moreover, to say that Wille determines Willkiir. Willkiir is the faculty of choice and is self-determining either in accordancewith, or in opposition to, Wille; the agency of determinationis on the side of Willkiir.Admittedly this objectionmust be qualified by the fact that Wille and Willkiir are not separate entities but concepts derived by analysis of volition. Beck makes this point very well (p. 203). For some reason,however,Beck findsit noteworthy that, in discussingWilleandWillkiir,Kant "does not often succeed in keeping discussion of one of them from interrupting discussion of the other" (p. 177). But isn't this preciselywhat we shouldexpect if Willeand Willkiiraremerelyabstracted functions of a unitary volition? Beck's interpretationof Willkiiralone is very confusedif not contradictory.On the one hand, Beck insists that whether Willkiirfulfils the demandsof the law or not (a) "it is a free will" (p. 203). On the other, Beck states, "Willkiirmay or may not be free, accordingto the kind of law it puts into the maxim or the degree to which the maxim and not the momentary representationof the object determines the action" (p. 178). If Willkiir (b) "gives way to the importunities of sense," then, accordingto Beck, it is (c) "a will in name only, really being an arbitriumbrutum"(p. 203). I find justification only for quotation (a). In direct oppositionto quotations (b) and (c) Kant says: "The human will is certainly an arbitriirmsensitivum,not, however, bruturnbut liberum.For sensibility does not necessitate its action. There is in man a power of self-determination, independently of any coercion through sensuous impulses."5Paton has rightly commented: "If we look at Kant carefully, This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 182 ETHICS we shall see that human arbitriumor choiceis neverpathologicallydetermined or necessitated by sensuous motives: it is always merely affected or influenced, and this is the main reason why it is called arbitriumliberumor free choice."6 It is erroneous to suppose that Willkiir by "giving way to the importunities of sense" is transformedinto an arbitrium brutum.Free choicemust remain,according to Kant, even when the moral law is violated. The Willkiirmay giveway to the importunitiesof sense; but it is not takenaway. Willkiir,when following inclinations rather than reason, is guilty, but this would not be possible unless it were also free. The most seriousfault I find in Beck's discussionof freedomand will is his failure to considerthe concept of Gesinnung. This concept provides the basis for degrees of moral achievement and for the continuity of moral responsibilitywhereby an individual has responsibility for his many temporallydiscreetacts of volition. Without this Kant's theory of volition is totally inadequate to the facts of moral experience.Because my own interpretation of Kant's concepts of freedom and will is in print, however, I shall not extend this discussionof these points. The reader who wishes to pursue the matter further may see the sections on Wille, Willkiir, and Disposition (Gesinnung) in my essay "The Ethical Importance of Kant's Religion."7 Turning to a point of far less importance, I question whether the analogue of the CopernicanRevolution in the second Critiqueis to be found, as Beck believes, in the conceptionof law as a product of freedom (p. 179). The Copernican Revolution of the first Critiqueconsists in the recognition of the knower's contribution to the knowledge of objects. Instead of vainly striving to assure the conformityof our ideas to objects, Kant argued that we should rather concern ourselves with the necessary conditions of experienceto which objects must conform if they are to be known. In the second Critiquethe CopernicanRevolution consists in the discovery that the object of moral volition-the good-is determined by the will of the moral agent and that the good does not determinethe will of the moral agent. To be sure, it is by referenceto the moral law that the will freely determinesthe object of volition. But the point of the CopernicanRevolution when applied to moral philosophyis that the moral object, the good, must conformto the conditionsof moral volition just as the theoretical object must conform to the conditions of knowing. Beck is surely to be congratulatedon chaptersviii and x, in which he organizes and comments upon large segments of the second Critiquein terms of "a metaphysical deductionof the morallaw" followed by a "transcendentaldeductionof pure practical reason." In two of the most illuminating chapters in the Commentary Beck contributes substantially and with great originality to our understanding of the various methods Kant employedin the argumentsof the second Critique. Although generally sympathetic to Kant's position, Beck wears no man's collar, and on several occasions subjects Kant's views to withering criticism. His demonstration of the arbitrary way in which Kant sometimeslabeledand thereby libeled other philosophers is both amusing and devastating (p. 104). For the most part I find myself in agreementwith Beck's criticismsof Kant. But his discussion and criticism of the concept of the highest good seem to be This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS fundamentally in error. Whereas Beck usually makes a sustained effort to determinewhat Kant is trying to say before criticizinghis views, he seems impatient and dogmatic in his insistence that the concept of the highest good "is not important in Kant's philosophy for any practical consequencesit might have, for it has none except those drawn from the concept of bonumsupremum"(p. 245). Apparently, Beck believes that the concept of the highest good adds nothing to the concept of moral perfection. "What am I to do?" he asks, when "I do all in my power ... to promote the highest good" (p. 244). And he answers, I "simply act out of respect for the law, which I already knew. I can do absolutely nothing toward apportioning happiness in accordancewith desert" (pp. 244-45). In one sense, of course,action to promote the highest good does not go beyond the requirementsof the law for it is a requirement of the law. But in another sense it does go beyond the law which, as mere form of volition, says nothing about what specificallyis to be done in a concrete situation. And it is obvious, Beck's denial notwithstanding, that in rearing children, serving on juries, and gradingpapersone tries to do and actually can do something"aboutapportioning happiness in accordance with desert." (It is the obviousness of this point that bothers me; Beck must have taken this point into consideration, though I do not see how.) I shall not attempt a full rebuttal of Beck's position on the concept of the highest good here; rather I propose to demonstratehis mistake by showingconstructively in Section III the way in which the concept of the highest good, while followingfrom the morallaw, adds content to the abstract form of the cate- 183 gorical imperativeand gives directionto moralvolition. If this much canbe shown, the importanceof the concept to Kant's ethics will also have been shown. III Kant insisted that a careful delineation of the parts or details of a theory is only the first step in a responsible inquiry. "But still another thing must be attended to," he added, "which is of a more philosophical and architectonic character. It is to grasp correctly the idea of the whole, and then to see all those parts in their reciprocalinterrelations, in the light of their derivationfrom the concept of the whole."8The idea of the whole of the second Critiquein terms of which we might see the interrelation of all the parts is the one thing that Beck's Commentarydoes not provide. This lack is its only seriousfault and calls for a sustained attempt at correction. Unless I am mistaken, Kant's doctrine of the good (of which the concept of the highest good is the central part) is that which binds together the various parts of the second Critique.I suspect that it was Beck's failure to consider Kant's doctrine of the good systematically that prevented him from seeing its importance as the unifying theme of the second Critiqueand distorted his interpretation of the concept of the highest good. A. The centralityof thegoodin the Critique of Practical Reason.-It is easy to overlookthe centrality of the doctrineof the good in the second Critique. Like Schopenhauer,we may be so greatly influenced by the Foundationswith its focus directed almost exclusively on the purely formal aspects of ethics that the startling shift of emphasisand organization in the second Critique is scarcely noticed.9 Or like Beck, we may be to This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 184 ETHICS some extent preoccupiedwith the formal schemes of organization, the section titles, and the rubrics of the second Critique.If we look beyond the titles to examine what Kant has actually written about in the secondCritique,the centrality of the theory of the good becomes apparent. Kant opens the second Critiquewith his proof that the experienceof obligation cannot be accountedfor nor the distinction between virtue and happiness maintained unless the concept of the good is derivedfromthe morallaw rather than the reverse.10The theoremsof pure practical reason present Kant's conclusions on this basic issue. In chapter ii, "The Concept of an Object of Pure Practical Reason," Kant developsthe implicationsof his first chapter. Realizingthat every act of will must have an object and denying that ethics can be grounded on any object defined prior to the law as an object of the will, Kant is compelledto determinean object for the will by means of the law itself. That is why he is concernedin this chapter with the nature of the good as the object of pure practical reason. Knowing also that the object of pure practical reason fails to meet the need of the will for a materialobject in the act of volition as long as it lacks sensibleinterpretation, Kant offersan interpretationof it in terms of the sensible world. In the section of chapterii entitled "Ofthe Typic of Pure Practical Judgment," Kant attempts to show that the concepts of good and evil can determine definite sensible objects for the will-objects involving happiness in proportionto virtue. They can do this, however,only after they themselveshave been determinedby reasonas the a priori objects of the will. Kant hopes in this way to have succeeded in providing a genuine material object (the good) for the act of volition without having defined it prior to the concept of law. Chapter iii concernsthe incentives of the will and attempts to prove that the good, as the object of the will, does not determinethe will to action by virtue of its material but by virtue of its form. The will, it is argued, is still self-determined, and it is obligated to seek any particularobject in question only by referenceto the law whichlegislatesin terms of specific content provided by sensibility. Any pleasure that the will feels in regard to an object to which it is obligated is found, therefore,to follow as the effect of the law and not to precede the law as the cause of its influence.Chapter iii, thus, exhibitsthe consistencyand mutual support of the views presented in chapters i and ii. In Book II of Part I, entitled "The Dialectic of Pure Practical Reason," Kant faces the problem of unifying the elements of virtue and happinessin the concept of the highest good. Having ruled out the good as the materialobject of the will definedpriorto the law, Kant, nonetheless, must restore this object of volition subsequent to the establishment of the law. Since the will must have an object,1"failure to re-establishthe good in this fashionwould leave the will without directionsin the performanceof its duty. The law by itself defines the moral good as virtue; sensibility, for its part, provides happiness as the natural good.12 But the law, in need of the material of sensibility, cannot avail itself of the material of the natural good apart from the re-establishmentof the unity of the good. In this unity the sensible material of happiness must be caught up in the formalityof the law without the sacrifice of the purity of the law. In orderto offer a unitary, though material, interpretation of the object of pure practical rea- This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS son, Kant introducesthe concept of the highest good. In so doing, Kant is confronted by an apparent antinomy that threatens the possibility of the concept of the highest good. Since happinessand virtue are heterogeneousconcepts, they cannot be united analytically in the concept of the highest good. Hence, they must be united synthetically. Now since the highest good is the practical object of the will-an object that the will must produce through its actions-the unity of happinessandvirtue in the highestgood must be causally derived. Either happiness must be the cause of virtue or virtue the cause of happiness. Either alternative, however, seems impossible:the former because happinesscannot cause virtue, and the latter because the effects of willing dependnot only on the intention of the will but also upon the support of the natural world. Kant resolves this antinomy by showing that the latter alternative is not really impossible but, rather, is capable merely of partial, contingent fulfilmentapart fromsupplementary mediation by God. The postulates of pure practical reason are offered to insure the possibility of the latter alternative and, thereby, the possibility of the concept of the highest good. In Part II of the second Critiquethe methodology of pure practical reason is discussed. In this context the incentives of pure practical reason are once again examined.This time, however, they are discussed from the standpoint of their effective employment in moral edification, that is, in the production of good actions, rather than (as in chap. iii of Part I, Book I) from the standpoint of the theoretical difficulties involved in their very existence. There can be no question, then, of the overwhelmingimportanceof the good in the Critiqueof PracticalReason.The dis- 185 cussion of the good in its various aspects as the object of pure practical reason providesthe unifying theme for the work as a whole. Comparativelyspeaking,concepts of duty and the categoricalimperative assume minor roles in the discussion although they are fundamental components of the total theory of the good as it is presented. By presenting an extensive discussion of the good in the second Critique,Kant relates himself unequivocallyto the classical traditionin ethics. His theory of the good shows clearly both his conformity to, and his departurefrom,the traditional points of view. He reversedtraditional procedureby establishingfirst the moral law and then deriving the good from it. This initial opposition to traditional thought led to yet another-the assertion of the heterogeneity of the good."3This duality of the good confrontedKant with a grave problem: that of providing for the unity of these components. Fortunately, in addition to this problem,there was the problemof determiningthe good as the materialobject of the will by reference to the demand of the moral law. Searchingfor the solutionto both of these problems at once made Kant's problem easier, and he found his solution in the concept of the highest good as the synthesis of the dual aspects of the good. Kant thereby reaffirmedthe importance of this traditional concept to ethical thought by making, albeit in a new and different manner, the concept of the highest good the object of the will. But the mere existence of the concept of the highest good as the object of the will is not impressiveuntil it can be given sufficientcontent to guide moralvolition. In the next three subsections I shall trace systematicallyKant's development of this concept toward this end. B. Perfection(themoralgood)as a corn- This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 186 ETHICS ponentof thehighestgood.-In full accord with ethical tradition, Kant repeatedly insisted that every volition must have an object.'4He argued, further, that if the categoricalimperativeis to have meaning the will must be bound with necessity to an object that is definedby practicalreason, that is, by reference to the moral law. If some object of sensibility (however refined)were acceptedby the will as the good and made into the object of volition, the will would not stand under a categorical obligation. Its relation to any particular object would be conditioned in two ways: first, by the success or failureof the act to achieve the object held to be good, and second, by the relation of the will to the object, which would be throughdesireand,hence,eitherwould be contingent upon the continuation of the feeling binding the object and the will together or would be determinedby natural causation. Since in categorical obligation, however, there must be an unconditionalrelation of the free will to the object, the object to which the will is obligated must be of unconditioned worth. But the only unconditionalobject that can be relatednecessarilyto the will without conditioning the will and destroying its freedom is the good will itself."5The good will, therefore, is itself the object of the will, and in its act of volition it wills nothing moreor less than its own perfection(freewilling) as an end which is also a duty.'6 Kant believesthat in this way material is added to the law, and an object is determinedby purepracticalreason.The law not only insists that for every act of volition there must be an object, thereby stating a formaldemandfor a material component in ethics; the law now also projects a materialobject for itself in the form of the embodimentof the law in a good will. The will, at the behest of the moral law, projects for itself the good as an end which is also a duty. And this end toward which the will must strive is its own moral perfection. The will, that is, must seek to attain virtue. Thus far I am in complete agreement, I believe, with Beck. He acknowledgesthe significance of this much of the concept of the highest good, that is, the supremegood. This conception of the object of pure practical reason is, however, not an object for volition with material content. We know now that the will must seek to attain its own perfection, its virtue. But what does this mean in terms of the actual intention of the will? The intention of the will can be understood in merely formalterms, as when one speaks of a person's having a good moral disposition, for here we are concernedmerely with the intention to follow the law. Furthermore,this moral dispositionis of pre-eminent importance in the assessment of a person's character.Nevertheless, in an act of volition one does not simply will a good disposition. Rather one expressesa good dispositionby willing something more concrete. If, in consequence, the moral law is to be of any use to a person in supplying the good as the materialobject of volition, it must be more instructive than thus far it has been shown to be. Kant himself is well awareof the need to say more. He is quite ruthless in his denunciationof the rationalisticethics of He thinks their Wolff and Baumgarten."7 first ethical principle, "Fac Bonum et OmitteMalum,"to be classicin its ineptitude. In regard to this principle Kant says, The meaning of the proposition is simply, "it is good that you should do what is good," which is tautological. It tells us nothing about what is good, but merely that we ought to do what we ought to do."8 This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS 187 Then raisinghis sights to includethe field develop his reason and understanding, of ethics in general, he adds, and thereby to free himself from the rudenesses of the state of nature. Still There is no branch of knowledge which so abounds in tautological propositions as ethics, we must rememberthat Kant says that offeringas the answer what was in fact the ques- one is to do all these things so that he tion."9 shall be worthy of the humanity within All these activities are carried out him. practice so folly of this Kant felt the to virtue. He must develop his as means strongly that he says of some of his colfaculties to the point that he can live a leagues: moral life. He is categorically obligated . . . teachers are prone to believe that they have to raise himself out of the rudenessof nadone everything required of them when their explanations and indications to their pupils are ture and animality,to becomeinstructed, as if a medical man told a patient sufferingfrom and to develop his humanity wherebyhe constipation that he ought to loosen his bowels sets ends for himself, because these atand to perspire freely and digest his food well. arethe conditionsof his attainThis is just telling him to do what he wants to tainments ment of moral perfection. know how to do. Such propositions are tautological rules of decision.20 Kant is obviouslyunwilling,therefore,to leave the definitionof good as the object of volition in this indefinitestate. Can anything more definite be said about the object towardwhich the moral person must strive when he seeks his moralperfection?Kant suggests: "It can be nothing else than the cultivation of one's own power (or natural capacity) and also of one's will (moraldisposition) to satisfy the requirementof duty in general.'"2'The last part of this explanation merely repeats that the object of the will is its own moral perfection; it is, therefore, of no help in addingmaterialsignificance to the object of pure practical reason. The first part, however, seems more promising. Kant suggests that, in the cultivation of his powers,man has a duty to educate and refinehimself to the fullest extent possible. Reason commands him to fulfil the potentialities of his rational nature so that he shall be worthy of the humanity that is within him.22At this point genuinematerialcontentseems to be added to the object of volition. In the processof willing his own perfection, the person now wills to educate himself, Moral goodness thus lies in the perfection, not of the faculties, but of the will. But the functional completeness of all our powers is required in order that the dictates of the will should be made operative. Perfection (of the faculties) therefore, appertains to morality indirectly.23 But if this natural perfection of our pow- ers is of value merely as a means to the attainment of moral perfection by providing us with the conditions for living morallives, then it cannot provide a material object of volition. A person educates himself and develops his humanity so that the conditionsfor the exerciseof his will are met. Once these conditions are met, however,what then does he will when he wills in a mannerbefitting a man with a good moral disposition? What does he will when he seeks moral perfection? An object of moral volition with material content has not yet been given. PerhapsKant does not regardthe perfection of one's faculties of mind and body simply as a means to moral perfection. Perhapshe intends to argue,rather, that one is obligatedto fulfilone's capacities because they are natural ends whose fulfilmentis good in itself. We find Kant saying occasionally that the cultivation This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 188 ETHICS of the powers of mind, soul, and body is the end or goal of human existence.24If this is Kant's view, then he is clearly in possession of an object of volition with material content. Under this new interpretation, one no longer wills the perfection of his natural faculties merely as a means of the exercise of moral volition. Having attained to the conditionsof moral volition already, one fulfils his duty and attains moral perfection in part by striving to fulfil his natural capacities.It may thus be thoughtthat Kant (following Aristotle,Wolff,Baumgarten,andothers) attributes goodness to the perfection of capacities simply because the perfection of these ends is good in itself. This interpretation,however,does not bear up under scutiny; it overlooks the fact that, for Kant, the good is always relatedto desire.The naturalgood is that which satisfies the desires of individuals. The moral good is that which satisfies everyone.25Kant insists that "what we call good [morallygood] must be, in the judgement of every reasonableman, an object of the faculty of desire, and the evil must be, in everyone's eyes, an object of aversion.""In the third Critique, Kant again insists that goodness,whether natural or moral, involves a reference to the faculty of desire and a concern for the real existence of the object that is regardedas good.27If the object itself arouses the faculty of desire, then it is naturally good. If, however, the object of desire is definedby the moral law and presented to the faculty of desire as the object it ought necessarilyto desire,then the object is morallygood. But unless an object is related to the faculty of desire in one way or the other it cannot be good in either sense. Kant notes no third way by which an object can be related to the faculty of desire. The perfectionof capa- bilities, therefore, cannot be regardedas good unlessit is either naturallygood, by being essential to the fulfilmentof sensible needs and inclinations, or morally good, by being demandedby the moral law. It cannot be regardedas a third kind of intrinsicgoodness;for unlessthe moral law demands it, or sensible desire delights in it, the perfection of natural capacities does not stand in relation to the faculty of desire at all. And apart from some relation to the faculty of desire an object cannot be good. Kant cannot be interpreted to say, however, that if one has no desire to develop his capacity to read and if reading is not essential to the moral life, then learningto read is not good. Though perhaps not immediately desirable, reading may be an essential means to the fulfilment of something else which is desired. Consequently, the cultivation of one's capacity to read may be naturally good in accordancewith a maxim of prudence under the idea of happiness as the total well-being of the individual.28But the point is this: if the perfection of natural capacitiesis to be good in any sense, this perfection must be desired either indirectly or directly, or it must be a necessary object of the faculty of desire demanded by the moral law.29 Apart frommoralperfection,which we have already discussed, perfection is related to man as a natural good and, hence, as the object of desire according to maximsof happiness.And most of the talents and skills of which man is capable are good, if at all, only as natural goods. Kant's position on this subject is well summarizedin his refutation of Baumgarten's view that the perfection of all the natural ends of man is to be included in the list of duties that we have toward ourselves.Kant says of Baumgartenand his theory: This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS He includes in his list all human perfections, even those which relate to our talents. He speaks of the perfection of all the powers of the soul. On this argument logic and all the sciences which go to perfect the understanding and satisfy our thirst for knowledge would need to be included; but there is nothing moral in these. Morality does not tell us what we ought to do in order to become perfect in the skilled use of our powers; any such precepts are merely pragmatic, they are rules of prudence for amplifying our powers because this conduces to our welfare.30 Kant thus insists that unless our powers and their cultivation are essential to the fulfilmentof the morallaw, they are good only as they contributeto the happiness of man. Nor can such perfections acquire a distinct quality of goodness by being groundedon the command of God. Unless a command of God is itself derived from the moral law, it is not binding on the will except by means of threats and promises that concern the will's happiness. Consequently,the perfectionof talents which God might command would be demandedeither upon moralgrounds, and thereforebe morally good, or upon groundsof sensiblewell-being,and hence be naturally good.3"Again we see that perfectiondoes not consitute a third kind of goodness. Once it is noted, however, that perfection is good only as a natural or as a moral good, we see that it does not offer us a sufficiently determinate object for moral volition. As a moral good, perfection providesonly preliminaryobjects of volition in terms of which the will attains to the conditionsof significantmoral existence. (For example, moral perfection directs the will to pay attention to the first signs of an emergingconscience,and to its nurture.)Once these conditionsare met, however,moral perfection ceases to be an instructive object of volition. As 189 a natural good, moreover, perfection is groundedonly upon prudential maxims; consequently, it can never be presented as a necessary object of volition. Kant has rightly said that there is nothing moral in this notion of perfection. It seems, therefore, that bonumsupremum (virtue) cannot function as a sufficiently determinate object of moral volition or provide material content for it. Before leaving this question we must note, however, that Kant does not always hold to the position that the perfection of natural capacities cannot provide a necessaryyet concretely determinate object of volition. Unfortunately, Kant occasionally does make this claim at the expense of the consistency of his theory of the good. In the Metaphysics of Morals,while addressinghimselfto the duties of a person toward himself, Kant says that the cultivation of the natural powers of mind, soul, and body-as means to all sorts of possible ends-is a duty of man to himself. He must not permit his talents to rust and atrophy throughneglect, nor shouldhe be content to leave his natural capacities undeveloped beyond their condition at birth. This duty, accordingto Kant, is not based on consideration of any advantage which the cultivation of his faculties (for all sorts of purposes) can procure for him. For this cultivation might be advantageously dispensed with in favor of the crudity of natural necessity (according to Rousseauian principles). Rather, it is a command of moral-practical reason and a duty of man toward himself to cultivate his faculties (of which one may be developed more than another according to the variety of his ends) and, from the practical standpoint, to be a man fitted to the end of his existence.32 In this passage Kant does not urge on man the cultivation of these powers as a naturalgood. He admitswith Rousseau that man might be better off in the rawness of the state of nature. On the other This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 190 ETHICS hand, we have noted that Kant does not arguethat the perfectionof all these powers of mind, soul, and body is essential to moralvolition. These are powers that, when attained, are of use to man for a variety of purposes.While some of them may be of help in living a morallife, not many of these powers nor a very great refinementof them can be required for purposes of morality, because the moral life can be lived by commen men who lack such refinements.Kant seems to be arguing, therefore, that, apart from the service of these powers to man's wellbeing and/or to his moral development, their developmentis good and is morally obligatory. As Kant puts it in this context, "as a rationalbeing he [man]necessarily wills that all his powers should be developed."33 Kant thus put himself in the position of advocating precisely the same view of perfectionwhich he refuted when it was advancedby Baumgarten.The very same theory of perfection was rejected again by Kant in the second Critiqueon the grounds that it was based upon the determinationof a material object of volition prior to the moral law and consequently was incapable of relating itself to the will as a duty.84Nevertheless, in the passages cited in the precedingparagraph,Kant not only introducedthis material concept of perfection into his theory ad hoc; moreover, by insisting that the attainment of such perfection is a duty, he contradictedthe central thesis of the Analytic of the second Critiquein addition to many explicit statements on the subject. Since I am not interested in making capital of such a contradictionbut hope, rather, to suggest the systematic unity of Kant's doctrine of the good, I dismiss the few isolated passages in which Kant introduces perfection of capacities as a third sort of good (that is, as a material object defined prior to the law that is nonethelessbinding upon the will) as unintentional lapses back into the rationalistic ethics of Wolff and Baumgarten.35 Hence, in terms of the presentation of Kant's systematic theory, we remain at the point arrived at in the discussion of the moralconcept of perfection.The only object so far determined for the will is that of moralperfection. Under the idea of moralperfection,as an end which is also a duty, a personis obligatedto perfect only those powers of mind and body that are essential to the exerciseof moral volition. C. Happiness (the natural good) as a componentof the highest good.-At this point Kant has gone as far as he can from the side of the law alone in the determination of a materialobject of volition.36He now confrontsan ethical paradoxat least as serious as those which confrontedthe Stoics and Epicureans and Socratesnamely, the paradoxof willing the willing of nothing. Every action must have an object or end. That end prescribed by the moral law is the moral good, which is the good will itself. Thus the will is obligated to will willing itself (that is, moral perfection) as its end. But if the will is to be good, it must will something in the act of volition. While the moral law prescribes the conditions of willing and sets these conditions before the will as its object, these conditions cannot be fulfilleduntil the will itself embodiesthese conditionsas the form in an actual, concrete volition whose material (while subject to the law) must be acquiredthrough sensibility, that is, throughthe faculty of desire. If, therefore, the law is not extended to the condition of man, then the law cannot provide a material object of volition, and Kant cannot escape the paradoxof willing the willing of nothing. This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD iN KANT'S ETHICS Kant's theory is well prepared, of course,for the extension of reasonto the conditionsof man since it has its foundation in the human situation. Kant builds his ethics on the foundation of the experience of obligation, which is the experience, not of a pure rational being, but of man, a rational-sensible being. This is the experienceof the heterogeneity of the good in which both the natural good as the fulfilment of man's sensible nature and the moral good as the fulfilment of man's rational nature are presupposed. Having recognizedthe fact of man's sensibility from the outset-not only as an essential part of his nature but also as a condition of the experience of obligation3-Kant, in keeping with the foundationsof his theory, can extend reason beyond the considerationof man as a merely rational being to the limits of man as both rational and sensible. Kant doesnot stop, therefore,with perfection as the sole end which is also a duty. He insists rather that one is likewise obligated to seek the happiness of others as a second end which is also a duty.38Men have happinessas their natural good, and happiness is defined as that satisfaction taken in the fulfilment of needs and inclinations.Kant observes: "To be happy is necessarilythe desireof every rational but finite being, and thus it is an unavoidable determinant of its faculty of desire."39Now as it is applied in a specific volition, the moral law can only prescribethe form of its own universality to which material, supplied by the faculty of desire, must be added. Since we are finite rationalbeings, we all have happiness as the object of desire; hence, we can introduce our own happiness as material content for our volition if one condition is met-namely, if we have included within the content and structureof our volition the happinessof 191 others. We are morally obligated to seek the happiness of others because we, in addition to being finite, sensible beings, who naturally and invariably seek our own happiness, are also rational beings, who are constrainedto act accordingto the universal demand of the moral law, which constrains our will to pursue the happinessof others as the priorcondition of the moral right to pursue our own. Kant reasonsas follows: The law that we should further the happiness of others arises not from the presupposition that this law is an object of everyone's choice but from the fact that the form of universality, which reason requires as condition for giving to the maxim of self-love [personal happiness] the objectivity of law, is itself the determining ground of the will.40 The reason why I ought to promote the happiness of others is not because the realization of their happiness is of consequence to myself (whether on account of immediate inclination or on account of some satisfaction gained indirectly through reason), but solely because a maxim which excludes this cannot also be present in one and the same volition as a universal law.4' As finite, rational,yet sensiblebeings,we naturally and necessarily desire to seek our own happiness;yet this is never possible in accordancewith law unless it is on the condition of our seeking the happiness of others. We do not necessarily care for others. As far as our own desires are concerned, we may have contempt for the welfare of others. But we can never will an object accordingto a universal maxim unless, in the determination of that maxim, considerationis given to the fulfilment of the happiness of others. Now a material object of volition that can inform and direct the will in the act of volition is supplied. And yet, remarkably, this material stands under the determinationof law becauseit is a demand of the law and not of inclinationthat one This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 192 ETHICS must seek the happiness of others. It is only the law with its demand of universality that insists one is wrong to desire others to further his interests (which is a desireof all men) unless he at the same time furthers their interests. Unless a person also wills the interests of others he has no right,no justificationunderthe law, for having others will his. But if a man has no respect for the law and chooses to disregard its demand, he is certainly able and even inclined to have others seek his interest while he totally disregardstheirs. He may find it is prudent to hand out a favor here and a favor there in order to get what he wants. In this case, however, he is bargainingand gives only in order to receive something in return. But when he considers his needs and wants as a sensiblebeing under the jurisdictionof the law of his rational nature, he must forego his desires either to exploit others, or to trade advantageouslywith them,or to ignoretheirneeds altogether. For he cannot rationally will the attainment of the natural good for himself except underthe conditionof his worthinessto do so-except, that is, under the conditionthat he will the attainment of the natural good universallyaccordingto the demand of the law. Thus he must seek the happiness of others as a condition of his worthinessto seek his own happiness which he in fact desires to seek. Hence we see that it is not his concernfor happiness that leads him to considerthe happiness of others.On the contrary,his concernfor virtue,thatis, for the worthinessto be happy, motivateshim to do so. He pursueshis own moralperfection by pursuingthe happinessof others. In admitting the content of sensibility into the maxim of the will, the law does not resign its claim to determinethe object of the will. It continues to impose its form upon the materialof the faculty of desire. As a consequencethe material object of volition, in spite of its sensible content, is not defined prior to the law, but is defined by the law itself. Apart from the law, any materialof the faculty of desire is merely a desired end. Only after the imposition of the form of universality upon the content of desire does that content (now drastically altered) become the good as the material object of moral volition. D. The unity of perfectionand happiness in the highestgood.-In presenting our own perfectionand the happinessof others as distinct ends which are also duties, Kant clearly approacheshis goal of the determination of the object of volition by reference to the law. The goal is not reached,however,until he can show the unity of these two ends in a single object that is a duty. There are many questionsregardingthe relation of these ends to one another that are left unansweredby the statement that one gives expressionto his moral perfection by seeking the happiness of others. This need not be the only way or even a completely satisfactoryway of attaining virtue. For example, since a person recognizes that his own worthinessto be happy depends upon his seeking the happiness of others, he must wonder whether his duty to pursue the happiness of others is not to some extent conditionedby their worthinessto receive it. Thus the will is left in great confusion apart from the definition of an object that can in some way unify these two morally necessary ends. But in reassertingthis need for a unifiedend or object of volition, we must keep clearly in mind that we are not discussinga need of the law. The moral law does not have its foundationin some object, nor is it incomplete as the law of moralityif it fails to determinean object. The concernfor the determinationof an This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS object stems from a human need.42It is the need of the humanwill for an object in the act of volition that forces Kant to this considerationof ends and to the extention of the law beyond its own limits alone to the condition of man. Once this extension is made, however, we see that these ends of perfection and happinessof othersare not to be regarded as separate and distinct objects of volition. Rather they are united in the duty "to try to effect with all one's power the highest good possiblein the world (which in the totality of the worldjoins together with purest morality, universal happiness accordingto morality)."43 This obligation-to "makethe highest good possible in the worldyour own final end"44Kant notes, is a synthetic proposition a priori which is introduced by the moral law. This extension is possible because of the moral law's being taken in relation to the natural characteristics of man, that for all his actions he must conceive an end over and above the law (a characteristic which makes man an object of experience).45 193 or "complete" or "perfect" (consummcatun) [vollendete].The supreme good "is the unconditionalcondition,i.e. the condition which is subordinateto no other (originarium),"48 while the complete or perfect good is "that whole which is no part of a yet larger whole of the same kind (perfectissimum). It is indeedtrue that "virtue (as the worthiness to be happy) is the supremeconditionof whatever appears to us to be desirable and thus of all our pursuit of happiness and consequentlythat it is the supremegood [das oberste Gut]."50Nevertheless, Kant denies that virtue, as the supremegood, is the entire and perfect good [das ganzeund vollendeteGut]as the object of the faculty of desireof rationalfinite beings. In orderto be this, happinessis also required,and indeednot in the partialeyes of a personwho makeshimself his end but even in the judgmentof an impartialreason,whichin generalregardspersons in the worldas ends-in-themselves.5' It is clear from this that the moral good, virtue, is by no means the highest good. It is rather the supremecondition of the highest good, and, therefore, Kant says "it is the supremegood [dasobersteGut]."52 But happiness,as the naturalgood, must be added to virtue in orderto realize the highest good. For, Kant insists: Because of man's sensible as well as rational nature, his obligationmust be presented in terms of action in the sensible world and not merely in terms of the form of the action itself, as mere autonomy or virtue. The concept of the highest the highest good [das hIchsteGut]means the good enunciates a unity of the heteroge- whole [dasGanze],the perfectgood [dasvollenneous components of virtue and happi- deteGut]whereinvirtue is always the supreme ness by means of an extension of the law good[dasobersteGut],beingthe conditionhaving of man's rationalnature to the needs and no conditionsuperiorto it." desires of his sensible nature. It enunThe highest good, is, therefore, the ciates, therefore, a unity of the moral synthesis of the moral good and the natgood and the natural good. ural good. And since the moral good is The concept of the highest good, ac- the supreme condition of this unity, we cording to Kant, "is a synthesisof con- find that in the fulfilment of the highest cepts,"46and it must never be confused good happinessmust be present in exact with the "supreme good."47When the proportion to morality. "Inasmuch as term "highest" [h1chste]is used in the virtue and happinesstogether constitute phrase "the highest good," it can mean the possessionof the highest good for one either "supreme" (supremum) [oberste] person,"54as we saw in section B, "and This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 194 ETHICS happinessin exact proportionto morality (as the worth of a personand his worthiness to be happy) constitutes that [the highest good] of a possible world."55An individualrecognizesa defect in his moral goodness by his transgressionof the law, and a defect in his natural goodness by unrequited needs and desires. But a person recognizesa defect in the highest good for him in two different wayseither by his failure to attain virtue, which is the supreme condition of his highest good as his worthinessto be happy, or by the existenceof a disproportion between his virtue and happiness. The highest good of the individual is never attained so long as he is deficient in virtue. Nevertheless, taking the degree of his moralattainment for what it is, there is also a violation of his highest good if he is not happy in exact proportion to the degree of his actual virtuous attainment. Under this second criterion for judgingthe highest good for an individual, the highest good can be lacking either because of an excess or a deficiency of happiness in relation to the virtuous attainment of the person in question. Oncethe highest good is recognizedby an individualas his obligation, he recognizes that an integral part of his attainment of virtue consists in his striving after the attainment of a proportionbetween his happinessand his virtue. Thus, if he recognizesthat he is not worthy of the happinesshe enjoys, he may find that he is morally obligated, in terms of the supreme good, to renounce this happiness. The criminalwho turns himself in can be seen to pursue both the moral good and the highest good for he establishes that proportionbetween his virtue and his happinesswhich is demandedby the highest good and by the moral good, as its supreme condition. In the act of turninghimself in, the criminalincreases his worthinessto be happy in the future, albeit perhaps insufficiently to permit a suspended sentence. Another man, of course, may lack happiness commensurate with his virtue. Such a man, in striving to attain the highest good, has an indirect duty to increase his own happiness.56 It is not morally possible, of course, for this man, in the name of his duty to promotethe highest good, to compromise his virtue in order to increasehis happiness or in orderto make it commensurate with his virtue. Because the attainment of virtue is the supremecondition of the highest good, to compromiseone's virtue -regardless of the disparityof happiness to virtue-involves acting contrary to one's duty to promote the highest good. By the slightest compromiseof his virtue, the erstwhilevirtuousman may find himself no happier than before; but he will certainlyfind himselfless than worthy of whatever happiness he does have. The virtuous but unhappy man must simply recognize that the moral law does not promise happiness but only the worthiness of it. Since he has acquired a right to happiness,he must recognizethat the unhappiness in his life is an affront to reason.As a rationalbeing he must strive to remedy it. Failing this, the virtuous man may have a rational faith that this affront will be remediedby God. But as a virtuous man in pursuit of the attainment of the highest good, he must be prepared to endure steadfastly in his virtue without benefit of the happiness which he deserves.57 These observations pertain merely to the idea of the highestgood for individual persons. When we generalize this basic conception of the relation of virtue to happinessto include the totality of finite rational beings, we attain to the idea of the highest good possible in the world, This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS an idea in terms of which the happiness of all finite rational beings is sought under the sole limitation of their worthiness to be happy. Thus under the idea of the highest good, one is not merelyconcerned to achieve virtue and to seek happiness proportionateto virtue in his own life; he is obligated in addition to strive for the realizationof happinessin proportion to virtue in the lives of all men. Furthermore, he is to strive for this goal with the realizationthat it is likewisethe obligatory goal of all men's efforts. Although this task is God-likein dimension,it does not totally transcend the powers of citizens and legislators. There are many tantalizing questions concerningthe nature of the highest good and its function in Kant's ethics that cannot be resolved or even consideredin a discussion of this scope. Nevertheless, a few conclusionsof importance for the interpretationof Kant's second Critique and his system of ethics can be drawn. First, the concept of the highest good is of central importance in Kant's ethics. Kant recognizedthat the concept of the good-as a material, determinateobject of volition-is necessaryin order to give concrete direction to moral volition. He likewise recognized that the good must be determined by the moral law if it is to be categoricallyobligatoryon the will. Therefore,he soughtto provide,by means of the applicationof the morallaw to the condition of man, material content for the good as this necessaryobject. Second, in attempting to provide material content for the good, Kant showedthat mor- 195 al perfection is an end which is also a duty. Moral perfection, however, does not provide a sufficiently determinate content for the good. Therefore, and third, Kant demonstratedthat the happiness of others is an end which is also a duty. Fourth, in recognitionof the difficulty of determining the relation of these two ends as duties, Kant proposed to unify perfectionand happinessin one material object determinedformally by the moral law as applied to the material of human desire.The unitary, necessary, material object of volition thus determined is the highest good. Kant's second Critique and technical theory must be interpretedin light of these four conclusions if they are to be correctly understood. Much more remains to be said about the concept of the highest good, and many of the criticisms raised against it by Beck are doubtlesslysound;nevertheless, the basic importanceof the concept of the highest good, both for ethical practice and for the understandingof the second Critique, cannot be denied. Beck's failure,in my opinion, to accordthe concept of the highest good its proper significance does not compromise in any serious way, however, the merits of his Commentary.It is a book "which would necessarilybe desired by a rational man whose reason controlledhis desires or at least controlledthe choicehe madeamong his desiderata" (p. 138). This means, as any Kant scholar can tell you, the book is good! THE UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS NOTES 1. A discussion of A Commentaryon Kant's Critique of Practical Reason by Lewis White Beck (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), pp. xvi+ 308. Page numbers cited in parentheses in the text refer to this work. 2. In order to simplify references I have abbreviated the titles of the books cited as shown below. I have usually cited both the German text and an English translation (in parentheses). Unless otherwise indicated translations are my own. This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 196 ETHICS KgS, Kant's gesammelteSchriften, ed. K6niglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften A, Anthropologie,KgS, Vol. VII Gr, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, in KgS, Vol. IV KdpV, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, in KgS, Vol. V KdrV, Kritik derreinen Vernunft,in KgS, Vol. III KdU, Kritik der Urteilskraft, in KgS, Vol. V MdS, Die Metaphysik der Sitten, in KgS, Vol. VI Rel, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzender blossen Vernunft, im KgS, Vol. VI Theorie und Praxis, Ober den Gemeinspruch:Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht fur die Praxis, in KgS, Vol. VIII ViiE, Eine Vorlesung Kants iber Ethik, ed. Paul Menzer Abbott, Kant's Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings on the Theory of Ethics, trans. T. K. Abbott Beck, Critique of Practical Reason and OtherWritings in Moral Philosophy, trans. L. W. Beck CoAJ, Critiqueof A estheticJudgement, trans. J. C. Meredith Greene, Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, trans. T. M. Greene and H. Hudson Kemp Smith, A Translation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith LoE, Lectures on Ethics, trans. Louis Infield Paton, The Moral Law or Kant's Groundworkof the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton 3. MdS, p. 226. 4. KdrV, A97, B130-32, B180-81, B561-63, passim. 5. Ibid., A534, B562. 6. H. J. Paton, The CategoricalImperative (London: Hutchinson's University Library, 1946), p. 215. 7. This essay is a part of the Introduction to the second edition of the Greene and Hudson translation of Kant's Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, published by Harper & Bros., and Open Court.; 8. KdpV, pp. 10-11 (Beck, p. 124). 9. The only difference that Schopenhauer noticed between the Foundations and the second Critique was an increase in garrulity and diffusion of thought. Thus he writes: "The Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft contains in its essentials the same material as the above mentioned Grundlegung; only the latter has a more concise and rigorous form, while in the former the subject is handled with greater prolixity, interspersed with digressions, and even padded with some pieces of moral rhetoric to heighten the impression (A. Schopenhauer, The Basis of Morality, trans. A. B. Bullock [New York: Macmillan Co., 19151), p. 26. 10. KdpV, Part I, chap. i. 11. Ibid., pp. 34, 35 (Beck, pp. 143, 146). 12. The distinction between the natural good and the moral good follows Kant's usage quite closely. He says, for example, in theAnthropologie,pp. 277 ff., "Die beiden Arten des Gutes [sind] has physische und moralische." The physical good is found to be happiness and the moral good is found to be virtue. Together they constitute the highest good (das hdckste Gut) as the moral-physical good (das hdchste moralisclh-physicheGut). I have deviated from Kant's terminology only to the extent of substituting the term "natural" for the term "physical." This alteration seems justified since, for Kant, "happiness" refers to the satisfaction of all desires, mental and spiritual as well as physical. Hence, to refer to happiness as the "physical good" seems mistakenly to restrict its meaning. 13. See my "The Copernican Revolution in Ethics: The Good Re-examined," Kant-Studien, Vol. LI, No. 1 (October, 1959). 14. KdpV, pp. 34, 35 (Beck, pp. 145, 146). 15. In being related with necessity to free willing (the good will) as its object, the will is conditioned only by that which is itself without any condition; the act of willing which accords with law (and is thus fully autonomous) is, by virtue of its universality, beyond all conditions. 16. MdS, pp. 385 if. (Abbott, pp. 296 ff.). 17. When Kant lectured on ethics, he used as his texts two works by A. G. Baumgarten, Initia philosophiae practicae primae and Ethica philosopizica. The German universities were required by state law to use textbooks in all courses, which helps to explain why Kant would use works by Baumgarten while disagreeing with him so completely (LoE, p. xi; see F. Paulsen, Immanuel Kant, His Life and Doctrine, trans. J. E. Creighton, and A. Lefevre [New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1902], Part I, p. 3). 18. ViYE,p. 31 (LoE, p. 25). 19. Ibid. 20. Ibid., p. 31 (pp. 25-26). Note also: "A practical proposition is tautological, when no performance can follow from it" (ibid., p. 177 [p. 141]). 21. MdS, p. 386 (Abbott, p. 297). 22. Ibid. 23. VaE, p. 32 (LoE, p. 26). 24. MdS, pp. 444 ff.; cf. Gr, p. 423 (Paton, p. 90). 25. ViiE, p. 30 (LoE, p. 24). 26. KdpV, pp. 60-61 (Beck, p. 169) (my italics). Beck's discussion of this point is instructive; see his Commentary,pp. 138-39. 27. KdU, p. 209 (CoAJ, p. 48). 28. Gr, pp. 415-16 (Paton, p. 83). 29. For this reason I think it is more in keeping with Kant's thought to stress the two-fold division of the good into the moral good and the natural good than to stress the three-fold division into bonitas problematical,bonitas pragmatic, and bonitas moralis. The lattter division corresponds as Beck shows to "the three kinds of imperative" (Commentary, p. 131). But both bonitas problematica and bonitas pragmatic belong to the class of natural goods. 30. Vi7E, p. 176 (LoE, p. 141). 31. KdpV, p. 41 (Beck, p. 152). This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HIGHEST GOOD IN KANT'S ETHICS 32. MdS, pp. 444-45. 33. Gr, p. 423 (Paton, p. 90). 34. KdpV, pp. 40 if. (Beck, pp. 151 ff.). 35. There is no goodness other than moral or natural goodness on which Kant could ground an obligation to seek the perfection of one's capacities. If one were to adapt Kant's theory to include the cultivation of all powers of mind, soul, and body as good in a sense neither moral nor natural, one would have to do so by relating these ends to desire. This could be done most easily by developing the implications of reason itself as the faculty of desire. Reason does have ends. It is a practical faculty that seeks the embodiment of ideas and ideals. The ideas of the Soul, the World, and Good as well as the ideas of Freedom, God, and Immortality are among those ends that reason poses for itself as tasks. The realization of these ideas constitutes the desire of reason, and, hence, these ideas may be said to be good. Now, if one were to show that all the powers of mind, soul, and body were essential to these ends of reason, he could perhaps present a theory of the goodness of the perfection of these powers that was distinct either from moral goodness or natural goodness. The goodness of this perfection, however, would still be conditioned by the relative goodness of the ends of reason. At this point one might have to conclude that the goodness of any particular end of reason is subject to final evaluation in terms of the highest good as the canon of pure reason. From this standpoint, however, all the ideas and ideals of reason are to be evaluated in terms of their contribution to the highest good in which moral goodness and natural goodness are combined, the former providing the supreme condition of the latter. Consequently, all the ends of reason, save the highest good itself (as reason's final goal), would be evaluated in terms of a concept of the good that simply unified the demands of both the natural good and the moral good. Thus the perfection of talents would be good either morally, as means to the attainment of the supreme condition of the highest good, or naturally, as a part of the completion of the highest good. We would still be at a loss, therefore, to point out a third sort of goodness constituted by the perfection of natural capacities. 36. One must not make the mistake of supposing that Kant was opposed to there being a material object of volition. He knew that there must be one for moral practice, but he insisted that the obligation to will a material object could never stem from the object itself. The obligation stems from the law. 37. KdpV, pp. 31, 91-92 (Beck, pp. 143, 197-98). Although I do not agree fully with Beck's discussion of the degrees of purity in Kant's ethical theory, I find his views singularly instructive (see Commentary, p. 54). 197 38. MdS, pp. 387, 393 if. (Abbott, pp. 298, 303 if.). 39. KdpV, p. 25 (Beck, p. 136); cf. KdpV, pp. 60-61 (Beck, p. 170). See also Gr, p. 415 (Paton, p. 83): ". . . there is one purpose which they not only can have, but which we can assume with certainty that they all do have by a natural necessity-the purpose, namely, of happiness ... a purpose which we can presuppose a priori and with certainty to be present in every man because it belongs to his very being" (my italics from "a purpose" through "being"). 40. KdpV, p. 34 (Beck, p. 146). 41. Gr, p. 441 (Paton, p. 109). It is very important to note that this doctrine, though not developed to any extent in the Foundations, is nonetheless present there. Thus Kant does partially prepare-even in his formal treatise on ethics-for the material application of the moral law. 42. Theorie und Praxis, p. 279. The "concept of duty need have no special purpose as a foundation, rather another purpose enters for the will of man"; cf. Rel, p. 4 (Greene, p. 4). 43. Theorie und Praxis, p. 279. 44. Rel, p. 7 (Greene, p. 7 n.). 45. Ibid.; cf. Kdp V, pp. I10 if. (Beck, pp. 214 ff.), and MdS, pp. 384 if. (Abbott, pp. 295 ff.). 46. KdpV, p. 113 (Beck, p. 217). 47. Paton seems to have overlooked this point for he holds that Kant asserted that the good will is the highest good. See Paton, op. cit., pp. 41 ff. 48. KdpV, p. 110 (Beck, pp. 214-15). 49. Ibid. 50. Ibid., p. 110 (p. 215). Kant's italics. 51. Ibid., pp. 110-11 (p. 215). Kant's italics. (See KdrV, B841 iff. [Kemp Smith, pp. 640 ff.].) 52. Ibid. 53. Ibid. It is important to note that Kemp Smith mistakenly translated "das h6chste Gut" as "the supreme good" (KdrV, B842 [Kemp Smith, p. 64]). He thereby contributed to the confusion of the highest good with the supreme good. 54. Ibid. 55. Ibid. 56. I hope this discussion at least suggests the answer to Beck's question, What am I to do to promote the highest good? (Commentary,p. 244.) 57. For my discussion of the highest good as a basis for an argument for the existence of God see "The Metaphysical Importance of the Highest Good as the Canon of Pure Reason in Kant's Philosophy," University of Texas Studies in Literature and Lan guage, Vol. I, No. 2 (Summer, 1959), and "Kant's Conception of the Highest Good as Immanent and Transcendent," Philosophical Review, Vol. LXVIII, No. 4 (October, 1959). This content downloaded from 129.82.28.124 on Sun, 20 Oct 2013 19:26:04 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions