M -EPLI MAASTRICHT EUROPEAN PRIVATE LAW INSTITUTE WORKING PAPER No. 2016/03 THE EXPANDING CIRCLE OF CONTRACT LAW Jan M. Smits FACULTY OF LAW MAASTRICHT UNIVERSITY SEPTEMBER 2016 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network at http://www.ssrn.com Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2831584 THE EXPANDING CIRCLE OF CONTRACT LAW Jan M. Smits Maastricht University [email protected] Abstract People and corporations are increasing held liable in private law for the external effects of their actions, in particular in cases that involve some fundamental aspect of “justice” such as severe violations of labour standards or threats to the environment. These public interests are traditionally guarded by the state, but are now increasingly enforced by private individuals, in particular in cross-border situations where the injustice takes place in a “far-away” country. This contribution explores what is the potential of contract law in dealing with this “private law justice across borders.” It asks whether the doctrine of privity of contract should be traded in for an approach that better takes the externalities of contracts into account. It is argued that current contract law is ill-suited to deal with this challenge and should adopt new techniques to expand the circle of people contract law seeks to protect. Keywords: Contracts and third parties; Privity; Voidability; Private law justice; Corporate Social Responsibility; Foreign direct liability claims; Externalities; “faraway” countries 2 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2831584 THE EXPANDING CIRCLE OF CONTRACT LAW Jan M. Smits 1 Introduction 1 Few principles of private law are more obvious than privity of contracts. Only the 2 contracting parties themselves have the rights and obligations that follow from their agreement; third parties are not affected by it. Legal doctrine has it that no real exceptions to this principle of the relative effect of contracts exist. Agency, a contract for the benefit of a third party (stipulatio alteri) and so-called “direct actions” from 3 third parties to a contracting party, or from contracting parties to a third party, all have an independent justification that leaves the doctrine of privity intact. 4 However, the sanctity of the dogma of privity does not mean that contracts do not affect third parties. On the contrary, if one looks beyond legal doctrine at the reality of contract practice, it becomes abundantly clear that individual contracts can affect other people in many different ways. If I buy the etching entitled “Echoes and Shadows” and hang it on my wall, I am depriving many others from enjoying it. In the same vein, my decision to buy a Volkswagen will make pollution increase to the detriment of others. Similarly, when two business partners agree to open a restaurant, they are likely to lure customers away from existing eateries in the area. The law usually does not consider these side effects of exchange as relevant. Yet the question gaining importance in present-day society is whether this approach to privity is still the right one and whether contract law should not expand the circle of people it seeks to protect. This explorative contribution offers some thoughts on 1 2 See e.g. Hein Kötz European Contract Law I (1997) 245 ff. Widely accepted in civil law jurisdictions, as reflected in art 6:110 of the Principles of European Contract Law (PECL). 3 Fr example recognised in French law, on which Kötz European Contract Law 254, but not in all o jurisdictions. 4 Cf Michael J Trebilcock The Limits of Freedom of Contract (1993) 58 ff. 3 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2831584 whether there is indeed a need to expand the circle of contract law and, if so, how this could be realised. 2 Defining the problem: private law justice across borders In April 2013, the world was shocked by the collapse of the Bangladesh Rana Plaza garment factory killing more than 1100 workers. The factory mostly produced garments for international clothing companies, including Benetton, Mango, JC Penney, Primark and Wal-Mart. Interestingly, victims and their relatives filed a class action in an American court against (inter alia) the American retailers, claiming that 5 the defendants were aware of the unsafe conditions at the place of work and failed to inspect the building properly, thus violating both international human rights 6 standards and the American law of torts. Such a so-called foreign direct liability claim aims to hold a wealthy party located in the United States liable for a wrong committed by one of its suppliers or sub-suppliers in another country. One can readily see why such a claim is brought: not only is it likely that the multinational company has deeper pockets than the local employer, also as a matter of policy it seems not so odd to consider the local supplier as part of a supply chain that reaches all the way from the local employee to the multinational clothing company that profits from the use of cheap labour. This phenomenon of direct claims brought against a multinational company benefiting from wrongs committed by persons it should have controlled better, is 7 now rapidly spreading to other jurisdictions. Another example is the mass claim of South African workers against Cape/Gencor to seek compensation for asbestosrelated diseases in the English courts. One can also think of environmental cases. These usually deal with very concrete situations of environmental pollution, as in 5 Abdur Ramahan et al v JC Penney Company Inc et al District of Columbia 26-04-2015 case no 1:2015cv00619 <pdfserver.amlaw.com/nlj/RahamanRanaPlazacomplaint.pdf>. 6 See eg Liesbeth FH Enneking “Crossing the Atlantic? The Political and Legal Feasibility of European Foreign Direct Liability Cases” (2009) 40 Geo Wash Int'l L Rev 903 903-938. 7 Lubbe v Cape PLC [2000] UKHL 41 (HL), subsequently settled. For an overview of other cases, see <www.business-humanrights.org/en/law-lawsuits>. 4 8 Kiobel v Royal Dutch Petroleum in which oil company Shell was sued (albeit unsuccessfully) in the US courts for oil spills in the Nigerian Ogoni River Delta. 9 Such cases can also aim to protect the environment in general. A recent example is the much publicised 10 Dutch Urgenda case in which a non-governmental organisation together with 886 individual claimants sued the State of the Netherlands, arguing that its climate policy was wrongful against them and future 11 generations. The district court ordered the State to ensure a reduction of carbon emissions to 25% of the level of 1990. A direct claim against an energy company before a German court is envisaged by the Peruvian farmer Saúl Luciano Lliyua. He claims that German company RWE, as a major emitter of greenhouse gases, is causing global warming and that he is directly threatened by this as a glacier close to his home in Huaraz is likely to melt and cause repeated flooding. The claimed damages of € 20 000 would allow Lliyua to install a glacial flood early warning 12 system. In much the same way as in the previously mentioned labour cases, these claims aim to establish a legally relevant link between the party that benefits from a certain activity (in these cases oil companies and carbon emitters) and the person who is suffering damage as a result. These examples show the increasing wish to hold people liable in private law for the external effects of their actions, in particular in cases that involve some fundamental aspect of “justice” like the above severe violation of labour standards or threats to the environment. These are to a large extent public interests that are traditionally guarded by the state, but which private individuals now increasingly seek to enforce themselves. This does not come as a surprise as it is highly difficult for a state to enforce its norms legally through public law across the borders of its 8 9 Kiobel v Royal Dutch Petroleum Co. 133 S.Ct. 1659 (2013). A similar case by Milieudefensie and Nigerian farmers is pending in the Dutch courts: see eg District Court The Hague 30 January 2013 ECLI:NL:RBDHA:2013:BY9854 (Akpan and Milieudefensie v Royal Dutch Shell), appeal is pending. 10 See eg Arthur Neslen “Dutch Government ordered to Cut Carbon Emissions in Landmark Ruling” The Guardian (24-06-2015), appeal is pending. 11 District Court The Hague 24 June 2015, ECLI:NL:RBDH:2015:7145 (Stichting Urgenda v Staat der Nederlanden), appeal is pending. 12 5 <www.germanwatch.org/de/der-fall-huaraz>. own country, and the vacuum must be filled by individual parties relying on private law . 13 They seek what could be called “private law justice across borders.” However, the mere fact that these claims are increasingly made does not imply that they will also succeed. Apart from issues of international jurisdiction, 14 substantive private law has difficulty in accommodating externalities that are as remote as described above. In case the law of delict is used as a basis for holding the defendant liable, the plaintiff needs to show that the company did not exercise reasonable care in preventing the damage to occur. When applying Lord Atkin’s timeless neighbour principle, this comes down to the question whether the plaintiffs 15 are so closely and directly affected by the act of the multinational company that the latter ought reasonably to have had them in contemplation as being so affected. In other words, must Benetton, Royal Dutch Shell, and RWE regard a Bangladeshi worker, an Ogoni fisherman and a Peruvian farmer as their neighbour in law? This seems difficult to construe in the present law, even though the need is increasingly felt to regard them as such. Contract law provides another potential basis for liability. Benetton, Shell and RWE must conclude a great variety of contracts with other parties (including producers, suppliers and consumers) before they are even able to damage the interests of the mentioned plaintiffs. As indicated in section 1, these are interests that the present law usually considers as external to the contract and therefore as irrelevant. This is not only true in international cases, but also in the typical domestic 16 situation of two parties in a distribution network who agree on a certain price or quality, which will subsequently affect the downstream and upstream parties in the chain. Existing contract law does not consider this worrying in any way, but here too the question is whether this is indeed the right approach in present-day society. 13 See in more detail Jan M Smits “Het privaatrecht van de toekomst” (2015) 52 Tijdschrift voor Privaatrecht 517-547. 14 15 The case of Kiobel v Royal Dutch Petroleum Co. 133 S.Ct. 1659 (2013), failed already on this ground. Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 580 (HL). 16 Roger van den Bergh “Private Law in a Globalising World: Economic Criteria for Choosing the Optimal Regulatory Level in a Multilevel Government System” in Michael Faure & André J Van der Walt (eds) Globalization and Private Law: The Way Forward (2010) 83. 6 There is one specific way in which contract law is relevant to the above cases. In practice, companies tend to make unilateral declarations about their commitment to the environment, fair labour and respect for human rights. They usually do so by declaring that they will comply with voluntary codes for corporate social responsibility. These Corporate Social Responsibility (“CSR”) Codes, including the 2009 King Code of Governance Principles for South Africa (“King18III”), 17 the 2011 19 United Nations Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights and the British 2014 Ethical Trading Initiative Base Code, contain guidelines for socially sensitive businesses. Such codes may considerably raise the potential for claims. 20 If, for example, multinational garment company A states that it will observe a CSR Code that ensures safe and hygienic working conditions in the manufacturing of the apparel it sells, but its suppliers or sub-suppliers do not provide for a safe working place for their employees, many parties within the supply chain have an interest in enforcement because they all share one another’s reputational risks. Thus, potential claimants could range from the end-consumer to A ’s retailers, and any other suppliers or sub-suppliers and their employees within the chain. 21 This does not mean that all these parties can in fact make a successful claim based on the violation of a CSR Code. The scarce case law shows that the closer the relationship between the claimant and the defendant, the higher the chances of success. For example, the claim by the University of Wisconsin for breach of contract against its direct contracting partner Adidas for not complying with anti-sweatshop provisions, requiring Adidas to provide certain benefits to workers producing college-branded apparel, led Adidas – settling in the shadow of the law – to pay 17 Institute of Directors King Code of Governance Principles for South Africa (2009). 18 Business and Human Rights Resource Centre “ U N Guiding Principles” (2015) Business and Human Rights Resource Centre <www.business-humanrights.org/en/un-guiding-principles> (accessed 21-042016). 19 Ethical Trading Initiative “ETI Base Code” (2015) Ethical Trading Initiative <www.ethicaltrade.org/eti-base-code> (accessed 21-04-2016). 20 For a meticulous analysis of how CSR Codes fit the existing system of private law see Anna Beckers Enforcing Social Responsibility Codes (2015). 21 See on this Jan M Smits “Enforcing Corporate Social Responsibility Codes under Private Law, or: on the Disciplining Power of Legal Doctrine” (2016) 23 Ind J Global Legal Stud forthcoming. 7 22 compensation to 2 700 workers in Indonesia. However, the claim of employees of Wal-Mart’s foreign suppliers in China, Bangladesh and Indonesia against Wal-Mart to improve local labour conditions failed, even though Wal-Mart was eager to advertise on its home market that it only used responsible suppliers. The California 23 Court of Appeal found it impossible to regard the employees as third-party beneficiaries of standards Wal-Mart obliged its suppliers to use. The obligation for suppliers to comply with the set standards was seen as an obligation between WalMart and its suppliers, and not as one between Wal-Mart and the plaintiffs. Similarly, the claim that Wal-Mart was the joint employer of claimants was not accepted as this would have required Wal-Mart to have had control over day-to-day employment, while this was not the case. This decision is an exemplary application of the established principles of contract law (courts in other jurisdictions would probably have reached a similar result), but it does not pay heed to the possibly changing perceptions of global justice. The question that remains is therefore whether, despite the current reluctance to allow claims in the above cases, emerging societal views about the importance of corporate social responsibility have not developed in such a way that a claim must be allowed in case of severe cross-border violations of labour standards or threats to the environment. It may not matter too much whether the basis for this claim lies in tort or contract because in both instances the ultimate question is which interests private law must protect: only the interests of a victim who stands in a “direct” relationship with the potential tortfeasor or of another contracting party, or also the interests of people who are further away? Put differently: which relationship is sufficiently close to be relevant for the law? My focus in the remainder of this contribution is on contract law, for which I wish to phrase the question in terms of externalities: which side effects of an individual contract must the law take into account? Put differently: should contract law expand the circle of people it wants to protect? It is impossible to answer this question without a small survey of the current way in which externalities are dealt with by contract law and on what view 22 University of Wisconsin v Adidas claim filed on 13 July 2012 in the US federal court, settled in April 2013: see <www.business-humanrights.org/en/adidas-lawsuit-re-university-of-wisconsin#c18941>. 23 Doe v Wal-Mart Stores 572 F.3d 677 (2009). 8 of contracts this is in fact based (section 3). This leads me to explore an alternative view and its consequences in section 4. Section 5 concludes. 3 Externalities and contract law It was seen in the above sections that contracts could have many external consequences, but that the law does not always consider these. This section looks at when the current law does still do so, and on which underlying view of contracts this is based. The focus of present-day contract law is almost entirely on what the contract implies for the parties. Exceptions to the doctrine of privity are preferably seen as consistent with the rule that only the parties can derive rights and obligations from their agreement. This explains why the topic of unfair contracts or terms is seen as 24 being about unfairness in the direct relationship between the two parties. Contractual fairness is at best a matter of applying doctrines such as good faith or unconscionability. Parties need, to a certain extent, take into account each other’s 25 interests, not those of others who may also be affected by the contract. This does not mean that the side effects of free exchange are never considered. They are, but mostly through the doctrine of prohibited contracts. Underlying the reasons for illegality – violation of a statute or of national public policy and good morals (boni mores) – lies not only the wider interest of society in general, but often also the wish to protect people who are not a party to the contract. This explains why, in a previous26age, this overriding public interest curtailed the pernicious effects of the industrial revolution, while today it still puts limits on a wide variety of contracts including cartel agreements, discriminatory contracts, and contracts in restraint of trade. A Dutch case provides a good example of how the interests of third parties can inform the notion of good morals. In Club 13, a brothel was purchased by a defendant who relied on making profits by renting out rooms to prostitutes. The Dutch Hoge Raad considered this a contract that could be contrary to 25 26 24 9 On which eg Jan M Smits Contract Law: A Comparative Introduction (2014) 136. For a European perspective: Kötz European Contract Law 124 ff. See also Stephen A Smith Atiyah’s Introduction to the Law of Contract 6th ed (2005) 20 ff. 27 good morals if its foreseeable consequences consisted of facilitating exploitation of third parties such as prostitutes. 28 The true question is therefore not whether contract law considers externalities, but which external effects it considers relevant and how it protects these as a matter of 29 legal technique. The answer that the present-day law gives is not optimal in view of facilitating plaintiffs in “far-away” countries. First, when it comes to the type of externalities taken on board, the current law reasons that the more harm suffered by others as a result of contracting is taken into account, the more freedom of contract would be curtailed. This is clearly in line with 30 the classical liberal view that contracting parties must be given full autonomy in setting their own rights and obligations. The more externalities must be taken into account, the less autonomy exists. This may explain why current contract law has no well-defined concept of externalities: liberal political theory lacks a convincing theory of how to accommodate harm done to others through contracting. 31 Defining 32 a practice as immoral if “the thought of it makes the man on the Clapham omnibus sick” is all nice and well, but it is too open-ended for assessing whether contracts leading to a severe violation of norms of corporate social responsibility must be prohibited. Although thinking in terms of externalities is the precinct of economists, they are also unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question when the law must consider externalities. Economists define negative externalities as costs suffered by third parties as a result of an economic transaction. In that case, the total social costs emanating from the transaction differs from the private costs borne by the parties. 33 Economists may argue that these costs are preferably internalised, but are not able to say in which cases this must happen, leaving open when the multinational company 27 28 Hoge Raad 2 February 1990 NJ 1991 265 (Club 13). Rightly so: Trebilcock Limits of Freedom 58 and Lyn KL Tjon Soei Len The Effects of Contracts Beyond Frontiers: A Capabilities Perspective on Externalities and Contract Law in Europe (2013) 95. 29 32 30 33 31 F his term: AJP Taylor “Far-Away Countries ” The New York Review of Books (06-06-1968). See for o an overview of contract theories eg Robert A Hillman The Richness of Contract Law (1997). See r Trebilcock Limits of Freedom 58 ff. Lord Devlin’s view, as described by HLA Hart The Morality of the Criminal Law (1964). t See eg Richard A Posner Economic Analysis of Law 6 ed (2003) 71. 10 must bear the costs of bad labour practices or environmental damage suffered in other countries. This means that the current law is in need of a new theory of when the effects of contracts outside of the direct circle of the parties must be taken into account.34 There is a second reason why current contract law finds it difficult to accommodate externalities. This is because of the use of the legal doctrine of prohibited contracts itself, which is not conducive to reaching acceptable results. Two difficulties exist. The first has to do with the substantive norm of public policy 35 and good morals itself. Without going into the intricacies of the doctrine of 36 prohibited contracts, it is clear that this norm, as referring to fundamental interests of the community, is essentially a national one: it aims to protect national society. This comes out best in the German37§138 BGB that emphasises the effects of the contract on the German public order, but a similar national interpretation of public order can be found in other jurisdictions. This makes it more difficult to also consider the effects of the contract that appear outside the own borders. The Dutch case of Club 13, referred to above, is a case in point: the persons possibly exploited in that case were the prostitutes affected by the defendant’s purchase of the brothel. These “third parties” were close enough to be directly affected by the contract, but it is not likely that the same conclusion would have been reached in case the exploitation 38 takes place at a geographically remote location (as in the case of sweatshops). Even if one would be able to apply a more international version of public policy and good morals, a second difficulty emerges. If we assume that certain types of corporate behaviour violate public policy and good morals, it is doubtful whether this leads to the desired legal effect. Following the maxim ex turpi causa non oritur 34 Tjon Soei Len The Effects of Contracts offers a theory based on Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approach to minimum justice. 35 36 See in a comparative perspective, Kötz European Contract Law 154. Cf Sasfin (Pty) Ltd v Beukes 1989 (1) SA 1 (A). 37 Cf H-P Haferkamp “§138” in M Schmoeckel, J Ruckert & R Zimmerman (eds) Historisch-kritischer Kommentar zum BGB Band I (2003) 708. Even though there is discussion about the question whether public policy and good morals can also refer to a specific part of society and not only to society as a whole. 38 Tjon Soei Len The Effects of Contracts 152 probably reaches a different outcome. 11 39 actio, an illegal contract is void or at least unenforceable. This makes illegality a 40 if we accept that it is possible to mitigate the consequences of crude instrument, even prohibited contracts. Declaring the multinational’s contract with a local supplier unenforceable means throwing away the baby with the bathwater: the contract must 41 not be unenforceable, it must be different. Moreover, it would gravely undermine the willingness of parties to conclude contracts if their bindingness is debatable. 42 One is therefore in need of a more nuanced technique. The conclusion from this section is that current contract law assesses externalities of individual contracts mainly through the doctrine of prohibited contracts. This is in line with a classical view of contracting that gives pride of place to the autonomy of the parties in setting their own rights and obligations. However, this approach suffers from the disadvantage that the doctrine of illegality is not particularly suited to accommodate either a substantive norm on international corporate behaviour or the consequences of violating this norm. This prompts the question whether an alternative approach is possible. 4 Towards an alternative view: Can we expand the circle? What the law qualifies as reasonable expectations of contracting parties is directly influenced by social norms. These norms tend to enter the legal system through open-ended concepts such as reasonable care, good faith, public policy, and good morals. The current interpretation of these concepts implies a rather limited view of whom we owe legal duties. It was seen above that the circle of contract law essentially only extends to the contracting parties and that externalities are therefore rarely taken into account. The techniques currently available in private law are also not conducive to include externalities. However, this does not mean that views of 39 40 Cf art 15:101-15:102 PECL. Art 15:103 of the PECL. In our type of situation, it is difficult to see how the techniques of partial nullity or severance could help in upholding the contract. 41 For a different view, see Tjon Soei Len The Effects of Contracts 161-162. 42 Cf Anthony Kronman “Contract Law and Distributive Justice” (1980) 89 Yale LJ 472 and Charles Fried Contract as Promise (1981) 106. 12 43 what the law should be, and the instruments it uses, cannot change. This section therefore aims to do two things. First, it explores whether any signs exist that today’s societal views are changing with regard to the need to do justice in the type of cases discussed in section 2. Second, it asks how these potentially changing views are best realised within the current legal framework. Any potential answer to the first question must start with asking about the effects of globalisation on society. There is an increasing amount of literature that looks at what it means for interpersonal relationships that the world is becoming ever more connected in terms of communication,44commerce, and culture and in facing crises 45 such as migration and global warming. This literature explains that globalisation is affecting our mode of thinking about ethics and law. Alan Fairnington has coined 46 the term selfish altruism, which would denote a break with the egoistic consumerism of the past. He argues that the twenty-first century society will see the rise of a new global morality with consumers who still want the best for themselves, but not at the cost of others. They wish to avoid collateral damage in their consumption pattern. Fairnington argues that this change in perspective is caused by increasing sensitivity of people to the cost of consumption as a result of issues like global warming, carbon footprints 47 and business scandals. Companies will have to answer to this need for “real values.” On this view, ethical behaviour is no 48 longer opposed to self-interest: it is simply not in our interest to ignore ethics because it will lead to global injustice and environmental catastrophe. 43 On this in the context of public policy David Ibbetson A Historical Introduction to the Law of Obligations (1999) 213: Courts have always moulded their ideas of social needs and interests. 44 Jürgen Habermas The Divided West (2006) 175 describes globalisation as: “[T]he cumulative processes of a worldwide expansion of trade and production, commodity and financial markets, fashions, the media and computer programmes, news and communications, networks, transportation systems and flows of migration, the risks generated by large-scale technology, environmental damage and epidemics, as well as organised crime and terrorism.” 45 46 Cf Jeremy Rifkin The Empathic Civilisation (2010). Alan Fairnington The Age of Selfish Altruism (2010). 47 Fairnington Selfish Altruism. See also John H Dunning (ed) Making Globalization Good: The Moral Challenges of Global Capitalism (2003). 48 Peter Singer “The Drowning Child and the Expanding Circle” New Internationalist Magazine (April 1997). 13 49 If people were indeed becoming “do-gooders”, this would be in line with what William Lecky referred to as “moral progress.” He wrote already in 1869: “ A t one time the benevolent affections embrace merely the family, soon the circle expanding includes first a class, then a nation, then a coalition of nations, then all humanity.” 50 This nicely fits Peter Singer’s observation that interpersonal relationships have 51 over the years only become more important. People have always had the tendency to help “their own” and not “others”, but in a globalising world less and less “others” exist: the circle of people one cares for is expanding. Interestingly, there is also experimental evidence for this globalisation of morality. Experiments show that the 52 willingness to donate to strangers increases with the extent of a country’s 53 globalisation. If globalisation increases, the desire to cooperate across the globe, and consider other people’s interests, increases as well. Now, the crucial point is whether this rise of ethical consumerism must also be reflected in the law. Does tomorrow’s reasonable person have to take into account the interests of third parties at far away locations? The problem here is not so much the existence of a general legal norm that prescribes to do so. Many will accept that there must be an enforceable obligation to avoid labour exploitation and environmental damage, but the real problem is against whom this norm can be enforced. It is impossible to give an answer without considering the exact relationship at hand. When it comes to the liability of the multinational company visà-vis the local employees in another country, 54 I have already hinted at arguments that speak in favour of extending the scope of liability. If the multinational company profits from the use of cheap labour within the supply chain, it could be argued that 49 Larissa MacFarquhar “Extreme Altruism: should you care for strangers at the expense of your family?” (22-09-2015) The Guardian <www.theguardian.com/world/2015/sep/22/extreme-altruismshould-you-care-for-strangers-as-much-as-family> (accessed 21-04-2016). 50 51 52 William EH Lecky History of European Morals from Augustus to Charlemagne I (1869) 103. Peter Singer The Expanding Circle: Ethics, Evolution, and Moral Progress (1981 and 2011). N Buchan, G Grimalda, R Wilson, M Brewer, E Fatas & M Foddy “Globalization and human R cooperation” (2009) 106 PNAS 4138 4138-4142. 53 54 Cf John McMurtry Unequal Freedoms: The Global Market as an Ethical System (1998). Different situations are discussed in Smits (2016) Ind J Global Legal Stud. 14 it must also be responsible for the working circumstances of the labourers employed by its subcontractors. This argument is even stronger if the company adheres to a 55 CSR Code containing committing language about the intention to comply with acceptable labour standards. Another argument is that the multinational company is better able to insure against the risk of disaster than the local employer. However, much depends on the exact circumstances and I do not believe that a general legal norm against violations of corporate social responsibility has already matured. 56 The same is true for environmental standards: even though there is a general understanding that global warming must be stopped, this does not imply that individual energy producers, acting at least partly in the public interest, can be held liable for all damage occurring in remote places of the world. This leads me to the second question. If a general legal norm in favour of responsible corporate social behaviour is evolving – and assuming such a norm will come about in the foreseeable future – how is it best accommodated within the legal 57 framework? This accommodation also influences the extent to which liability must be accepted: The doctrinal system at least partly steers the appropriate outcome. It was already seen that invalidity of the contract is not the optimal consequence. Instead, the traditional answer is that distributive concerns (including the taking into 58 account of externalities) are best dealt with by public law, for example through progressive taxation. However, it is clear that this solution will not work across borders: making Wal-Mart pay taxes in the US will not help workers in Bangladesh, just like the German tax collector will not pay for the damage RWE may cause in Peru. It is precisely this aspect that calls for a private law solution in taking 55 56 Much depends on how the CSR-Code is formulated: see Smits (2016) Ind J Global Legal Stud. See for this cautious approach Smits (2016) Ind J Global Legal Stud and for a cautious opposite view Hugh Collins, “Conformity of Goods, the Network Society, and the Ethical Consumer” (2014) 22 European Review of Private Law 619 619-640. Beckers Enforcing Social Responsibility Codes argues in favor of legislative intervention to regulate third-party rights. 57 See in more detail Jan M Smits “What is legal doctrine? On the aims and methods of legal-dogmatic research” in Rob van Gestel, Hans Micklitz & Edward L. Rubin (eds) Rethinking Legal Scholarship (2016) forthcoming. 58 For opposing views of the role of distributive justice in private law see Ernest J Weinrib Corrective Justice (2012) and Martijn W Hesselink CFR and Social Justice (2008). 15 externalities into account. Theoretically, we may then enter a field that lies in between the private and the public, and the corrective and the distributive. The legal instrument best geared towards doing such private law justice across borders would allow a party to seek redress that not only satisfies his own interest, but also contributes to achieving the wider collective goal of preventing the same type of damage to occur in the future. In the contractual setting of a party able to rely on a CSR Code (which, as we saw, will depend on the exact wording of the code and the relationship between the parties), the action to be brought would ideally consist of forcing the company to perform its proclaimed policy in the future. This necessarily entails a shift from damages claims towards injunctions. A claim in tort law will also preferably consist in preventing someone from causing damage instead of in compensating losses already suffered. In brief, the shift necessary to deal with the externalities identified in this contribution is a shift from compensation towards prevention. This naturally requires a judge who is willing to take up this more political role. One firm conclusion can be drawn from this section – externalities of contracts need not only be dealt with through the unpolished technique of declaring a contract unenforceable. The interests of third parties such as labourers and farmers in faraway countries can also be protected by other means. However, expanding the circle of contract law in this way does require a moving away from contractual autonomy. Privately enforced injunctions avoid that negative externalities will occur at all. 5 Instead of a conclusion This contribution is in many ways an exploration. The nice thing about exploring a new area is that one is likely to find new things; the bad thing is that one is not sure how to deal with the newly found. Is it really a new species or only an existing one in disguise? The claim made in the above is that we are indeed facing a new challenge in private law. In our increasingly interconnected world, courts are increasingly confronted with cases in which some type of cross-border justice is sought for violation of labour standards or environmental damage. This invokes the need in both the law of delict and contract to reflect upon the externalities that are to 16 be taken into account. The traditional solution of contract law is to do this primarily by declaring contracts unenforceable, but this is not the optimal solution. Instead, we are in need of private law remedies that prevent a party from doing wrong. This means that a public goal is partly achieved through private law means. Future contract law may therefore no longer be just a matter of the doing of “simple justice 59 between man and man”, as the South African court once called it, but also of including the interests of third parties. With this, the circle is indeed expanding. 59 Sasfin (Pty) Ltd v Beukes 1989 1 SA 1 (A) 9 per Smalberger JA. 17