Subido por lwlupette

platon puppet theatre

Anuncio
The Puppet Theater in Plato's Parable of the Cave
Author(s): Asli Gocer
Source: The Classical Journal, Vol. 95, No. 2 (Dec., 1999 - Jan., 2000), pp. 119-129
Published by: The Classical Association of the Middle West and South, Inc. (CAMWS)
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/3298308
Accessed: 24-06-2019 00:02 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Classical Association of the Middle West and South, Inc. (CAMWS) is collaborating
with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Classical Journal
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PUPPET THEATER IN PLATO'S
PARABLE OF THE CAVE
Although there has been much discussion about the shadows
of artifacts the prisoners watch in Plato's parable of the
cave (Republic 514a-519a), little has been said on the art
form to which this shadow-play is likened. The famous image is,
of course, that of the chained prisoners looking at the shadows
projected an to a surface in front of them. The shadows are of the
various paraphernalia some people are carrying in front of a fire
behind the prisoners. The setting is described in this manner:
"There is a path stretching between them [the prisoners] and the
fire. Imagine that along this path a low wall has been built, like
the screen in front of puppeteers [hosper tois thaumatopoiois] above
which they show their puppets [ta thaumata]" (R. 514bl-6).1 The
prisoners are amazed and amused by the flickering shadows
thinking that they are seeing real things moving in front of them.
This is because they cannot distinguish shadows as shadows.
According to the fable, only a few of the prisoners will be freed to
go out of the cave to see objects themselves in the sun light and then
be made to come down to share with the prisoners the bad news
that the shadows they have been looking at are merely shadows.
In doing so they will be ridiculed, and even killed. There are as
many layers to this parable as there are attempts to account for its
meaning. I can neither list nor evaluate them all here. I shall
consider only the similarity that Plato draws between the activity
in the cave and shadow puppet theater. Since I assume that few
things in the Platonic dialogues are said casually, I take the
reference to thaumatopoioi seriously and presume that the
description of puppeteering in the allegory is not an abstraction.
My suspicion is that the comparison within the allegory,
paradoxically, refers to an actual form of puppet theater. Indeed,
as I shall try to show, we have good circumstantial evidence to
1 All English quotations and abbreviations are from Cooper and Greek from
Shorey and Bury.
THE CLASSICAL JOURNAL 95.2 (1999) 119-129
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
120
ASLI
GOCER
suppose
this
suggestions
is
an
the
the
case.
shadow
I
likens the activity in the cav
clear on the kind of art form
make better sense of the mea
Why
the
reference
to
th
interest of commentators is a
of this paper. Suffice to not
parable mainly focus on the
and
produce
famously
instance,
On
his
that
view,
doctrine
against
non-complim
sees
of
the
story
refers
the
of
the
ascent
releasing
the
to
the
religious
s
o
min
interp
secular route to the meaning
a symbol of intellectual enlig
philosophy.4 Alan Bloom arg
and
alleges
that
interpretation
impressions of
thoughts.
a
If
freeing
this
of
is
the
politicians.5
political
this
is
a
treats the a
prisoners, a
In
true,
mind
Blo
fro
addition
interpretations,
t
so
parallels between the eff
cinema or television in co
Shershow has recently argu
hidden in Plato's metaphys
Plato's
disdain
both
for
the
o
metaphysical hierarchy and
in the cultural milieu of A
effort
has
2
Cornford,
3
While
what
been
p.
to
deter
227.
agreeing
religious
made
on
the
tradition
religious
it
depicts
Guthrie, p. 518; others suggest Parm
4 Annas, p.253-257.
5 Bloom, p. 404-405; Waterfield, p.
of
the
6
7
fable.
Most recently by Nehamas,
Shershow, p. 16-19.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
p.
23
PLATO'S PARABLE OF THE CAVE 121
in the image.8 The significance of the reference
metaphysics of shadows but more important
(thus ethical) triviality of this kind of theate
want to suggest that Plato's choice of shado
heralds more than his now notorious attack on a
out a peculiar form of comedy that embodies
vulgar, fantasy, and satire. In addition to
entertainment, therefore, I suggest that the pup
cave must be evaluated as a certain comedic per
most memorably represented by Aristophanic th
Let us turn, then, to exploring the comedic
shadow puppet theater, which was appropriate
Although there is little doubt that they were fa
one knows exactly whence puppet theater cam
Greeks. There is some suggestion that it was in t
that a group of popular entertainers arrived in
Dorian Megara by way of Sicily and ushered in
popular entertainment. So hilarious was their r
new phrase, "Megaran laughter," was coined t
comic performances from other merry-makers."
phanes and Xenophon all refer to them as thaum
a generic term for a conjurer, it is clear that th
be associated with a new style entertainer, wh
call a street performer: mimic, acrobat, ju
importantly, puppeteer. It is plausible that Plato
performers when he likens sophists and poets (H
to thaumatopoioi, for he accuses them of caring o
and entertainment rather than provoking thou
(Sph. 265c ff.; R. 602c; L. 663c.). Time and agai
the thaumatopoioi to visual artists as well, w
charming their viewers as the puppeteers do the
8 Except for a brief speculation by Guthrie, p. 518. G
however, that there is no shadow theater per se in the cave; t
such a performance.
9 For Plato there is no distinction between the beautiful a
e.g.); I cannot analyse the point here.
10 The date is said to be around, 480 B.C., see Nicoll, p. 20.
Republic is guessed between 380 and 370 BC; see Shorey (vol.I)
1 Presumably, a belly laughter, Nicole, p. 20
12 Aristotle, Poetics iii 1448a; Nichomachean Ethics iv.2; cf. A
60. Xenophon, Symposium iv. 55. For discussion on Corinth
involving thaumotopoioi in a puppet show, see Nicoll, p. 20-13
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
122
ASLI
GOCER
260d, Euth. 305b, G. 518b; S
suppose that Plato was fam
and cult statuettes, which were also used in various forms of
shadow puppet theater.13 W. K. C. Guthrie has suggested,
however, that the most plausible candidate for the kind of art form
Plato had in mind is the Karagoz theater.14 This is the modem
Turkish shadow puppet
theater that also figures in the Greek
15
tradition of Karagiozis. Although Guthrie does not go any
farther than briefly suggesting it, there is some reason to explore
the connection.
There is no question that the Karagoz theater comes out of the
ancient form of popular entertainment of shadow play and
puppetry. Geographically speaking, this is a tradition that
spreads from the Far East to eastern Mediterranean. The date of its
origin, however, is uncertain.16 Though it is probably Eastern in
origin, the likes of which have been documented in India, China,
and Egypt, no
one really knows when and exactly how Karagoz got
17
to the West. In its modem form still practiced in Turkey and
Greece, Karagoz theater consists of mini puppets that have been
affixed to sticks. The puppets are cutouts from leather and have
articulated body parts that are joined with ties, which are
operated by the puppeteer behind a screen. The puppets are thus
two-dimensional, and the set pieces are minimal. The light is
provided from behind the screen, which causes the puppets to
appear only as shadows to the viewing audience on the other side.
The puppeteer is typically alone in singing and playing the
different parts. Karagoz theater consists of what might be called
'standard' figures. Members are differentiated by their social class
and regional differences, which are portrayed by differences in
styles of clothing, dialect, and song. The main character is usually
a phallic-bearing figure who is preoccupied with food, sex, money,
13 Dodds, p. 194, p. 205 no. 96.
14 Guthrie, p. 518. For an opposition to this view, see Pryzluski p. 596. Pryzluski
rejects Guthrie's suggestion on the grounds that in the Karagoz theater the light is
behind the screen. This objection misses, however, the point that the shadow puppet
theater is merely an analogy in the cave parable; see n. 8.
15 Among the many views on the origins of the Greek Karagoz one theory holds
that Ottoman Turks learned the craft from the Byzantines and passed it on to the
Ottoman Greeks; Ritter, p. 616; and Bieber, p. 254; for other speculations see
Siyavusgil.
16 Myrsiades, p. 195, n.6; also see And.
17 Tietze, p. 16, n. 2.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO'S PARABLE OF THE CAVE 123
and thoughts of revenge against those who wrong
have a fixed set of social views, and his mor
according to the changes in his environment. Othe
troupe are either vulgar braggarts, obsequious w
old men, incompetent doctors, cruel authority fig
loose and quarrelsome women. The Karagoz "play
of improvised buffoonery by these types. It ca
satire as a genre, one which involves satirizi
everything. The main charge against this tradit
it is entirely without moral purpose or dramatic p
coarse in exploiting human defects and pecu
purposes of satiric entertainment. The tone is som
but often wacky and contemptuous of all establish
puppet theater that falls out of the Karago
entertainment for the masses, which consists of s
engaged in verbal jousting, singing, and dancing
outrageous humor and miscellaneous spoofs that K
embodiment of the ancient Greek comic spirit.
Given how little we know of its origin it is of co
important not to make any grandiose conclusions
Karagoz for 4th century Athens. And yet Plato's c
it clear that at least something like it did exist in
If this is true, then we may be in a better positio
Plato chooses to represent this specific form of
what is purported to be a parable of the effects of
mind rather than a generic reference to theatrical
Plato's sole point in the cave parable were th
mistake images for reality, then surely even bette
shadows would do. It would even be preferab
skiagraphia and other illusory forms of painti
often does, to register his complaints about th
shadows and inherent inaccuracy of perspective.
Aristophanes provides corroborating evidence f
something like the Karagoz theater is at play
the cave. For Aristophanic theather reflects the v
tone of Karagoz-like comedy. To be sure, the o
comedy are obscure, but the resemblence betwe
know of the merry-making tradition of the Mega
S8 Myrsiades, p. 26.
'9 R. 586b-c; Tht. 208e; Prm. 165c; L. 663c; Phd. 69b, e.g. For
of skiagraphia, and Greek attitudes toward shadow painting, se
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
124
ASLI
GOCER
and puppeteering is strikin
Aristophanic comedy is an a
and the that of the proto-K
the
Karagoz
finds
its
exp
Aristophanic burlesque. Eve
seems to mimic some of th
associated with the professional thaumatopoioi. For he
assimilates into his comedies the very routine of the Karagoz
puppeteers: puns, dialect, slapstick, taboo subjects, and fantastic
grotesquerie. His characters, very much in the tradition of Karagoz
performances, are often vicious, always foolish, and never
restrained. The language is, as it is in the Karagoz tradition,
bawdy and frequently obscene. Aristophanic theater like the
Karagoz style puppet theater involves the profoundly banal.
Indeed the most important idea Aristophanes appropriates from
this tradition is this: No matter how trivial, base, or inane the
topic, what provokes laughter is what governs comedy. We are
also well versed in Plato's complex attitude toward Aristophanes
consistingof antagonism toward his comedy and admiration toward
the man. Both in the form of certain kind of puppet theater and in
the spirit of Aristophanic theater, it is safe to suggest that at the
time Plato was composing the Republic there existed in Athens a
comic tradition that thrived on belly laughter. This important
historical fact may show that Plato is not only making
metaphysical points about shadows and puppets in his parable of
the cave, but taking on an entire culture of comedy.
Plato's attitude towards puppets is characteristically complex
and at times self-conflicting. On the one hand, he worries about
"tricksterism" and spell-making of the puppeteers (R. 364c), and
declares illegal any kind of image magic through the use of puppets
(L. 933b); an the other, he thinks that we are nothing but puppets
ourselves in the hands of god (L. 644e; cf. Sph. 266b). The
implications of this theology are too wide to be considered here.
The point is rather that the puppet image looms large in Platonic
20 For competing theories on the origins of Old Comedy and Aristophanic
theater, see McLeish, p. 50-54 and p. 93-108.
21 Whitman, p. 291.
22 For his argument that Old Comedy starts with Aristophanes, see Cartledge, p.
12-15. For an analysis of Aristophanic mockery of Platonic ideals, see. For a discussion
of Platonic mockery of Aristophanic ideals, see David, p. 21-29. For an analysis of
dueling utopias of Plato and Aristophanes, see Smith.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO'S PARABLE OF THE CAVE 125
metaphysics, and for that reason in the entir
Similarly, his references to shadows in other c
his image metaphysics. The most famous exampl
the term 'shadow' performs can be found in h
that the less real an entity the more shadow
more you know the better you will be able to
shadow (R. 520c, e.g.). Plato's entire philos
consists, therefore, of terms pertaining to puppe
However important puppets and shadows are to his
metaphysics, Plato's reference to the puppet theater in the cave
must nevertheless be re-evaluated in connection with the repeated
distinction he draws between seriousness and laughter. For Plato's
specific criticism is not that we might be fooled by the illusion of
puppetry, but that we might be tempted to laugh, and importantly,
laugh at nonsense. In a remarkable passage, Plato considers the
following thought experiment in the Laws (658b-c): What if, he
asks, whatever gave pleasure could be allowed to compete in
dramatic contests? Plato imagines that people would enter not only
epic poetry and lyric songs, but tragedy and comedy as well hoping
to win this pleasure contest. But "it will be no surprise if somebody
even reckons his best chance of winning lies in putting an a puppet
show [thaumata epideiknus]" (L. 658c2-3). A question is posed: who
deserves to win such a contest? Plato's answer is telling. He writes
that infants [ta smikra] will think it is the puppeteer who is
deserving of the first prize, while older children will pick the
comedian (L. 658c9-d3). Young men and ladies of taste will go for
tragedians, but older men will prefer epic poetry (L. 658d8-9).
Notable here is the fact that for Plato it is the infants who will
pick the puppet show, for they are the slaves of easy laughter. We
all know about Plato's dislike of violent laughter. "We mustn't be
lovers of laughter," Plato famously writes, "for whenever anyone
indulges in violent laughter, a violent change of mood is likely to
follow... Then, if someone represents worthwhile people as
overcome by laughter, we won't approve" (R. 388e4-5, 606c; cf. L.
732c-d). While it is true that violent laughter was considered
undignified in general, Plato's reasons seem to go beyond mere
convention. As I will discuss below, they lie in his aversion to
change, both for psychological and metaphysical reasons. So stark
is his aversion to laughter that Plato is unabashedly declares the
object of comic laughter to be a form of evil (Phlb. 48cl, 49dll-e4).
The nature of the laughable [to geloion], Plato contends, lies in
malice, for only a malicious person derives pleasure from watching
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
126
ASLI
GOCER
misfortune, deformity, w
children are ignorant of th
souls,
they
This is
nature
must
be
prevente
because, "imitations
and settle in to habi
395d1-3; cf. 404e). The metaphysical and psychological
underpinnings at work here are complex, but they are intimately
connected. The metaphysical reasons pertain to Plato's general
commitment to permanence and stability. "The best things are least
liable to alteration or change," it is famously said in the Republic
(380e4). "Whatever is in good condition, whether by nature or craft
or both, admits least of being changed by anything else (R. 381bl2). Laughter implies not only a physical change in the human body
but a psychological transformation as well. Both kinds of change
undermine Plato's project for becoming like the unchanging and
serene Forms, an analysis I cannot provide here.23 There is also a
theological subtext to aversion to change as well. Plato discusses
god as being in an utterly serene condition, in a state between excess
of pleasure and pain (L. 792e, 732b; cf. R. 381c; Stm. 269e). God is
said to be not subject to the kinds of upheavals brought about by
laughter (R. 375c, 410d, e.g.). As such god is the ultimate model (L.
716d, 803c; Tht. 176a; Stm. 274e; Prt. 326d). All legislation that
pertains to art, education, city administration is24 based an this,
what Plato takes to be the goal of becoming god-like. Plato is
especially anxious, however, for the long-term psychological
consequences of laughter. As the discussion in Philebus 48d-50d
shows, the main worry is that the innocent laughter here and there
creates and feeds false pleasures. Continued practice of deriving
false pleasures, however, will result in devastating cognitive
mistakes that will ultimately cost the person the harmony of his
psyche. In order to do justice to this topic, we must investigate
Plato's theory of pleasure, which we cannot do here. Let us also
leave aside the question of whether Plato is mistaken about the
psychological harms of laughter. Suffice to point out for our
purposes that Plato objects not only to art forms that provokes 25
laughter but also the representation of laughter in art. It would
be a grave transgression, Plato says, to represent whether in
pictures, buildings, or any other works, images of drunkenness and
23 For a defense of this point, see Gocer (1999).
24 See Gocer (1998).
25 R. 389a rejects Illiad 1.599-600 for this reason.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO'S PARABLE OF THE CAVE 127
laughter, and characters that are vicious, unre
and graceless (R. 401b; 403e; L. 637b). Use of pro
representation of profane language are also objecte
grounds. For Plato art that depicts such thing
amusement. As such, it feeds the childish side o
enjoys profanity and obscenity, and is amused
perversion. This is why for Plato art that appeals
puppet theater, is utterly devoid of psychologic
lacks moral purpose. He says, "it is because t
weakness in our nature that tromp l'oeil paint
conjuring [thaumatopoiia], and other forms of tric
that are short of magical" (R. 602d). And precise
power that Plato thinks that the kind of nonsen
laugh like children is to be excluded from good soci
Plato's famous worry is that the majority is c
like children most people judge anything on basis
and primal pleasure it brings about. Certainly t
thinks that puppet theater is good simply beca
laugh. Plato finds the idea laughable itself that
can truly judge, art or anything else for that matt
his view what is truly laughable are a host of
should in fact leave us crying, a law that does
natural law, for instance, (Stm. 296a) or a sophi
distinctions in words instead of investigating how
278b). Frivolity and nonsense are exactly the ki
modes that Plato worries will lead to instabilit
psychological damage. The reason some kinds
excluded from the republic-included in those a
puppeteering-is that they fail to be the right
citizens to emulate. The picture Plato presents
stark, and strikingly modern. Like Plato we too se
the weak sides of the psyche binged an mere a
diversion, the person would become like the le
imitating, and thus cease to function as a full hum
the rating systems for cinema and television and s
we appear to share with Plato, the person w
passing time with trifling amusement will lose his
an account of overfeeding the wrong sorts of desi
end will warp his relationship to reality. And
largely made up of emotional quasimodos such as t
amusement to enlightenment, Plato worries (and
our arguments for artistic freedom), justice
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
128
ASLI
GOCER
impossibility. Platonic alarmi
the fact that he takes as give
such entertainment threatens
If what I propose about the
is anywhere near the mark
cave parable is a brilliant tour de force. This analogy is
thoroughly consistent with Plato's general criticism of popular art,
which in his view brings about psychological disaster to the
individual soul and political damage to the city. It is also
consistent with his metaphysical project of showing that the
majority think that what they see is real. Moreover, with this
example Plato highlights once again the cognitive
inconsequentiality of comedy, and especially the kind exemplified
by Aristophanes. His discussion shows once again the deep divide
that exists between what he considers the truly laughable and
serious and the popular opinion. In this sense, the puppet theater is
a splendid example, consistent with his metaphysical,
psychological, and political doctrines that underlie his criticism of
art in the Corpus, of the multiple layers in Plato's parable. I
conclude this paper venturing one other suggestion. If the analysis
above is true, then perhaps it is better to think of Plato's criticism
of mimesis not as a sweeping condemnation of all such activity but
rather a censure of certain specific artistic endeavor. If Plato's
disdain for the puppet theater is indeed explained at least in part
by his aversion for the psychological and moral deformity caused
by childishness and boorish laughter, perhaps his criticism of
mimetic activity is targeted to particular forms of art rather than a
general denunciation of all artistic activity, as it has been
traditionally supposed. But that is for another project.
ASLI GOCER
University of Toronto
BIBLIOGRAPHY
And, Metin. 1975. Karagoz: Turkish Shadow Theater. Ankara.
Annas, Julia. 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford.
Bieber, Margarete. 1938. The History of Greek and Roman Theater. Pr
Bloom, Allan. 1968. The Republic of Plato. New York.
Bury, R. G., trans., 1926. The Laws. Cambridge, Massachusetts.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO'S PARABLE OF THE CAVE 129
Cartledge, Paul. 1990. Aristophanes and His Theater of
Cooper, John, ed. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indiana
Cornford, F.M. 1941. The Republic of Plato. London.
David, E. 1984. Aristophanes and Athenian Society
Century B.C. Leiden.
Dies, A. 1937. Bulletin de l'Assocation Guillaume Bude
Dodds, E.R. 1951. Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley.
Ettinghausen, Richard. 1934. "Early Shadow Figu
American Institute for Persian Art and Archeology 6:
Gocer, Asli. 1999. "Hesuchia, A Metaphysical Princ
Psychology." J. Annas, McPherran, eds. New
Metaphysics and Epistemology. Apeiron 33 (forthcom
-----. 1998. "The Theological Basis of Plato's Criticism o
to Icons. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 36.3: 3
Guthrie, W.K.C. 1975. History of Greek Philosophy. V
Man and his Dialogues: Earlier Period. Cambridge.
Jurkowski, Henryk. 1996. A History of European Pupp
Keuls, Eva C. 1978. Plato and Greek Painting. Leiden.
McLeish, Kenneth. 1981. The Theatre of Aristophanes.
Myrsiades, Linda S. and Myrsiades, Kostas. 1992. Ka
Comedy in Greek Puppet Theater. Lexington.
Nehamas, Alexander. 1988. "Plato and the Mass Media." The Monist 71:
214-34.
Nicoll, Allardyce. 1931. Masks, Mimes, and Miracles: Studies in Popular
Theater. London and New York.
Pryzluski, Jean. 1938. "La theatre d'ombres et la caverne de Platon."
Byzantion XIII: 595-603.
Ritter, Hermann. 1903. Der Mimus, ein literarentwick-lu ngsgeschischtlicher
Versuch I. Berlin.
Shershow, Scott C. 1995. Puppets and "Popular" Culture. Ithaca.
Shorey, Paul, trans. 1935. The Republic in Two Volumes. Volume II.
Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Smith, Nicholas D. 1992. "Political Activity and Ideal Economics: Two
Related Utopian Themes in Aristophanic Comedy," Utopian Studies 3.1:
84-94.
Siyavusgil, Sabri Esat. 1961. Karagoz. Istanbul.
Tietze, Andreas. 1977. The Turkish Shadow Theater. Berlin.
Waterfield, Robin. 1993. Republic. Oxford.
Whitman, Cedric H. 1964. Aristophanes and the Comic Hero. Cambridge.
This content downloaded from 141.2.140.67 on Mon, 24 Jun 2019 00:02:32 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Descargar