sold or manumitted, and were collective rather than individual property.&dquo;3 Athens, on the other hand, introduced full commodity slavery as did many other Greek city-states. Great social differentiation among the free citizenry was arrested in this case by the intercession of the &dquo;tyrants&dquo; on behalf of the small and medium farmers. Slaves provided field labor and domestic service but were probably outnumbered by free laborers in agriculture. Athenian armies were mainly composed of medium farmers armed at their own expense, their few slaves tilling the land in their absence. &dquo;The precondition of later Greek ’democracy’ or extended ’oligarchy’ was a self-armed citizen army. &dquo;4 This selfarmed citizen army rested upon a basis of slavery. The limits of Athenian expansion were soon reached. Direct participation by a free citizenry prevented the development of bureaucracy necessary to administer conquered territories. Likewise, the ruling classes of subordinated states were precluded from Athenian citizenship because their interests diverged from those of the class of medium and small farmers which supported the Athenian state. Rome overcame both of these obstacles. A patrician aristocracy dominated the Roman Republic from its inception. Ownership of land became more and more concentrated and the economic base of the small and medium farmer class was continually eroded. Cities were filled with masses devoid of land or any other property. The Roman Republic was the first to unite &dquo;large agrarian property with gangslavery... on a major scale.&dquo;5 Citizenship no longer implied direct participation in government. The massive slave base for the civilian economy released large proportions of the free adult male citizenry for permanent conscription into the armies. The full potential of the slave mode of production was completely released. The predatory militarism of the Roman Republic was its main lever of economic accumulation. War tribute brought lands, tributes and slaves; slaves, and lands supplied the matériel for war.66 Because of the intimate connection between the slave mode of production and economic expansion by conquest, the decline of Rome was foreshadowed by the closing of the frontiers of the Empire. For, unlike the feudal economy which succeeded it, the slave mode of production of Antiquity possessed no natural, internal mechanism of selfreproduction, because its labour-force could never be homeostatically stabilized within the Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism by Perry Anderson (London New Left Books, 1974). REVIEWED BY DAVID JAMES For some three decades, an important theoretical debate in Marxist historiography has focused on central questions concerning the character of feudalism and the transition from it to capitalism.’ Many of the questions raised in this debate have never received adequate answers. These include questions concerning (1) the nature of the feudal mode of production, in particular the social relations peculiar to feudalism and the dynamic internal to feudalism which results from them; (2) the nature of the feudal state, its class character and role with respect to feudal social relations; and (3) explanations for the transition from feudalism to capitalism. Recent works by Perry Anderson bear frontally on the first two of these questions. His Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism and its sequel Lineages of the Absolutist State (London: New Left Books, 1974) comprise the first half of an incredibly ambitious research project covering all of Western history from ancient Greece to the present. The first of these two, and the book which receives primary attention in this review, examines &dquo;the social and political world of classical antiquity,&dquo; the nature of the transition to and the resultant structure and process of European feudalism. The second question concerning political relations and the feudal state is partially addressed by Passages but is more completely confronted by its sequel Lineages. Those who are primarily interested in an examination of the transition from feudalism to capitalism will have to wait for the completion of Anderson’s project. The planned third and fourth volumes will cover the &dquo;great bourgeois revolutions, from the revolt of the Netherlands to the Unification of Germany ; and with the structure of the contemporary capitalist states that eventually emerged from them. &dquo;2 Anderson argues that feudalism was born as a synthesis of two prior modes of production: the ancient or slave mode of production developed in its purest form by Rome; and the primitive, communal mode of the Germanic peoples of Western Europe. Thus, his analysis of feudalism logically required an analysis of classical antiquity and the process which led to the synthesis. The first social formations dominated by the slave mode of production were the city-states of Greece. The Sumarian, Babylonian, Assyrian and Egyptian empires had known slavery, but nowhere did it provide the preponderence of the rural work force. By contrast, citizens of Sparta possessed land which was tilled by &dquo;helots&dquo; owned not by individuals but by the state. This freed the citizenry for military duties and resulted in a high degree of egalitarianism among the politically enfranchised. Spartan development, however, was limited because of the &dquo;undeveloped form&dquo; of slavery represented by helotry; slaves &dquo;could not be bought, system.’ Even though Rome’s economic base was constricting, to the growing imperial state was later added the huge clerical bureaucracy of the Church, both primarily supported by slave labor. Fresh supplies of slaves to till the large estates and maintain the state apparatuses be- and more expensive. In response, slave labor was increasingly converted to permanent ascription to the soil. A new class of dependent producers came more 64 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 emerged: the colonus, a dependent, peasant tenant, tied the primacy of the real over knowledge of the real.&dquo;13 Thus, for Hechtor, if ideas prevented Romans from innovating when the material conditions of their con- to the estate of a landlord and paying rents in kind or cash, or farming on a share-crop basis. The colonus, distinct from slaves and free small-holders, anticipated tinued existence required it, a clear violation of the materialist premise has occurred. Anderson’s argument is less than clear at this point. Some of his statements seem to support Hechtor’s interpretation while others point to material although not exclusively economic conditions - which mitigated against routine technical innovation. 14 To pose the question as one of ideas versus economic conditions is to raise a false dilemma. The Marxist premise, in my view, is not that the economic base completely specifies the superstructure but that it places limits on the variation of those superstructures. Clearly, from the standpoint of the individual, political and ideological structures are no less material than the economic structures which constrain, shape, create the social relations in which the individual participates. Within these limits, ideological (and political) structures enjoy a relative autonomy from the economic base. The &dquo;relative&dquo; modifier of autonomy implies a notion of limits rather than degree of autonomy. When these limits are exceeded, crises result which either bring ideology back within limits or production relations are transformed creating different limits on ideological structures. Erik Wrigh tl5 has given greater conceptual precision to the different meanings incorporated within the Marxist concept of determination which should help dispel some of the confusion around this issue. But how are structural limits imposed on the consciousness of individuals? On this subject Anderson is silent and perhaps justifiably so since his self-assigned task was quite different. An adequate answer to this question is beyond the scope of this article but an outline of an answer can be suggested. 16 Material relations (structures) create the ideational categories through which individuals become subjects. Individuals are reconstituted as subjects - become aware of themselves - through the labels imposed by structures. Thus, an ideological structure is not composed of ideas but is a material structure which evokes those ideas. To choose a contemporary example, the physical separation of mental and manual labor within the organization of production in the factory is an ideological structure which simultaneously creates the need for and legitimates the presence of experts, lower pay for non-experts, etc. Another example is provided by the American South in which political and economic structures enforced racial segregation and created subjects who were either &dquo;black&dquo; or &dquo;white.&dquo; The category &dquo;citizen&dquo; without racial distinction did not exist materially and therefore the probability of people having that image of themselves in their social relations with others was greatly reduced. Thus, the difficulty encountered in creating alliances between black and white members of the working class was structurally determined. Similarly, the pre-feudal political and economic structures of Rome created individuals-subjects who were either Roman citizens and landowners or slave laborers the dominant form of land tenure under feudalism. Anderson argues, however, that the emergence of the colonate did not displace the dominance of slavery and its inherent productive limits and resistance to the implementation of technical innovation. The slavemode of production was based upon the annexation of labor rather than the exploitation of land [under feudalism] or the accumulation of its labor-additive capital [under capitalism] type of growth constituted a structural field ulaltimately resistant to technical innovations, 8 them.$ exclusive of not initially though ... Slaves have no incentive to increase their productivity. What’s more, the availability of slave labor sets the upper limit on the productivity of free labor. Slaves continued to be employed in key sectors, particularly in support of the state apparatuses as well as in the rural agriculture of Italy and Spain. Thus, slavery placed its limits on productivity until the end of the Empire. Technology received no impetus from the conversion of slaves into coloni. The forces of production of Antiquity remained locked at their traditional level.9 In his review of Passages and Lineages, Michael Hechtor concludes that Anderson’s argument is weak at this point.’° Part of his disagreement with Anderson stems from his criticism of Anderson’s use of the con- cept &dquo;mode of production&dquo; and the relation between &dquo;superstructure&dquo; and &dquo;material base&dquo; of which more will be said below. The rest of his disagreement rests upon what I believe to be a misunderstanding of Anderson’s argument. Hechtor states that [t]he major problem with [Anderson’s] analysis is that it cannot easily explain why technological development was not spurred once the cost of slave labor began its precipitous rise.&dquo; Hechtor believes that Anderson primarily attributes this stagnation to an ideology which debases labor and is thereby diverted from labor-saving invention: Why should the Romans’ antipathy toward manual labor and their resulting disinclination to develop labor-saving techniques have persisted despite crucial changes in the very process of pro- duction ? In such an argument, part of the superstructure, the ideology of the ancient mode of production, is not only autonomous from the material base, but actually becomes determinative of production. 12 , Hechtor’s criticism is an expression of one of the central problems of Marxist social theory: what is the relationship between material conditions of existence and social consciousness? In Poulantzas’ phrase, Marxists assert the &dquo;primacy of being over thought; 65 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 and later coloni. Landowners were subjects who were citizens, politicians, and soldiers rather than the supervisors and organizers or labor. To be actively engaged in production was to forfeit the privileges and responsibilites of landowners. The innovations required to save the landowning class, the most crucial of which was the reorganization of that class to give it a more direct role in agriculture, could have occurred only through the transformation of that class. The moral de- his estate in order to give the law to his subjects, it created a joint interest with the peasantry in increasing production in order to provide for the support of private armies. Even the development of the colonus, the dependent producers tied to the land which anticipated feudal relations of production, did not provide the impetus to increase productivity. The state (and the church) still rested upon slave labor as did the provision of household service for the nobility. The colonus was a selfmanaging producer. His principal advantage to the landowner was that he &dquo;alleviated problems of largescale management and supervision.&dquo;18 Thus, the failure to systematically introduce technology in agriculture was not just a matter of choice, but was an &dquo;unreasonable&dquo; strategy for landowners given the political gradation of labor was the ideational expression of material structures which elevated non-producers at the expense of the direct producers in such a way as to make technical and organizational innovation improbable rather than the reverse. It follows that the question of central importance is what were those structures which precluded innovation in agriculture? If Anderson’s argument depends upon the content of ideas per se, namely, the moral degradation of labor, then Hechtor’s criticism is well placed. If the material possibility existed whereby the Roman noble class could have survived by adopting a new form of labor control, the argument that an idea, the moral degradation of labor, prevented such adoption by the entire class is extremely weak. Surely a few daring landlords existed who would have pioneered innovation when threatened by failure and economic ruin. The success of these few would have spurred imitation by other landlords when the survival value of the new form of labor control was demonstrated. Anderson doesn’t indicate the relative importance of ideational factors as compared to structural factors and fails to make explicit arguments which are implicit in Passages and Lineages. A more adequate explanation can be constructed from points he makes in other and economic structures of Rome. What was rational from the point of view of the individual citizen-landowner was irrational from the point of view of the class. Whatever the reasons for Rome’s decline, it left two important legacies. The Church, under the impetus of &dquo;saving souls,&dquo; contributed to the Romanization of Western Europe by introducing Latin to the underlying populations. Until then, about the third century A.D., only the dominant classes had knowledge of Latin; the dominated classes had continued to speak their native languages and were, thereby, denied access to letters and science, Latin being the only written language in the West. The Romance languages resulted from the popularization of Latin. The missionary task of the early Church had the effect of transmitting the cultural and legal forms of Rome to the great majority of the population in the Western half of the Empire and, thus, to the feudal and capitalist future. In regions where the Empire was defeated before this Latinization took place, Roman social forms disappeared with hardly a trace. In the Eastern half of the Empire which already possessed four written languages besides Latin and where Rome never imposed the slave mode of production so thoroughly as in the West, the Roman cultural and legal impact was greatly altered. Feudalism never developed autonomously in the East. Of particular importance in the West was the legacy of Roman civil law. Rome’s was the first legal system to develop the concept of &dquo;absolute property,&dquo; which made the &dquo;novel distinction between mere’possession’ factual control of goods, and ’property’ - full legal title to them.&dquo;’9 Although this concept of private property was to virtually vanish under feudalism, its rebirth during the Renaissance was to play an important role in the transition from feudalism to capitalism. This argument, however, is only sketched in outline form and awaits full development in Anderson’s proposed future volumes. places in these works. First of all, the dominance of slave labor placed constraints on the productivity of free labor. Slave-labour was not in general less productive than free, indeed in some fields it was more so; but it set the pace of both, so that no great divergence ever developed between the two, in a common economic space that excluded the application of culture to technique for inventions.... Technique as premeditated, progressive instrumentation of the natural world by man was incompatible with wholesale assimilation of men to the natural world as its ’speaking instru- - ments’.17 Secondly, and this point is more implicit than explicit in Passages, a unitary sovereignty - the Greek city Imperial Rome - placed the responsibility for supporting the armies on the state. Competition between landlords did not depend on their ability to support armies with the surplus from their estate but on their success in winning high offices in the central state. Thus, landowners had to leave the supervision of production to others. In the case of Rome, the supervisors of slave labor were often slaves themselves. By contrast, the parcellization of sovereignty under feudalism not only required the presence of the lord on states and * * * * * The communal mode of production existing throughout Europe beyond the frontiers of the Empire had been in a process of transformation because of its long-term contact with Rome. Originally, it was 66 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 characterized by an absence of private property in land: here that serfdom first emerged; a manorial system was developed; seigneurial justice was most pronounced; and hierarchical subinfeudation became thickest.23 North of this zone, a free, allodial peasantry with strong communal institutions survived for some time. South of this zone, &dquo;Roman legal conceptions of property as free, heritable and alienable, qualified feudal landed norms from the start. &dquo;24 This line of reasoning, especially as finally developed and qualified in Lineages, provides a provocative, if controversial, explanation for the differential development of feudalism - and capitalism - in Eastern and Western Europe. Anderson’s greatest contribution in Passages is to give the concept of &dquo;feudalism&dquo; a precise theoretical meaning. Whatever the merits of his interpretation of the historical evolution from Antiquity to feudalism and beyond, he has performed a major service in specifying the crucial attributes of European feudalism. The power of his specification follows as a result of his comparative method. Comparison of a large number of feudal and non-feudal societies allowed him to identify key political attributes of feudalism which have not been clearly conceptualized in earlier definitions. 25 Anderson’s concept of feudalism is completely applicable only to Europe: outside of Europe, only Japan had important feudal characteristics contributing, Each year the leading men of a tribe would determine which part of the common soil was to be ploughed and would allocate sections of it to respective clans, who would till and appropriate the fields collectively: the periodic redistributions prevented great disparities of wealth between clans and households, although herds were privately owned and provided the wealth of the leading tribal warriors. There were no peacetime chieftains with authority over a whole people: exceptional military chiefs were elected in time of war.zo Trade with Rome as well as the development of or- ganization capable of contending with Rome militarily led to internal differentiation and increasing stratification within the tribal societies. Land was increasingly allocated to individuals rather than clans. Many Germanic warriors saw service with the Roman Legions and by example or personal intervention contributed political and military organization. The tribes closest to the imperial borders were the most affected; thus, the increasing military pressure exerted upon Rome was to a large extent the &dquo;structural consequence&dquo; of Rome’s &dquo;existence and success.&dquo; Itt is in this context that Anderson describes feudalism as a synthesis of two prior modes of production, both in a state of decline. He emphasizes the notion of synthesis as something more than mere mixture in explaining the advent of feudalism. In fact, the failure of a combination of similar elements in South-East Europe to achieve such a synthesis provides an important counter-example to his central argument .2’ No western-type feudalisms ever developed in the Balkans. What were the elements of the feudal synthesis? Anderson sketches in the outlines of the evolution of several of the most important feudal institutions from their roots in the primitive communal and slave modes of production: the feudal manor from the GalloRoman villa; serfdom from the Roman colonus and from the slow degradation of free German peasants; the fusion of ’vassalage’ (personal homage) and ’benefice’ (grant of land),&dquo; both with roots in Germanic and Roman social forms, to create the ’fief’ (&dquo;a delegated grant of land, vested with juridical and political powers, in exchange for military service&dquo; ); 22 the hybrid legal system with aspects of folk justice emphasizing reciprocal obligation between rulers and ruled as well as codified and written law, an aspect of the Roman to the transformation of &dquo;barbarian&dquo; perhaps, to its amazing capitalist development at a later time. Nevertheless, critical elements were absent in Japan, notable free towns, which prevented an autonomous transition to &dquo; compulsion&dquo; : legacy. Viewing feudalism as a synthesis implies that its character will vary geographically with the strength of the two anterior modes of production which produced the synthesis. [T]he core region of European feudalism was that in which a ’balanced synthesis’ of Roman and Germanic elements occurred: essentially, Northern France capitalism.26 Anderson’s definition of feudalism appears familiar. (1) The peasant producer was bound to the soil, the means of production, by a specific legal relationship: glebae adscripti, literally, bound to the earth. Neither labor nor its product were commodities. (2) Under feudalism, the rights to property in land were conditional rather than absolute as under the Empire or later under capitalism. The peasant cultivators did not own the land, but neither did the lord. While the lord exercised control of his land and subjected the peasantry to his legal jurisdiction, he held rights to the land from a feudal superior only in return for knight-service in time of war. &dquo;The liege lord in his turn would often be the vassal of a feudal superior, and the chain of such dependent tenures linked to military service would extend upwards to the highest peak of the system - in most cases, a monarch - of whom all land could in the ultimate instance be in principle the eminent domain.&dquo;27 (3) The class of feudal lords extracted a surplus from the peasantry by &dquo;politico-legal relations of This extra-economic coercion, taking the form of labour services, rents in kind or customary dues owed to the individual lord by the peasant, was exercised both on the manorial demesne attached directly to the person of the lord, and on the strip tenancies or virgates cultivated by the peasant.28 This combination of political compulsion and economic exploitation personified by the dominance in both by the feudal lord is the basis of the now familiar and zones contiguous to it .... It was 67 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 statement that feudalism is characterized by the unity of political and economic relations. (4) But, while economic and political relations were coterminous at the moment of extraction of the economic surplus, political power was far from unitary as it had been during the Empire. The consequence of such a system was that political sovereignty was never focused in a single centre. The functions of the State were disintegrated in a vertical allocation downwards, at each level of which political and economic relations were, on the other hand, integrated. This parcellization of sovereignty was constitutive of the whole feudal mode of production. 29 self-governing communes, enjoying corpolitical and military autonomy from the nobility and the Church.&dquo;35 This created a dynamic opposition of town and country not possible in earlier modes of production. The importance of the towncountry nexus in explaining the dynamism of feudalism as well as the transition from it to capitalism is an tures were porate area of growing consensus among students of these periods. Some, like Hechtor consider it the sole cause of the feudal dynamic but few argue that towns (and trade) are external to feudalism as did Sweezy during the classic debate of the 1950’s.36 Anderson appears he gives to the influence of neglecting other crucial factors. The third &dquo;structural specificity&dquo; of feudalism identified by Anderson is only a more elaborate statement of the consequences of the parcellization of sovereignty. The resources of monarchs were essentially limited to those of their personal domains as lords. They enjoyed no direct access to the population as a whole; feudal relations between the king and his noble vassals mediated this access. Extra-suzerain exactions from the noble class (e.g. taxes) were subject to the collective consent of the nobility. Thus, the absence of a powerful integrating force at the top of the feudal hierarchy posed a problem for its survival. &dquo;A complete fragmentation of sovereignty was incompatible with the class unity of the nobility itself, for the anarchy implied by it was necessarily disruptive of the whole mode of production on which their privileges rested.&dquo;3’ Throughout the sequel Lineages, this theme is replayed time and again to explain the success or failure of feudal social formations in forming absolutist states. The parcellization of sovereignty mitigated against the formation of a strong, central bureaucracy. The inherent anarchy of the noble class was given greatest expression when the nobility was strong; thus, Poland was partitioned by absolutist states with noble classes united by strong monarchs.38 Peasant revolts always inspired a transient unity among the nobility. A unity imposed from above was often more permanent but stability was far from guaranteed. The centralized political authority of Rome or the Asian Empires was always more stable. The dynamism of feudalism was reflected in the cultural achievements and agrarian progress of the High Middle Ages (about 1150-1300 A.D.). By the middle of the fourteenth century, however, feudalism was in crisis. Anderson argues that the &dquo;basic determinant&dquo; of ’seizure’ of the mechanisms of the crisis lay in a correct in the emphasis towns while not Finally, the articulation of these aspects of the feudal mode gave rise to three &dquo;structural specificities of Western feudalism.&dquo; All three of these features, and in contrast to Hechtor’s reading of Anderson, are important determinants of the &dquo;dynamic&dquo; of the feudal mode of production .30 &dquo;Firstly, the survival of communal village lands and peasant allods from pre-feudal modes of production, although not generated by the latter, was not incompatible with it either.&dquo;3’ This &dquo;scalar structure of property&dquo; had two aspects: the separation between manorial property, on the one hand, and village communal lands and allods held by peasants outside of the direct control of a feudal superior on the other; and secondly, a separation within the manor itself between &dquo;the lord’s demesne, directly organized by his stewards and tilled by his villeins, and the peasant virgates, from which he received a complementary surplus but in which the organization and control of production was in the hands of the villeins themselves.&dquo;32 Scalar property created a margin in which a portion of improved productivity could accrue to the direct producer. A structure was thereby established which, within limits, rewarded technical innovation. In fact, agricultural productivity increased dramatically during the medieval period. In order to realize the maximum surplus from peasant labor, the nobility introduced some organizational rationality (e.g. crop rotation) and fostered the introduction of new techniques, notably the water-mill. Nevertheless, the small space allowed the direct producer to realize the fruits of his/her own labor was probably the most important factor affecting productivity. The greater productivity of feudalism in Western Europe, which had a smaller proportion of the peasant’s labor devoted to the lord’s demesne as compared to Eastern Europe, is important suggestive evidence in support of this contention.33 &dquo; reproduction.&dquo;39 Demographic expansion coupled with the diminishing returns from extensive rural expansion, given the level of the forces of production, Secondly, parcellized sovereignty provided an growth of medieval towns. at the core of the crisis. The urban economy also encountered obstacles to its continued development. Silver, the basic medium of exchange, became increasingly scarce. Part of the reason for this scarcity was again the low level of development of the forces of was autonomous space for the As was the case with peasant allods and communal urban commodity production predated feudalism. &dquo;But the feudal mode of production nevertheless was the first to permit it an autonomous lands, production. Deep shaft mining was technically impractical and silver-mining almost vanished by the end of the fourteenth century. The shortage of metals led to a spiralling inflation and a widening gap between the prices for urban manufactures and agricultural goods. development within a natural-agrarian economy.&dquo;34 The towns and cities of Antiquity and of the Asian Empires were subordinated to a central political authority. &dquo;By contrast the paradigmatic mediaeval towns of Europe which practised trade and manufac68 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 of the mode of production. The result was a decline in seigneurial revenues, which in turn unleashed an unprecedented wave of warfare as knights everywhere tried to recoup their fortunes with plunder.4° The second issue concerns the causal relationship between base and superstructure or, in other words, how the mode of production determines politics and ideology. Clearly, the wide variety of superstructural forms which coexist with the same or similar economic base precludes any simple one-to-one causal path from the base to the superstructure. As has been argued above, a more adequate claim is that the economic structure places limits on the range of possible variation of the forms of state and ideology which are compatible with it. There is less controversy concerning the claim concerning limits than there is with regard to the first issue mentioned above. Nevertheless, the absence of a general Marxist theory of politics at the mode of production level has meant that the major dynamic of societal transformation has, by default, had to be a narrowly conceived economic one. The inclusion of political elements in explanations of the transformations of concrete social formations has had an ad hoc quality and often appears to substitute a variety of historicism for the economistic bias of the more general treatments of the problem of transformation. Recent contributions to the debate on the transition from feudalism to capitalism have tended to retain this economic one-sidedness despite Hilton’s early (1952) warning that &dquo;political conditions need closer attention. &dquo;44 To these endogenous causes of the crisis was added the devastation of the Black Death; perhaps 40 percent of the population perished by 1400 creating a serious labor shortage. The increasing pressure from the nobility &dquo;to reinforce servile conditions and make the producing class pay the costs of the crisis now met with wild, violent resistance ...&dquo;4’ Massive peasant revolts swept through Europe. The ultimate consequences of these revolts and their defeat were very different in Western and Eastern Europe. The presence of viable towns in the West had already led to a weakening of feudal relations due to market relationships and peasant flight to the urban areas. Additionally, many towns in the West actively supported peasant rebellions. Although all peasant revolts were eventually defeated, the crisis was &dquo;the turning-point in the dissolution of serfdom in the West.&dquo;42 Because of the weakness of the towns in the East, the crisis had the opposite consequences: the famous &dquo;second serfdom&dquo; resulted with an increasing degradation of the peasantry. But this is the main story of the sequel. In Lineages, Anderson develops these arguments in a case by case examination of the most important feudal formations. The most penetrating criticism of Passages and Lineages has come from reviewers who disagree with Anderson’s use of the concept &dquo;mode of production.&dquo; For example, Hechtor and others object to the inclusion of &dquo;superstructural elements,&dquo; namely, parcellization of sovereignty, within its definition.43 These criticisms appear to stem from a misunderstanding of Anderson’s general theoretical usage of the concept of mode of production as well as its specific application in the case of feudalism. Because I expect that other readers will misunderstand his approach and will therefore tend to underate the theoretical importance of his work, the remainder of this review will be devoted to a clarification of Anderson’s theory and how it appears to have advantages over what is perhaps the most common usage among Marxists of the concept of mode of production. There are two inter-related issues here which are often confused in debates on this topic. The first concerns the level of abstraction with which it is possible to theorize about superstructure; that is, can the superstructure be analyzed at the same level of abstraction as the mode of production or must theoretical statements about superstructure be confined to the social formation level. To make the contrast more explicit, can a general theory of the feudal state be constructed in a fashion similar to a general theory of the feudal mode of production or must we confine our analyses of feudal politics to concrete social formations dominated by the feudal mode of production? Anderson’s theory of feudalism and the slave mode of production is of the first type. The inclusion of parcellization of sovereignty within the definition of feudalism is a theoretical statement about political structure at the level Anderson’s Passages and Lineages are first attempts to correct this theoretical lacuna. It is for Marxists to assert that extra-economic coercion is required to separate the direct producers from the economic surplus in pre-capitalist modes of production. commonplace The specificity of that extra-economic coercion is determined by a particular concatenation of political and economic relations, namely, parcellized sovereignty and scalar property in the case of feudalism. Thus, Anderson appears justified in asserting that &dquo;precapitalist modes of production cannot be defined except via their political, legal and ideological superstructures since these are what determine the type of extra-economic coercion that specifies them. &dquo;45 Anderson’s formulation is convincing because it both accounts for the diversity of feudalism across Europe and provides a plausible explanation of its development thereafter. Thus, the &dquo;proof&dquo; of the theory offered in Passages is to be found in Lineages: the explanation for the &dquo;second serfdom&dquo; in Eastern Europe, the partition of Poland, the emergence of the Absolutist state are examples. No other single theory of which I am aware has such wide explanatory power. Even so, perhaps the adequacy of Anderson’s approach cannot be fully evaluated until the arrival of his promised third volume which will address the question of the transition from feudalism to capitalism. Of course, works of such scope as Anderson’s are not without fault. Some may feel that Anderson neglects the economic base in his attempt to incorporate the political. Certainly it lacks the depth of theoretical insight and historical detail into the dynamics of the feudal economy that one can find in Witold Kula’s An Economic Theory of the Feudal System.46 In fact, I find 69 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015 Kula’s book to be a valuable compliment to Anderson’s work in that it examines the implications of scalar property within the Polish historical context while pre- ticular societies are unlikely to be satisfied with Anderson’s brief sketches .41 On the other hand, non-specialists will require the assistance of a good historical atlas in order to follow Anderson’s arguments concerning the inter-relationships of the myriad political units involved. He provides no maps. Nevertheless, Anderson supposing (without mentioning) parcellized sovereignty. Surely Anderson will have provided a great service if his work inspires an analysis of feudal politics which is as detailed as Kula’s analysis of the feudal has confronted the &dquo;theoretical problems&dquo; of historical materialism with the &dquo;empirical issues posed by historians&dquo; as was his purpose and surely to the advantage of his readers. David James economy. One critical omission from Passages is an adequate explanation for the closing of the borders of the Roman Empire. Why did Rome at its height abandon further expansion which, Anderson contends, was crucial for its long-run survival? And as Keith Thomas has noted, Dept. of Sociology University of Wisconsin Madison, Wisconsin specialists acquainted with the complexity of parNOTES 1. See Rodney Hilton, ed., The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism (London: New Left Books, 1976); Karl Marx, PreCapitalist Economic Formations, introduced by Eric J. Hobsbawm, (New York: International Publishers, 1964). 2. Lineages, p. 11. 3. Passages, p. 36. feudalism was "politically decentralized" and that the feudal lord held certain "judicial or quasi-judicial functions in relation to the population" but neither systematically developed the implications of these aspects of their definition. Hilton (ed.), op. cit., p. 34. 26. Lineages, pp. 435-461. 27. Passages, p. 148. 4. Ibid., p. 33. 5. Ibid., p. 60. 6. Ibid., p. 62. 7. Ibid., p. 76. 8. Ibid., p. 79. 9. Ibid., p. 95. 10. Michael Hechtor, "Review Essay: Lineages of the Capitalist State," American Journal of sociology, 82 (March, 1977), 1063-1064. 11. Ibid., p. 1064. 12. Ibid. 13. Nicos Poulantzas, Political Power and Social Classes (London: New Left Books, 1973), 12. 14. See Passages, p. 27. 15. Enk Wright, Classes, Crises and the State (London- New Left 28. Ibid., p. 147. 29. Ibid., p. 148. 30. Hechtor, op. cit., pp. 1066-1067. 31. Passages, p. 148. 32. Ibid., p. 149. 33. See Ibid., pp. 260-262 for some of the qualifications which must be given this interpretation. 34. Ibid., p. 150. 35. Ibid. 36. Hechtor, p. 1067. Paul M. Sweezy, "A Critique," The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism: A Symposium, Maurice Dobb and others, (New York: Science and Society, 1967), pp. 1-20. Sweezy’s article originally appeared in Science and Society, Spring 1950, and is also included in Hilton, loc. cit. 37. Passages, pp. 151-152. 38. Lineages, pp. 236-359. 39. Passages, p. 197. 40. Ibid., p 200. 41. Ibid., p. 202. 42. Ibid., p. 204. 43. For example, see Hechtor, p. 1063-1064 and Theda Skocpol and Mary Fulbrook, untitled review of Passages and Lineages, Journal of Development Studies 13 (April, 1977), 290-295 44. Hilton, ed., op. cit., p. 154. 45. Lineages, p. 404. 46. (London: New Left Books, 1976). 47. Keith Thomas, "Jumbo History," New York Review of Books, 22 (April, 17, 1977), pp. 26-30. Books, 1978). 16. depen- dent My approach to the problem follows that suggested by Louis Althusser, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses," in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971). 17. Passages, p. 27-28. 18. Ibid., p. 95. 19. Ibid., p. 67. 20. Ibid., p. 107. 21. Ibid., pp. 265-293. 22. Ibid., p. 139. 23. Ibid., pp. 154-155. 24. Ibid., p. 155. 25. For example, Sweezy seems to accept Dobb’s definition that theory’s limiting assumptions, analytical ambiguities and empirical anomalies, Thurow has added an addi- Generating Inequality: Mechanisms of Distribution in the U.S. Economy by Lester Thurow (New York Basic Books, 1975) tional nail to the coffin of neo-classical economics. In the neo-classical paradigm an individual’s income is determined by their productivity (i.e., the marginal productivity of the factors of production the individual possesses). Not so, Thurow persuasively argues. An individual’s earnings are determined by the distribution of job opportunities (and a corresponding rigid wage distribution associated with these jobs) and by one’s position in the &dquo;labor queue.&dquo; Employers rank $5.95. REVIEWED BY ANDREW ZIMBALIST In certain respects, Lester Thurow’s Generating Inequality is to the marginal productivity of wages what the Cantabrigians are to the neo-classical theory of capital. In exposing the marginal productivity 70 Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at NANYANG TECH UNIV LIBRARY on April 26, 2015
Puede agregar este documento a su colección de estudio (s)
Iniciar sesión Disponible sólo para usuarios autorizadosPuede agregar este documento a su lista guardada
Iniciar sesión Disponible sólo para usuarios autorizados(Para quejas, use otra forma )