STREAM READINGS Gender, Poverty and Social Inclusion GLOBAL SCHOLARS ACADEMY | BUDAPEST, HUNGARY | JULY 18 - 22, 2022 OVERVIEW Gender, Poverty and Social Inclusion Faculty • • Ratna Kapur (United Kingdom) Queen Mary University of London Lynette Chua (Singapore) National University of Singapore Description In this stream we explore the concepts of gender, poverty, and social inclusion through a conversation on the liberal individual subject, which rests at the core of the international human rights discourse. We discuss how the subject is produced through prevailing assumptions about gender, sexuality, race, class and culture that operate along an axis of inclusion and exclusion. The analysis is illustrated through case studies on anti-trafficking tourism as humanitarianism, as well as feminist and LGBTQ advocacy struggles and state repression in relation to the family. STREAM READING | OVERVIEW TABLE OF CONTENTS Gender, Poverty and Social Inclusion Source Pages Part One: Overview UN Secretary-General, Integrating the Gender Perspective into the Work of United Nations Human Rights Treaty Bodies: Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc HRI/MC/1998/6 (3 September 1998) 1 Article 7.3 of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 1998 1 Hartman, S. (1997) Scenes of Subjection- Terror, Slavery, and Self-Marking in 19th Century America. Excerpts from pp. 96-98 1-3 Brooks, G. The Lovers of the Poor, Selected Poems. Available at poetryfoundation.org/poems/43317/ the-lovers-of-the-poor 4-6 Marks, S. (2009) “Human Rights and the Bottom Billion” 1 European Human Rights Law Review 37-49. Excerpts from pp. 37-45 7-9 Bhambra, G.K. ( 2021) “Narrating Inequality, Eliding Empire” 72 British Journal of Sociology 69-78. Excerpts from pp. 69-72 10-12 Part Two: Close Reading Classical / Contemporary Texts - Butler, J. (1999). Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Excerpts from pp. 163, 172185 13-14 Spivak, G. (1998). “Can the Subaltern Speak?” In Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, C. Nelson and L. Grossberg, eds. Excerpts from pp. Excerpts pp. 66, 75-83, 102. 15-17 Jackson, Z. (2020) Becoming Human: Matter and Meaning in an Anti-Black World. Excerpts from pp. 7-9 18-19 Fineman M.A. (2008) “The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition” 20(1) Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 1. Excerpts from pp. 8-12. 20-22 Part Three: Contemporary Case Studies A. Anti-Trafficking Tourism as Humanitarianism Bernstein, E. (2018) Brokered Subjects: Sex, Trafficking and the Politics of Freedom. Excerpts from pp. 107-119 23-26 Chuang, J. (2010) “Rescuing Trafficking from Ideological Capture: Prostitution Reform and Antitrafficking Law and Policy” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 158, pp. 1655-1728. Excerpts from 1657, 1701-1703 UNODC. (25 Nov. 2009). Human Trafficking Fuels Violence Against Women. Available at: https://www. unodc.org/unodc/en/frontpage/2009/November/human-trafficking-fuels-violence-against-women. html B. Feminist/LGBT Advocacy and State Repression -Wang, D. 2020. “Jia, as in Guojia: building the Chinese Family into a Filial Nationalist Project” 5 (1) China Law & Society Review 1-32. Excerpts from pp. 2, 17- 20 STREAM READING | TABLE OF CONTENTS 27-28 29 30-32 ___________________________________________________________________________ UN Secretary-General, Integrating the Gender Perspective into the Work of United Nations Human Rights Treaty Bodies: Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc HRI/MC/1998/6 (3 September 1998) ___________________________________________________________________________ The term ‘gender’ refers to the socially constructed roles of women and men that are ascribed to them on the basis of their sex, in public and in private life. The term ‘sex’ refers to the biological and physical characteristics of women and men. Gender roles are contingent on a particular socio-economic, political and cultural context and are affected by other factors, including age, race, class and ethnicity. Gender roles are learned and vary widely within and between cultures. As social constructs, they can change. Gender roles shape women's access to rights, resources and opportunities. ___________________________________________________________________________ Article 7.3 of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 1998 _________________________________________________________________________ In international treaty law the only binding definition of gender is under Article 7.3 of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 1998 which states as follows: “For the purposes of this Statute, it is understood that the term ‘gender’ refers to the two sexes, male and female, within the context of society. The term ‘gender’ does not indicate any meaning different from the above” (w.e.f. 2000) ___________________________________________________________________________ Hartman, S. (1997) Scenes of Subjection- Terror, Slavery, and Self-making in 19th Century America. Excerpts from pp. 96-98 ___________________________________________________________________________ *96 Cobb, concerned with the neglect of sexual injury and the failure to protect slave women from rape in slave law, slated that “although worthy of consideration by legislators,” it need not cause undue concern because “the occurrence of such an offense is almost unheard of; and the known lasciviousness of the negro, renders the possibility of its occurrence very remote.”62 As the black male’s nature made “rape too often an occurrence,” the black female’s imputed lasciviousness removed it entirely from consideration. It is not simply fortuitous that gender emerges in relation to violence—that is, gender is constituted in terms of negligible and unredressed injury and the propensity for violence. The en-gendering of race, as it is refracted through Cobb’s scale of subjective value, entails the denial of sexual violation as a form of injury while asserting the prevalence of sexual violence due to the rapacity of the Negro. While Cobb’s consideration of sexual violation initially posits gender differences within the enslaved community in terms of female victim and male perpetrator, ultimately the “strong passions” of the Negro—in this instance, lust and lasciviousness—ultimately annul such distinctions and concomitantly any concerns about “the violation of the person of a female slave.” Since, according to Cobb, blacks were endowed less with sexuality than with criminality, they were in 1 need of discipline rather than protection, since as sexual subjects they were beyond the pale of the law and outside the boundaries of the decent and the nameable. In George v. State, George, a slave, was indicted for rape under a statute making it a crime to have sex with a child under ten years of age. The Mississippi Supreme Court overturned a lower-court ruling that convicted George for the rape of a female slave under ten years old and sentenced him to death by hanging. The attorney for George cited Cobb’s Law of Slavery in his argument before the court, declaring that “the crime or rape does not exist in this State between African slaves. Our laws recognize no marital rights as between slaves; their sexual intercourse is left to be regulated by their owners. The regulations of law, as to the white race, on the subject of sexual intercourse, do not and cannot, for obvious reasons, apply to slaves; their intercourse is promiscuous, and the violation of a female slave by a male slave would be mere assault and battery.”63 According to George’s attorney, the sexual arrangements of the captive community were so different from those of the dominant order that they were beyond the reach of the law and best left to the regulation of slave owners. The Mississippi Supreme Court concluded that based on a “careful examination of our legislation on this subject, we are satisfied that there is no act which embraces either the attempted or actual commission of a rape by a slave on a female slave. . . . Masters and slaves cannot be governed by the same common system of laws: so different are their positions, rights, and duties.” The lower court’s judgment was reversed, the indictment quashed, and the defendant discharged on the grounds that “this indictment cannot be sustained, either at common law or under our statutes. It charges no offence known to either system.” The opinion held that slaves were not subject to the protection of common law and that earlier cases in which whites were prosecuted for the murder of slaves under common law were founded on “unmeaning twaddle . . . ‘natural law,’ ‘civilization *97 and Christian enlightenment,’ in amending propio vigore, the rigor of the common law.” If subjectivity is calculated in accordance with degrees of injury and sexual violation is not within the scope of offenses that affected slave existence, what are the consequences of this repression and disavowal in regard to gender and sexuality? Does this callous circumscription of black sentience define the condition of the slave female, or does it challenge the adequacy of gender as a way of making sense of the inscription and exploitation of captive bodies? Put differently, what place does the enslaved female occupy within the admittedly circumscribed scope of black existence or slave personhood? As a consequence of this disavowal of offense, is her scope of existence even more restricted? Does she exist exclusively as property? Is she insensate? What are the repercussions of this construction of person for the meaning of “woman”? . . . To return to the central issues, the law’s selective recognition of slave personhood in regard to issues of injury and protection failed to acknowledge the matter of sexual violation, specifically rape, and thereby defined the identity of the slave female by the negation of sentience, an invulnerability to sexual violation, and the negligibility of her injuries. However, it is important that the decriminalization of rape not be understood as dispossessing the enslaved of female gender, but in terms of differential production of gendered identity or, more specifically, the adequacy or meaning of gender in this context. Therefore, what is at stake here is not maintaining gender as an identitarian category but rather examining gender formation in relation to property relations, the sexual economy of slavery, and the calculation of injury, 2 The weighing of person and property—the limited recognition of the slave as person, to the extent that it did not interfere with the full enjoyment of the slave as *98 thing—endowed the enslaved with limited protections and made them vulnerable to injury, precisely because the recognition of person and the calibration of subjectivity were consonant with the imperatives of the institution. The protection of property (defined narrowly by work capacity and the value of capital), the public good (the maintenance of black subordination), and the maintenance and reproduction of the institution of slavery determined the restricted scope of personhood and the terms of recognition.64 These concerns also governed the regulation and nullification of mothering and the protections extended to white women in order to control their sexual conduct and consolidate black subordination.65 The affiliation of sexuality, property, and injury and the particular determination of “offences to existence” and alienable or extricable features of the slave person are illuminated by the negation of black parenting and the law’s protection of white women. 3 ___________________________________________________________________________ Brooks, G. (1963) The Lovers of the Poor, Selected Poems ___________________________________________________________________________ arrive. The Ladies from the Ladies’ Betterment League Arrive in the afternoon, the late light slanting In diluted gold bars across the boulevard brag Of proud, seamed faces with mercy and murder hinting Here, there, interrupting, all deep and debonair, The pink paint on the innocence of fear; Walk in a gingerly manner up the hall. Cutting with knives served by their softest care, Served by their love, so barbarously fair. Whose mothers taught: You’d better not be cruel! You had better not throw stones upon the wrens! Herein they kiss and coddle and assault Anew and dearly in the innocence With which they baffle nature. Who are full, Sleek, tender-clad, fit, fiftyish, a-glow, all Sweetly abortive, hinting at fat fruit, Judge it high time that fiftyish fingers felt Beneath the lovelier planes of enterprise. To resurrect. To moisten with milky chill. To be a random hitching-post or plush. To be, for wet eyes, random and handy hem. Their guild is giving money to the poor. The worthy poor. The very very worthy And beautiful poor. Perhaps just not too swarthy? perhaps just not too dirty nor too dim Nor—passionate. In truth, what they could wish Is—something less than derelict or dull. Not staunch enough to stab, though, gaze for gaze! God shield them sharply from the beggar-bold! The noxious needy ones whose battle’s bald Nonetheless for being voiceless, hits one down. But it’s all so bad! and entirely too much for them. The stench; the urine, cabbage, and dead beans, Dead porridges of assorted dusty grains, The old smoke, heavy diapers, and, they’re told, Something called chitterlings. The darkness. Drawn Darkness, or dirty light. The soil that stirs. The soil that looks the soil of centuries. And for that matter the general oldness. Old Wood. Old marble. Old tile. Old old old. 4 Not homekind Oldness! Not Lake Forest, Glencoe. Nothing is sturdy, nothing is majestic, There is no quiet drama, no rubbed glaze, no Unkillable infirmity of such A tasteful turn as lately they have left, Glencoe, Lake Forest, and to which their cars Must presently restore them. When they’re done With dullards and distortions of this fistic Patience of the poor and put-upon. They’ve never seen such a make-do-ness as Newspaper rugs before! In this, this “flat,” Their hostess is gathering up the oozed, the rich Rugs of the morning (tattered! the bespattered. . . .) Readies to spread clean rugs for afternoon. Here is a scene for you. The Ladies look, In horror, behind a substantial citizeness Whose trains clank out across her swollen heart. Who, arms akimbo, almost fills a door. All tumbling children, quilts dragged to the floor And tortured thereover, potato peelings, softEyed kitten, hunched-up, haggard, to-be-hurt. Their League is allotting largesse to the Lost. But to put their clean, their pretty money, to put Their money collected from delicate rose-fingers Tipped with their hundred flawless rose-nails seems . . . They own Spode, Lowestoft, candelabra, Mantels, and hostess gowns, and sunburst clocks, Turtle soup, Chippendale, red satin “hangings,” Aubussons and Hattie Carnegie. They Winter In Palm Beach; cross the Water in June; attend, When suitable, the nice Art Institute; Buy the right books in the best bindings; saunter On Michigan, Easter mornings, in sun or wind. Oh Squalor! This sick four-story hulk, this fibre With fissures everywhere! Why, what are bringings Of loathe-love largesse? What shall peril hungers So old old, what shall flatter the desolate? Tin can, blocked fire escape and chitterling And swaggering seeking youth and the puzzled wreckage Of the middle passage, and urine and stale shames And, again, the porridges of the underslung And children children children. Heavens! That Was a rat, surely, off there, in the shadows? Long And long-tailed? Gray? The Ladies from the Ladies’ 5 Betterment League agree it will be better To achieve the outer air that rights and steadies, To hie to a house that does not holler, to ring Bells elsetime, better presently to cater To no more Possibilities, to get Away. Perhaps the money can be posted. Perhaps they two may choose another Slum! Some serious sooty half-unhappy home!— Where loathe-love likelier may be invested. Keeping their scented bodies in the center Of the hall as they walk down the hysterical hall, They allow their lovely skirts to graze no wall, Are off at what they manage of a canter, And, resuming all the clues of what they were, Try to avoid inhaling the laden air. 6 ___________________________________________________________________________ Marks, S. (2009) “Human Rights and the Bottom Billion” 1 European Human Rights Law Review pp. 37-49. Excerpts from pp. 37, 38, 39, 41, 42, 43, 44, 45 ___________________________________________________________________________ (p.37) Global poverty is today widely discussed as a human rights issue. But how should it be approached? In addressing this question, the present paper examines the influential work of Paul Collier, Thomas Pogge, and the Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights. While each contributes significantly to our understanding, it is argued that none attaches sufficient importance to the relationality and systematicity of privilege and deprivation. In his recent book The Bottom Billion development economist Paul Collier writes of the billion or so people who live in the world's very poorest countries. The statistics for these places are grim even by the standards of states that are not affluent: average life expectancy is 50, as against 67 elsewhere in the developing world; infant mortality is 14 percent, as against 4 per cent in other developing countries; and the proportion of children with symptoms of long-term malnutrition is 36 per cent, while in other developing countries it is 20 per cent. But for Collier the point about these societies which justifies concentrating on their distinctive problems is not just that they are exceptionally poor; it is also that the prognosis for them is exceptionally bleak, inasmuch as their economies are failing to grow. Indeed, for much of the time since the 1980s their economies have been in accelerating decline, with the result that today they are about where they were in 1970. Collier identifies 58 countries as being in this situation, most, though not all, of them in Africa, and he argues that it is they which today constitute the “real challenge of development”. Rather than thinking, as we have been accustomed to do, in terms of a rich world and a poor world, he contends that we need to start thinking in terms of a rich world, a developing world and a world that is failing to develop, home to his eponymous “bottom billion”. (p.38) ……..Perhaps the most conspicuous context for discussions of global poverty within human rights circles is the effort by the Office of the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights to elaborate and promote a “human rights approach to poverty reduction”,….. Yet the idea that human rights may have something to do with poverty and its reduction is certainly not confined to this project of the OHCHR; discussions on the subject unfold within many settings, including academic literature. In a further section of the paper, I shall highlight the writings of philosopher Thomas Pogge on the “human rights of the global poor”. Pogge's scholarship is instructive because he helps us to see what is missing in the analyses of both Collier and the OHCHR. Alongside their considerable contributions, it becomes apparent that they leave out of account the role of international law in establishing the very conditions within which poverty can occur……… The bottom billion …..Collier's central claim is that the bottom billion countries are not just the poorest but also differ from the rest of the developing world in having economies that are failing to grow, the first half of his book is devoted to explaining why this is so. In his assessment, the explanation is that bottom billion countries are caught in a series of traps. He does not argue that poverty is itself a trap; rather, the traps have to do with features of the countries concerned……. 7 *39...Collier plainly believes that international law can play a role in helping the bottom billion countries to escape from the traps in which they are caught, but it needs recasting and supplementing. His recommendations engage long-running debates over humanitarian intervention, investment protection and the democratic entitlement, among many other things…Yet if the bottom billion are to be helped to escape, it is surely necessary to understand how these particular circumstances come to constitute traps--what it is that makes it possible for them to operate in this manner. One aspect of this concerns international law……. *41 Human rights and poverty reduction……. …………[T]he Office of the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights began in 2001 to consider the elaboration of guidelines on a “human rights approach to poverty alleviation”. This was seen to dovetail with the broader effort, launched by the UN Secretary-General in 1997, to integrate human rights into all the Organization's activities, including its activities in the sphere of development. Draft Guidelines on a Human Rights Approach to Poverty Reduction were prepared in 2002, and in 2004 a report was issued setting out the conceptual framework which informed the Guidelines and which, in turn, they were intended to promote.9 It is on this report, entitled “Human Rights and Poverty Reduction: A Conceptual Framework”,….. The report starts by noting that the move to integrate human rights into poverty reduction strategies, as advocated and elaborated within development agencies, draws on the very considerable legitimacy of human rights. This is seen to derive not only from the moral authority of norms that are rooted in considerations of human dignity, but also from the fact that human rights norms are widely endorsed in all regions of the world, and that all states of the world are parties to at least one human rights treaty……. *42 In this approach, the central issue is not just economic growth, but the extent to which each individual has command over economic resources…….At the same time, and more generally, what is significant is the basic idea that poverty reduction is not simply a matter of charity, prudence or good practice, but can instead be claimed as a right that imposes legal duties on governments and others…… ……….Collier adopts an approach that stresses economic growth, and that considers global poverty in largely aggregative terms. His analysis also has a location-specific dimension that sits uneasily with the universality of human rights. In contrast, the OHCHR insists that human rights have multifaceted relevance to poverty reduction, and that approaches to development must take into account a range of rights-related matters, among them the principle of nondiscrimination……. At another level, however, these two texts may not be so very far apart. One thing, at any rate, that both share is the sense of global poverty as a problem with its roots largely in domestic factors. That is to say, the issue for both Collier and the OHCHR is bad policies, despotic leaders, and corrupt elites, along with lack of accountability, lack of expertise, deficient public institutions, geographical disadvantage, and persistent civil strife…… *43 The human rights of the global poor The OHCHR's report exemplifies one approach to global poverty as a human rights issue. Another approach can be illustrated with reference to the work of Thomas Pogge. In a series of writings Pogge has put forward the argument that, in the context of persistent, widespread and often life-threatening poverty, human rights are both “recognized and violated by international law”. By this he means that the international recognition and protection of rights, including 8 rights to the basic necessities for life, coexist with a normative and institutional order that systematically undermines those rights so that at the same time international law contributes to their violation. In defending this claim, he insists that poverty cannot be explained by reference to national or local factors alone. Apart from other considerations, the “domestic poverty thesis”,11 as he calls it, leaves out of account the extent to which current inequalities are historical, and especially colonial, legacies…… *44…..For all the attention lavished in development economics on the phenomenon of the resource curse, Pogge observes that the global order is standardly held “fixed as a given background”;14 the role is rarely considered of the “global rules that grant the resource privilege to any group in power, irrespective of its domestic illegitimacy”.15 I referred earlier to the way Collier's “trap of being landlocked with bad neighbours” is mediated by international legal norms, and here we see that the same applies to his “natural resource trap”. Indeed, the same applies to each of the traps in which the bottom billion countries are caught; each can be seen as partly set by international law if only we choose to look. Pogge's claim is that the international order which includes these norms is effectively imposed on the global poor, and that this imposition “constitutes a massive violation of the human right to basic necessities--a violation for which the governments and electorates of the more powerful countries bear primary responsibility”….. *45….Citing the current toll of an historically unprecedented 18 million poverty-related deaths per year, he contends that today's global poverty represents “arguably the largest [human rights] violation ever committed in human history”. In analytical terms, he contends that this violation implicates even negative obligations. That is to say, the issue is not just a failure to prevent avoidable harm, but an active contribution to its incidence; it is not just the lack of aid, but the ongoing need for aid. As he explains, “the poor are systematically impoverished by present institutional arrangements and have been so impoverished for a long time during which our advantage and their disadvantage have been compounded”. It follows for him that the collective obligation of the rich world is to change those arrangements, and his work includes discussion of possible reform initiatives. …. How does this analysis compare with the report by the OHCHR? Again it is important to note the significant differences in their respective projects. The OHCHR addresses development agencies, urging them to take into account human rights and, in so doing, to pay particular attention to a series of fundamental norms, principles and ideas drawn from international human rights law and the experience of the institutions associated with it. For his part, Pogge addresses the world at large, and particularly people in rich countries, trying to make them aware of how global poverty constitutes a violation of human rights and how they and their governments are themselves complicit in that violation. At the same time, there is obviously shared subject matter insofar as both write about global poverty as an issue of human rights. In this regard, it is notable that, while the OHCHR leaves aside the question of how the international system may contribute to the production of poverty, Pogge takes that as his central theme……Pogge leaves some important questions unanswered. What are the dynamics of the process he describes? How is it that disadvantage and advantage are compounded? And is this outcome purely fortuitous, or are there systemic logics at work? ...... p.49 ....Collier's analysis is notably lacking in attention to the relational dimensions of global poverty. This is epitomised in the notion of the “bottom billion” itself--a number that is relative (to the top or next billion), and yet, as a concept, curiously autonomous and nonrelational: these poorest of the poor are simply there, a feature on our analytical landscape. 9 And just as in his work all eyes are on the bottom billion and what we might do to help them, so too in human rights circles the focus is on the victims and on the rights and correlative obligations they may assert. Those who benefit from current arrangements remain comfortably out of view. Bhambra, G.K. ( 2021) “Narrating Inequality, Eliding Empire” 72 British Journal of Sociology 69-78. Excerpts from pp. 69, 71, 72 ___________________________________________________________________________ *69 Piketty opens Capital and Ideology—the successor volume to the blockbuster Capital in the Twenty-First Century—with the following line: “Every human society must justify its inequalities: unless reasons for them are found, the whole political and social edifice stands in danger of collapse” (2020, p. 1). It is a curious formulation, since it presupposes both that inequalities can be justified and that the “political and social edifice” is itself built independently of its legitimation. Piketty goes on to write, “every ideology, no matter how extreme it may seem in its defense of inequality, expresses a certain idea of social justice” (2020, p. 9). Of course, a more nuanced sociological account would ask how the edifice is constructed to withstand challenge and to question the ways in which ideologies are entwined with power. Piketty, however, is interested in setting out the forms of inequality that (p.70) structure different nations and examining the ideologies used to justify those inequalities. Further, he seeks to examine the contemporary implications of these processes so that we are better able to transform them, in the future, toward more egalitarian ends. The central problem animating the volume is that the meritocratic narratives that have come to justify modern inequality are looking ever more fragile. Further, he argues that if the economic system they are justifying is not radically transformed, we are looking at the collapse of the global economy and a future defined by xenophobic populism. In order to avoid such an outcome, Piketty continues, it is necessary to understand the weaknesses of such narratives and, for this, it is important to adopt a transnational approach and one that is historically informed. This would enable the construction of “a new universalist egalitarian narrative” and one that would, in turn, provide the basis for “a new participatory socialism for the twentyfirst century” (2020, p. 3). In these terms, Piketty, then, is making a justificatory argument for less inequality, and not simply addressing modern justifications of inequality……. ……….The key issue… is that Piketty organizes his historical comparative analysis in terms of inequality within nations. Yet, the polities he is discussing were rarely nations over the long durée. Rather, they were imperial formations constituted by a colonizing state and the territories and populations that were incorporated. In fact, the “nations” that Piketty discusses, only become nations after decolonization. The relations between colonizer and colonized are also significant in the production and reproduction of inequalities both within countries and between them. Without an adequate understanding of global colonial entanglements, I argue that it is not possible to put forward a credible future alternative to current inequalities…….. *71 In his discussion of slavery, for example, Piketty starts by stating that “slave societies existed long before European colonialism” and then goes on to comment that his focus will be on “the ways in which slavery was abolished in the modern era” (2020, p. 203). There are a scant couple of pages addressing slavery in ancient societies, serfdom, and modern slavery, before a more extensive discussion of abolition covering the rest of the chapter. There is no significant discussion of what slavery actually was and how the modern form of it—chattel slavery—was established. There is very little discussion of the revenue brought into European countries through their involvement in the trade in human beings, their use of enslaved labor 10 on plantations, or the impact of the expansion of these markets for the sale of their goods. There is also no explicit discussion of what idea of social justice was embedded in the legitimation of the regimes of slavery or colonialism given that Piketty earlier states that “every ideology … expresses a certain idea of social justice” (2020, p. 9). What constitutes (or, what could constitute) the legitimacy of modern slavery as a regime of inequality? Do those who were enslaved need to feel that their bondage is justified? Piketty does not address such questions and nor is there any discussion of why those who were enslaved, or the societies from which they were taken, were not thought to have anything of significance to say about the processes of enslavement or their own humanity (see Grovogui, 2009). Given that modern chattel slavery entails the commodification of the laborer and his or her use as property, it is more appropriately understood as part of the proprietarian regime and not a regime separate from it (see Bhambra & Holmwood, 2018). Nearly all of Piketty's discussion of slavery is about its abolition, which, in turn, is discussed primarily in terms of the compensation to be paid to those who had owned other people. While abolition is presented as a consequence of reforms deriving from the ideology of equality, Piketty also argues that given that those who were enslaved were private property, it was appropriate that slave owners be compensated for their loss. He is largely silent on the justice of reparations for those who were enslaved and lost property in their own persons …… *72 There are similar issues with Piketty's conceptualization of colonialism which presents colonial societies as separate from proprietarian ones. He turns to addressing colonial societies by stating that the “forms of domination and inequality … were less extreme than slavery” (2020, p. 252). He then goes on to identify two ages of European colonialism. The first from 1500 to 1850 which was characterized by “military domination and forced displacement and/or extermination of populations” (2020, p. 253). The second was from 1850 to the 1960s and, he suggests, “is often said to have been kinder and gentler” although he accepts that “violence was scarcely absent from the second phase” (2020, p. 253). However, his focus on colonial societies is on the ideologies that sustained forms of inequality within societies that were colonized. Not on the inequalities produced through colonialism. As such, he focuses on caste in India, for example, as opposed to accounting for the processes of colonial drain that enriched Britain as they impoverished India…. In contrast to Piketty, I would argue that colonialism cannot be understood as a category separate to that of proprietarianism. This is because it is constituted by the proprietarian regime taking other territories and populations into private ownership and through its enforcement of trade relations and the use of coerced labor on colonial plantations. Are those who are subject to colonial rule willing subjects? Do they consent to their colonization and exploitation? By not even raising such issues—issues that pertain to questions of legitimacy which are, in turn, seen to be integral to the framework as otherwise presented— points to the inadequacy of the conceptualization at work here. For example, while Piketty acknowledges that the Chinese and Indian share of global manufacturing output, which had been 53% in 1800, had fallen to 5% by 1900 he does not see this as necessarily linked to the historical processes of colonialism and its determination of the modern world. Rather, he suggests that “it would be absurd to view this as the only possible trajectory leading to the Industrial Revolution and modern prosperity… one can imagine other historical trajectories” (2020, p. 381). The modern world, it seems, need not have been produced through slavery and colonialism. But the 11 point is surely to account for its actual historical trajectory not conjecture that it need not have happened this way and imagine other ones? The purpose of such conjecture is to imagine a logic of proprietarianism independently of slavery and colonialism. In this way, the actual trajectory is elided for the present as something in need of redress. As such, Piketty's regimes of inequality implicitly justify unequal treatment of others without including them in the discussion of that treatment….. 12 ___________________________________________________________________________ Butler, J. (1999) Gender Trouble : Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Excerpts from pp. 163, 172-173, 174, 178,179, 180, 181,182, 183, 185 ___________________________________________________________________________ *163 Categories of true sex, discrete gender, and specific sexuality have constituted the stable point of reference for a great deal of feminist . . .*172 theory and politics. These constructs of identity serve as the points of epistemic departure from which theory emerges and politics itself is shaped. In the case of feminism, politics is ostensibly shaped to express the interests, the perspectives, of “women.” . . . Or is “the body” itself shaped by political forces with strategic interests in keeping that body bounded and constituted by the markers of sex?... From Interiority to Gender Performatives . . . That disciplinary production of gender effects a false stabilization of gender in the interests of the heterosexual construction and regulation of sexuality within the reproductive domain. . . . gen- *173 der discontinuities that run rampant within heterosexual, bisexual, and gay and lesbian contexts in which gender does not necessarily follow from sex, and desire, or sexuality generally, does not seem to follow from gender—indeed, where none of these dimensions of significant corporeality express or reflect one another. When the disorganization and disaggregation of the field of bodies disrupt the regulatory fiction of heterosexual coherence, it seems that the expressive model loses its descriptive force. That regulatory ideal is then exposed as a norm and a fiction that disguises itself as a developmental law regulating the sexual field that it purports to describe. . . . Such acts, gestures, enactments, generally construed, are performative in the sense that the essence or identity that they otherwise purport to express are fabrications manufactured and sustained through corporeal signs and other discursive means. . . . In other words, acts and gestures, articulated and enacted desires create the illusion of an interior and organizing gender core, an illusion discursively maintained for the purposes of the regulation of sexuality within the obligatory frame of reproductive heterosexuality. . . . *174 The displacement of a political and discursive origin of gender identity onto a psychological “core” precludes an analysis of the political constitution of the gendered subject and its fabricated notions about the ineffable interiority of its sex or of its true identity….. . . . *178 Discrete genders are part of what “humanizes” individuals within contemporary culture; indeed, we regularly punish those who fail to do their gender right. . . Consider that a sedimentation of gender norms produces the peculiar phenomenon of a “natural sex” or a “real woman” or any number of prevalent and compelling social fictions, and that this is a sedimentation that over time has produced a set of corporeal styles which, in reified form, appear as the natural configuration of bodies into sexes existing in a binary relation to one another. . . . *179 Gender ought not to be construed as a stable identity or locus of agency from which various acts follow; rather, gender is an identity tenuously constituted in time, instituted in an exterior space through a stylized repetition of acts. . . . acts, in the possibility of a failure to repeat, a de-formity, or a parodic repetition that exposes the phantasmatic effect of abiding identity as a politically tenuous construction. 13 *180 . . . That gender reality is created through sustained social performances means that the very notions of an essential sex and a true or abiding masculinity or femininity are also constituted as part of the strategy that conceals gender’s performative character and the performative possibilities for proliferating gender configurations outside the restricting frames of masculinist domination and compulsory heterosexuality…. *181 Conclusion: From Parody to Politics . . . The feminist “we” is always and only a phantasmatic construction, one that has its purposes, but which denies the internal complexity and indeterminacy of the term and constitutes itself only through the exclusion of some part of the constituency that it simultaneously seeks to represent. The tenuous or phantasmatic status of the “we,” however, is not cause for despair or, at least, it is not only cause for despair. The radical instability of the category sets into question the foundational restrictions on feminist political theorizing and opens up other configurations, not only of genders and bodies, but of politics itself. . . . My argument is that there need not be a “doer behind the deed,” but that the “doer” is variably constructed in and through the deed. This is not a return to an existential theory of the self as constituted through its acts, for the existential theory maintains a prediscursive structure for both the self and its acts. It is precisely the discursively variable construction of each in and through the other that has interested me here. *182 The question of locating “agency” is usually associated with the viability of the “subject,” where the “subject” is understood to have some stable existence prior to the cultural field that it negotiates. Or, if the subject is culturally constructed, it is nevertheless vested with an agency, usually figured as the capacity for reflexive mediation, that remains intact regardless of its cultural embeddedness. On such a model, “culture” and “discourse” mire the subject, but do not constitute that subject. This move to qualify and enmire the preexisting subject has appeared necessary to establish a point of agency that is not fully determined by that culture and discourse. And yet, this kind of reasoning falsely presumes (a) agency can only be established through recourse to a prediscursive “I,” even if that “I” is found in the midst of a discursive convergence, and (b) that to be constituted by discourse is to be determined by discourse, where determination forecloses the possibility of agency…. *183 What discursive tradition establishes the “I” and its “Other” in an epistemological confrontation that subsequently decides where and how questions of knowability and agency are to be determined? What kinds of agency are foreclosed through the positing of an epistemological subject precisely because the rules and practices that govern the invocation of that subject and regulate its agency in advance are ruled out as sites of analysis and critical intervention? That the epistemological point of departure is in no sense inevitable is naively and pervasively confirmed by the mundane operations of ordinary language…that regard the subject/object dichotomy as a strange and contingent, if not violent, philosophical imposition. …*185 The subject is not determined by the rules through which it is generated because signification is not a founding act, but rather a regulated process of repetition that both conceals itself and enforces its rules precisely through the production of substantializing effects. In a sense, all signification takes place within the orbit of the compulsion to repeat; “agency,” then, is to be located within the possibility of a variation on that repetition. . . . 14 ___________________________________________________________________________ Spivak, G. (1998) “Can the Subaltern Speak?” in Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, C. Nelson and L. Grossberg, eds. Excerpts pp. 66, 75, 76, 77, 78, 80, 82, 83, 102 ___________________________________________________________________________ *66 Some of the most radical criticism coming out of the West today is the result of an interested desire to conserve the subject of the West, or the West as Subject. The theory of pluralized ‘subject-effects’ gives an illusion of undermining subjective sovereignty while often providing a cover for this subject of knowledge. Although the history of Europe as Subject is narrativized by the law, political economy and ideology of the West, this concealed Subject pretends it has ‘no geo-political determinations’. The much-publicized critique of the sovereign subject thus actually inaugurates a Subject. I will argue for this conclusion by considering a text by two great practitioners of the critique: ‘Intellectuals and power: a conversation between Michel Foucault and Gilles Deluze’ . . . *75 . . . This S/subject, curiously sewn together into a transparency by denegations, belongs to the exploiters’ side of the international division of labor. It is impossible for contemporary French intellectuals to imagine the kind of Power and Desire that would inhabit the unnamed subject of the Other of Europe. It is not only that everything they read, critical or uncritical, is caught within the debate of the production of that Other, supporting or critiquing the constitution of the Subject as Europe. It is also that, in the constitution of that Other of Europe, great care was taken to obliterate the textual ingredients with which such a subject could cathect, could occupy (invest?) its itinerary—not only by ideological and scientific production, but also by the institution of the law. . . *76 The clearest available example of such epistemic violence is the remotely orchestrated, far-flung, and heterogeneous project to constitute the colonial subject as Other. This project is also the asymmetrical obliteration of the trace of that Other in its precarious Subject-ivity. . . . This is not to describe ‘the way things really were’ or to privilege the narrative of history as imperialism as the best version of history.26 It is, rather, to offer an account of how an explanation and narrative of reality was established as the normative one. To elaborate on this, let us consider briefly the underpinnings of the British codification of Hindu Law… Here… is a schematic summary of the epistemic violence of the codification of Hindu Law…….. At the end of the eighteenth century, Hindu law, insofar as it can be described as a unitary system, operated in terms of four texts that ‘staged’ a four-part episteme defined by the subject’s use of memory . . . *77 Legal theorists and practitioners were not in any given case certain if this structure described the body of law or four ways of settling a dispute. The legitimation of the polymorphous structure of legal performance, ‘internally’ noncoherent and open at both ends, through a binary vision, is the narrative of codification I offer as an example of epistemic violence. The narrative of the stabilization and codification of Hindu law is less well known than the story of Indian education, so it might be well to start there.28 Consider the often-quoted programmatic lines from Macaulay's infamous ‘Minute on Indian education’ (1835): ‘We must at present do our best to form a class who may be interpreters between us and the millions whom we govern; a class of persons, Indian in blood and colour, but English in taste, in 15 opinions, in morals, and in intellect. To that class we may leave it to refine the vernacular dialects of the country, to enrich those dialects with terms of science borrowed from the Western nomenclature, and to render them by degrees fit vehicles for conveying knowledge to the great mass of the population.’29 The education of colonial subjects complements their production in law. . . . *78 Let us now move to consider the margins (one can just as well say the silent, silenced center) of the circuit marked out by this epistemic violence, men and women among the illiterate peasantry, the tribals, the lowest strata of the urban subproletariat. According to Foucault and Deleuze…. the oppressed, if given the chance, ….and on the way to solidarity through alliance politics….., can speak and know their conditions. We must now confront the following question: on the other side of the international division of labor from socialized capital, inside and outside the circuit of the epistemic violence of imperialist law and education supplementing an earlier economic text, can the subaltern speak? Antonio Gramsci's work on the ‘subaltern classes’ …is concerned with the intellectual’s role in the subaltern’s cultural and political movement into the hegemony. This movement must be made to determine the production of history as narrative (of truth)....,Gramsci considers the movement of historical-political economy in Italy within what can be seen as an allegory of reading taken from or prefiguring an international division of labor.36 Yet an account of the phased development of the subaltern is thrown out of joint when his cultural macrology is operated, however remotely, by the epistemic interference with legal and disciplinary definitions accompanying the imperialist project. ….. The first part of my proposition—that the phased development of the subaltern is complicated by the imperialist project—is confronted by a collective of intellectuals who may be called the ‘Subaltern Studies’ group.37 ……Their project is to rethink Indian colonial historiography from the perspective of the discontinuous chain of peasant *79 insurgencies during the colonial occupation. . . . *80 . . . In subaltern studies, because of the violence of imperialist epistemic, social and disciplinary inscription, a project understood in essentialist terms must traffic in a radical textual practice of differences. … . . . For the ‘true’ subaltern group, whose identity is its difference, there is no unrepresentable subaltern subject that can know and speak itself; the intellectual’s solution is not to abstain from representation. The problem is that the subject’s itinerary has not been traced so as to offer an object of seduction to the representing intellectual. In the slightly dated language of the Indian group, the question becomes, How can we touch the consciousness of the people, even as we investigate their politics? With what voice-consciousness can the subaltern speak? . . . *82 It is well known that the notion of the feminine (rather than the subaltern of imperialism) has been used in a similar way within deconstructive criticism and within certain varieties of feminist criticism.46 In the former case, a figure of ‘woman’ is at issue, one whose minimal predication as indeterminate is already available to the phallocentric tradition. Subaltern historiography raises questions of method that would prevent it from using such a ruse. For the ‘figure’ of woman, the relationship between woman and silence can be plotted by women themselves; race and class differences are subsumed under that charge. Subaltern historiography must confront the impossibility of such gestures. The narrow epistemic violence 16 of imperialism gives us an imperfect allegory of the general violence that is the possibility of an episteme.47 Within the effaced itinerary of the subaltern subject, the track of sexual difference is doubly effaced. The question is not of female participation in insurgency, or the ground rules of the sexual division of labor, for both of which there is ‘evidence’. It is, rather, that, both as object of colonialist historiography and as subject of insurgency, the ideological construction of gender keeps the male dominant. If, in *83 the context of colonial production, the subaltern has no history and cannot speak, the subaltern as female is even more deeply in shadow.. . . *102 Between patriarchy and imperialism, subject-constitution and object-formation, the figure of the woman disappears, not into a pristine nothingness, but into a violent shuttling which is the displaced figuration of the ‘third-world woman’ caught between tradition and modernization. . 17 Jackson, Z. (2020) Becoming Human: Matter and Meaning in an Anti-Black World. Excerpts from pp. 7-9 ___________________________________________________________________________ *7 about a world “out there” but also how we “know ourselves.” Epistemology is a problem not of the past but one that is constituent with our being. By the nineteenth century, the Chain of Being’s physical anthropology, using human and animal physical measurements, sealed the connection between Africans and apes as scientific fact. One must only recall the manner in which Sara Baartman, the so-called Hottentot Venus, was displayed for the British and French public as both pornographic spectacle and scientific specimen (Gilman 88). Her physiognomic characteristics—posterior and genitals—were presumed to signal a difference in sexuality that was pronounced enough to further divide the categories of “female” and “woman”: an idealized white femininity became paradigmatic of “woman” through the abjection of the perceived African “female” (Gilman 83–85). Female, rather than woman, African femaleness is paradoxically placed under the sign of absence, lack, and pathology in order to present an idealized western European bourgeois femininity as the normative embodiment of womanhood (Gilman 85–108). In this context, the potential recognition of womanhood in blackness, and especially black femininity, is placed in tension with the discourses on black female sexuality. Hortense Spillers put it this way: “In the universe of unreality and exaggeration, the black female is, if anything, a creature of sex, but sexuality touches her nowhere . . . the female has so much sexual potential that she has none at all that anybody is ready to recognize at the level of culture” (Black, White, and in Color 155, emphasis in original). The perpetual specter of black female lack in the realm of culturally and historically produced femininity, at the register of both performativity and morphology, produces “the African female” as paradigmatically indeterminate in terms of gender and paradigmatically the human’s limit case. The spectacularization of the posterior has perhaps blinded our critical attention to the manner with which ontologizing racial characterization not only divides and stratifies gender but also calls *8 into question the very meaning of sexual difference. Shifting critical attention from the posterior to the breast, I demonstrate that racism not only posits cleavages in womanhood such that black womanhood is imagined to be a gender apart (an “other” gender) but also an “other” sex. Additionally, antiblackness itself is sexuating, whereby so-called biological sex is modulated by “culture.” ……Thus, antiblack formulations of gender and sexuality are actually essential rather than subsidiary to the metaphysical figuration of matter, objects, and animals that recent critical theory hopes to dislodge. I argue the plasticization of black(ened) people at the register of sign and materiality is central to the prevailing logics and praxis of the human and sex/gender. Recent scholarship in black queer theory suggests we can no longer presume that gender is a metonym for “woman” and sexuality a metonym for “queer.” The wanton manipulation of gendered and sexual codes is essential to the production of antiblackness generally, irrespective of self-identification.6 Queer theory scholars have argued that the masculine–feminine dynamic is on the register of the symbolic, rather than the biological, even though it masquerades as if the borders dividing masculine from feminine map neatly onto the “natural” polarity of sex.7 What feminism has not sufficiently interrogated is 18 the manner in which the masculine–feminine dichotomy is racialized. We have neither adequately identified that racialization is intrinsic to the legibility of its codes and grammar, namely that antiblackness constitutes and disrupts sex/gender constructs, nor determined the consequence this has for the matter of the sexed body. Such a predicament creates conditions of gendered and sexual anxiety and instability. As Spillers states, “[I]n the historic outline of dominance, the respective subject-positions of ‘female’ and ‘male’ *9 adhere to no symbolic integrity,” as their meaning can be stripped or appropriated arbitrarily by power, as black females’ claim to “womanhood and femininity still tends to rest too solidly on the subtle and shifting calibrations of a liberal ideology” (“Mama’s” 204, 223). Thus, while codes of gender are cultural rather than prediscursive, one must also attend to the matter of the body, as the body’s materiality is thought to provide the observable “fact” of animality. The African’s “failure” to achieve humanity has historically been thought to be rooted in “the body,” in an insatiable appetite that made it impossible for the African to rise above “the body,” “the organ,” in order to come back to itself in self-reflection, never achieving the distance required in order to contemplate the self (Mbembe 190). Gender, and especially sexuality, was leveraged against counterclaims acknowledging black reason and civility. For thinkers such as Thomas Jefferson, black gender and black kinship stood as an impediment to black progress. So, while it seems that the human must be reconsidered, a critical engagement with the discourses of gender and sexuality must be coincident to our interrogation of both dominant and emergent praxes of being. At this time, most feminist scholars can agree that an “intersectional” approach to the question of subjectivity is required, but scholars have not clarified how the different elements of subjectivity braid together historically and culturally……. Our task would be to take seriously the particularization of gender and sexuality in black(ened) people in the context of a humanism that in its desire to universalize, ritualistically posits black(female)ness as opacity, inversion, and limit. In such a context, the black body is characterized by a plasticity, whereby raciality arbitrarily remaps black(ened) gender and sexuality, nonteleologically and nonbinaristically, with fleeting adherence to normativized heteropatriarchal codes. In such a context of paradoxical (un)gendering, and by gendering I mean humanization, power only takes direction from its own shifting exigencies—a predicament that might be described as chaos. 19 ___________________________________________________________________________ Fineman, M.A. (2008) "The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition" 20 (1) Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 1. Excerpts from pp. 8 – 12. ___________________________________________________________________________ [p. 8] In discussions of public responsibility, the concept of vulnerability is sometimes used to define groups of fledgling or stigmatized subjects, designated as "populations."' Vulnerability is typically associated with victimhood, deprivation, dependency, or pathology. For example, public health discourse refers to "vulnerable populations," such as those who are infected with HIV-AIDS. Groups of persons living in poverty or confined in prisons or other state institutions are often labeled as vulnerable populations. Children and the elderly are prototypical examples of more sympathetic vulnerable populations. In contrast, I want to claim the term "vulnerable" for its potential in describing a universal, inevitable, enduring aspect of the human condition that must be at the heart of our concept of social and state responsibility. Vulnerability thus freed from its limited and negative associations is a powerful [p.9] conceptual tool with the potential to define an obligation for the state to ensure a richer and more robust guarantee of equality than is currently afforded under the equal protection model. This vulnerability approach both expands upon and complements earlier work I have done in theorizing dependency. The technique is to focus on a concept or term in common use, but also grossly under-theorized, and thus ambiguous. Even when the term is laden with negative associations, the ambiguity provides an opportunity to begin to explore and excavate the unarticulated and complex relationships inherent but latent in the term. Thus reconsidered, the concept of vulnerability can act as a heuristic device, pulling us back to examine hidden assumptions and biases that shaped its original social and cultural meanings. Conceiving of vulnerability in this way renders it valuable in constructing critical perspectives on political and societal institutions, including law. Vulnerability raises new issues, poses different questions, and opens up new avenues for critical exploration. Vulnerability initially should be understood as arising from our embodiment, which carries with it the ever-present possibility of harm, injury, and misfortune from mildly adverse to catastrophically devastating events, whether accidental, intentional, or otherwise. Individuals can attempt to lessen the risk or mitigate the impact of such events, but they cannot eliminate their possibility. Understanding vulnerability begins with the realization that many such events are ultimately beyond human control. Our embodied humanity carries with it the ever-constant possibility of dependency as a result of disease, epidemics, resistant viruses, or other biologically-based catastrophes. Our bodies are also vulnerable to other forces in our physical environment: There is the constant possibility that we can be injured and undone by errant weather systems, such as those that produce flood, drought, famine, and fire. These are "natural" disasters beyond our individual control to prevent. Our bodily vulnerability is enhanced by the realization that [p. 10] should we succumb to illness or injury there may be accompanying economic and institutional harms as a result of disruption of existing relationships. Because we are positioned differently within a web of economic and institutional relationships, our vulnerabilities range in magnitude and potential at the individual level. 20 Undeniably universal, human vulnerability is also particular: it is experienced uniquely by each of us and this experience is greatly influenced by the quality and quantity of resources we possess or can command. Significantly, the realization that no individual can avoid vulnerability entirely spurs us to look to societal institutions for assistance. Of course, society cannot eradicate our vulnerability either. However, society can and does mediate, compensate, and lessen our vulnerability through programs, institutions, and structures. Therefore, because both our personal and our social lives are marked and shaped by vulnerability, a vulnerability analysis must have both individual and institutional components. A. The Vulnerable Subject Understanding the significance, universality, and constancy of vulnerability mandates that politics, ethics, and law be fashioned around a complete, comprehensive vision of the human experience if they are to meet the needs of real-life subjects. Currently, dominant political and legal theories are built around a universal human subject defined in the liberal tradition. These theories presume the liberal subject is a competent social actor capable of playing multiple and concurrent societal roles: the employee, the employer, the spouse, the parent, the consumer, the manufacturer, the citizen, the taxpayer, and so on. This liberal subject informs our economic, legal, and political principles. It is indispensable to the prevailing ideologies of autonomy, self-sufficiency, and personal responsibility, through which society is conceived as constituted by self-interested individuals with the capacity to manipulate and manage their independently acquired and overlapping resources. The legal metaphor encapsulating this vision of societal organization is "contract." Liberal subjects have the ability to negotiate contract terms, assessing their options and making rational choices. They consent to such agreements in the course of fulfilling society's mandate that they assume personal responsibility for themselves and for their dependants. Privacy principles that restrain the state and its institutions from interfering with the [p.11] liberal subjects' entitlements to autonomy and liberty depend on this presumed competence and capability. Vulnerability analysis questions the idea of a liberal subject, suggesting that the vulnerable subject is a more accurate and complete universal figure to place at the heart of social policy. There have been many critiques of the liberal subject, most of which focus on autonomy. For instance, feminist scholars have scrutinized and criticized the ways in which dominant theory and popular politics idealize notions of independence, autonomy, and selfsufficiency that are empirically unrealistic and unrealizable. Feminist critics, specifically in bringing dependency and care work into light and under scrutiny, have offered a model of interdependence in which the liberal subject is enmeshed in a web of relationships and perceived as dependent upon them. A vulnerability critique builds on these insights, but differs in several ways. Vulnerability is a more encompassing concept and, for that reason, analyses centered around vulnerability are more politically potent than those based on dependency. Because dependency is episodic and shifts in degree on an individual level for most of us, mainstream political and social theorists can and often do conveniently ignore it. In their hands, dependency, if acknowledged at all, is merely a stage that the liberal subject has long ago transcended or left behind and is, therefore, of no pressing theoretical interest. In addition, society has historically dealt with dependency by relegating the burden of caretaking to the 21 family, which is located within a zone of privacy, beyond the scope of state concern absent extraordinary family failures, such as abuse or neglect. Thus largely rendered invisible within the family, dependency is comfortably and mistakenly assumed to be adequately managed for the vast majority of people. By contrast, understood as a state of constant possibility of harm, vulnerability cannot be hidden. Further, while institutions such as the family may provide some shelter, they are unable to eliminate individual vulnerability and are themselves vulnerable structures susceptible to harm and change. Because vulnerability is ever-present and enduring, institutional as well as individual, it suggests a critique of dominant modes of thinking about inequality that is at once complementary to but more powerful than dependency. My argument is not for vulnerability to supplant dependency, for they each reveal different and important things. Rather, the assertion is that vulnerability analysis may ultimately prove more theoretically powerful. In addition, the vulnerability perspective calls attention to another problematic characteristic of the liberal subject: S/he can only be presented as an adult. As such, the liberal subject stands not only outside of the passage of time, but also outside of human experience. The construction of the adult [p.12] liberal subject captures only one possible developmental stage-the least vulnerable-from among the many possible stages an actual individual might pass through if s/he lives a "normal" lifespan. We must confront this foundational flaw in the liberal model if we are to develop legal and social policies that reflect the lived realities of human subjects. The vulnerable subject approach does what the one-dimensional liberal subject approach cannot: it embodies the fact that human reality encompasses a wide range of differing and interdependent abilities over the span of a lifetime. The vulnerability approach recognizes that individuals are anchored at each end of their lives by dependency and the absence of capacity. Of course, between these ends, loss of capacity and dependence may also occur, temporarily for many and permanently for some as a result of disability or illness. Constant and variable throughout life, individual vulnerability encompasses not only damage that has been done in the past and speculative harms of the distant future, but also the possibility of immediate harm. We are beings who live with the ever- present possibility that our needs and circumstances will change. On an individual level, the concept of vulnerability (unlike that of liberal autonomy) captures this present potential for each of us to become dependent based upon our persistent susceptibility to misfortune and catastrophe. 22 ___________________________________________________________________________ Bernstein, E. (2018) Brokered Subjects: Sex, Trafficking and the Politics of Freedom. Excerpts from pp. 107, 109-112, 115 -118 ___________________________________________________________________________ *107 Although the sale of sexual services is currently illegal in Thailand, the Thai government does little to curb the existence of businesses that cater to sex tourists.31 In fact, the government has historically supported sex tourism because of its military and economic positioning in the area…….. *109 Preconditioned by anti-trafficking NGOs and popular representations of human trafficking, reality tourists interpret commercial sex as a deplorable symptom of third-world poverty and regard sex workers as victims-by- definition who lack meaningful voice and agency. The erotically charged images of anti-trafficking campaigns and the reality tourists’ desires to save worthy victims ironically mirror the humanitarian impulses that inflect some forms of sex tourism—revealing a neocolonial formation that includes not only secular and evangelical activists but also those clients of sex workers who also endeavor to “help. Anti-Trafficking Tourism as Humanitarian Endeavor Previous chapters have pointed to the various ways in which moral agendas around sex work have become intricately interwoven with contemporary anti-trafficking campaigns. They have also described anti-trafficking activists’ frequent equation of even adult and voluntary forms of prostitution with “sex trafficking,” and the tendency among activists (including when their focus is expanded to include forms of trafficking into other labor sectors) to single out sex trafficking as the most devastating case. As commentators such as legal scholar Jennifer Chacón have *110 noted, “trafficking” as defined in current federal law and in international protocols could conceivably encompass sweatshop labor, agricultural work, or even corporate crime, but it has been the far less common instances of sexually trafficked women and girls that have stimulated the most concern by evangelical Christians, prominent feminist activists, and the press.41 The tour operators on our trip frequently reproduced such assumptions and elisions, as did the promotional materials for the tour. For instance, the photo that advertises the Thailand tour in Global Exchange’s promotional materials invokes the simultaneous moral and erotic allure of the enigmatic industry. It depicts an interracial couple embracing in a public balcony ensconced in bright red light. The blurry image, never explicit in its caption of what viewers are actually witnessing, suggests a clandestine peek into what is referred to in the accompanying text as a photographic representation of “the global sex trade.” The photo foregrounds the “redlight district” as evidence of the realities of human trafficking, despite the fact that brothel-style sex establishments such as the one depicted have all but disappeared from Thailand due to the aforementioned combination of changing local market economies, public health concerns around controlling HIV/AIDS, and recent legislation around prostitution.42 Furthermore, the district that the photo is meant to portray would likely include a diverse range of beer bars, go-Go bars, massage parlors, and karaoke bars, all distinct types of commercial establishments that employ sex workers to provide various forms of entertainment. Reality tourists are thus not encouraged to see the vast array of possible labor arrangements and power relations that encompass commercial sex work, or the particular political and economic factors that make the situation of the Thai sex industry unique. 23 *111 Both the tour leaders and the participants on our reality tour shared the conviction that commercial sex and human trafficking cannot be easily distinguished, a fact that became clear during the initial round of group introductions. During our first dinner together, over a table of Thai tourist staples like pad thai and Singha beer, the tour leaders asked participants to introduce themselves and to briefly explain their interest in the anti-trafficking tour. Several of the young women named popular movies on both sex work and sex trafficking, like Born into Brothels and Taken, as their primary motivation for joining the tour.43 As one master’s degree student from a university in central California eagerly shared: “We watched Born into Brothels in one of my classes and that just opened the door for me.” The deeply felt significance of this film was shared by a journalist from Atlanta, who echoed: “I am very passionate about ending human trafficking. Born into Brothels was also the film that really introduced me to the sex trade.” Other participants attributed their interest in the issue to the 2004 Hollywood film Taken, which tells the story of an American teenager who is kidnapped on a vacation to Paris and nearly forced to become a sex worker before she is rescued. Reflecting on them as a “wake-up call” as to how pervasive global sex trafficking has become, another female tourist noted that movies like Taken alerted her to “just how real” the problem of human trafficking was. The grounding of knowledge claims in sensationalist films about sex trafficking had thus shaped tourists’ visions of “reality” and led them to broadly define all sex work as human trafficking before they had even left US soil. Consistent with the findings of other studies of humanitarian travel, the reality tour that travelers embarked on in Thailand did nothing to disabuse them of preexisting feelings and beliefs. In her study of Canadian aid workers, Barbara Heron emphasizes the important role played by Western media in the process of “othering” Global South nations, and the ways in which it “normalizes our centering of ourselves in relation to other people’s needs.”44 In her ethnographic research on volunteer tourism in Guatemala and Ghana, Wanda Vrasti similarly found that tourists had established certain expectations of travel prior to departure, including levels of poverty that deem a tourist destination * 112 worthy of aid, and a gracious and welcoming recipient population in the host country. *115 One day of our anti-trafficking reality tour was subcontracted to the Mirror Art Foundation, which agreed to provide us with an ecotour of the region, including an elephant ride, dinner, and participation in a dance performance in an ethnic minority village. Our group was driven down a bumpy, unpaved road located about twenty minutes from the nearest highway and deposited at the foot of a local Akha community. One of six indigenous hill-tribe populations in Thailand, the Akha are based in rural mountainous areas in the north, and many Akha persons continue to be without Thai citizenship and thus ineligible for land, services, or social protection under the law. Traditionally practitioners of subsistence farming, Akha communities now engage in cash cropping for sale, and increasingly participate in the tourist economy by hosting ecotours and producing ethnic handicrafts.55 As we disembarked from our van, half a dozen Akha women stood waiting at the entrance to the village, adorned in colorfully woven headpieces and dresses, unveiling baskets full of handicraft items for sale. After completing their purchases, our group was ushered to sit in a giant circle of chairs where we were given the opportunity to direct questions to a person described as the village leader. Eager to have this opportunity, a social worker from Boston 24 asked earnestly: “Have you had any cases of human trafficking here?” Through a translator provided by the Mirror Art Foundation, the Akha village leader told us he had never heard of the term “human trafficking,” and after some clarification of the terminology, he told the group that this was not a key problem in the village. Disregarding his response, other reality tourists persisted with similar lines of questioning: “What about migration? Do people from this village leave to work?” The village leader once again said that this wasn’t their primary problem. As the discussion circle disbanded and we headed to a meal that had been prepared for us (described by tour guides as a “typical” Akha dinner…..), tour participants huddled together and agreed that the village leader must have been lying. They easily dismissed the village leader’s claim that in lieu of human trafficking, the more pressing issues of concern were securing Thai citizenship for ethnic hill-tribe populations and the aggressive infringement of land by corporations and the Thai government.56 While they appreciated the Akha village’s food, handicrafts, and costumes as an “authentic glimpse” into hill-tribe life, they quickly dismissed as fabricated the village leader’s claim that his village was not particularly vulnerable to human trafficking. Just as Vrasti found in her study of volunteer tourism, the cultural authenticity of the tourist experience and the validity of insider claims were called into question only when they violated tourists’ preexisting notions of social realities.57 Significantly, the tourists ignored the most “authentic” *117 voice they had heard so far—that of the Akha village leader himself—because it did not conform to the understandings of human trafficking that they already harbored, accounts that had been confirmed for them by the Mirror Art Foundation’s “experts.” Selling Sex and Trafficking: Conflations and Contestations In contrast to the Akha village leader who claimed that human trafficking was not as relevant as were concerns about citizenship and land rights—issues that were never otherwise addressed during the tour—the reality tour’s insistence on the pernicious and pervasive nature of human trafficking was explicitly asserted during our visit to the Labor Rights Promotion Network in Bangkok, an organization that focuses on the labor rights of migrant workers in the Thai fishing industry. Founded in 2004, LRPN was one of the earliest advocates and service providers for victims of labor trafficking in deep-sea fishing and the shrimp-peeling industries.58 Alongside the growth of global anti-trafficking campaigns, LRPN has received a significant amount of international attention for *118 addressing the problems of severe labor exploitation in the Thai fishing industry. LRPN has also received a steady stream of funding to pursue research, advocacy, and direct interventions in human trafficking. During our visit to the organization, we huddled around a large table in the organization’s meeting room while LRPN’s director of human trafficking programs described the basic parameters of three recent trafficking cases that they had worked on: a labor trafficking case, a case of trafficking for domestic servitude, and a case of sex trafficking. When describing the sex-trafficking case, LRPN pulled up photographs of a raid that they had conducted in collaboration with the Thai Department of Special Investigations, one of the government antitrafficking agencies. The majority of photographs focused on the special team that had been assembled to deal with the case: a large group of first responders including cameramen, note takers, social workers, and police agents converging on a room where several sex workers lived. One grainy 25 photo that briefly flashed on the screen depicted eight women sitting in a simple living room adorned with only heavily worn furniture. The presenter explained that the squalid living conditions in this home represented a clear indication of human trafficking. Aside from the brief and occluded glimpse into what appeared to be merely a room full of Asian women, the presenter never indicated to us why this case was considered a case of trafficking under current Thai law.59 Puzzled by the still-unspecified particulars of the alleged sex-trafficking case, we queried the LRPN representative further, hoping to get a better sense of how the organization identified trafficking cases and how they distinguished consensual from coerced forms of sexual labor. Frustrated by our persistent questioning, one reality tour participant shook her head grimly and whispered to her neighbor: “Why don’t they believe that it’s trafficking? Did you see the conditions they were living in?” Like the other tour participants, she was already schooled in the cinematic language of what the medical anthropologist Carole Vance has termed “melomentary,” a cinematic genre in which “the horror of sex is amplified by the horror of poverty.” In melomentaries, Vance notes, the camera visually attributes “residential crowding, lack of clean water, TB, poor hygiene, disease, and living on the street specifically to brothels, prostitution, and sex trafficking, rather than to the more general and widespread living conditions of impoverished people.”60 Fluent in the cinematic languages of melomentary that Vance describes, the tour participants required no proof of human trafficking beyond the photos of the dimly lit and crowded living conditions in a brothel located in one of the poorer sections. In fact, we were soon to discover that the actual case turned out to be significantly more complicated than initially presented. When we interviewed the LRPN presenter on our own following the larger group meeting, we learned that the case concerned a group of migrant Laotian sex workers, many of whom, LRPN admitted, were working willingly. Given that they were undocumented, the police raid that was done in the name of “combating human trafficking” left the majority of workers facing deportation. Meanwhile, those workers who were under the age of eighteen were automatically classified as “victims of trafficking,” because as minors, they legally did not have the right to choose to be sex workers. This latter group was taken to government shelters, where they would be held (with or without their consent, it was not clear) until the legal proceedings against their brothel owners were completed. Through our own supplementary research with local sex worker organizations and activists, we would also later learn that many sex workers find such protectionist interventions to be even worse than jail or deportation because the “sentences” are indefinite, and because once they are deemed to be “victims of trafficking,” apprehended sex workers are subject to a number of gender-specific forms of discipline and control. The Empower Foundation has identified a number of common anti-trafficking practices which are justified by the state in the name of providing protection but are often experienced by sex workers as intrusive and discriminatory, including compulsory medical testing.61 26 ______________________________________________________________________________ Chuang J. (2010). “Rescuing Trafficking from Ideological Capture: Prostitution Reform and Anti- trafficking Law and Policy” 158 (6) University of Pennsylvania Law Review, pp. 16551728. Excerpts from 1657, 1701-1703 ______________________________________________________________________________ U.S. law and policy have fueled controversy over anti-trafficking strategies, both at home and abroad. In 2000, the United States led negotiations over a new international law on trafficking, the United Nations Protocol to Prevent, Suppress and Punish Trafficking in Persons, Especially Women and Children (the U.N. Trafficking Protocol). At the same time, the United States enacted a comprehensive domestic law on trafficking, the Trafficking Victims Protection Act. Both instruments define trafficking as the movement or recruitment of men, women, or children, using force, fraud, or coercion, for the purpose of subjecting them to involuntary servitude or slavery in one or more of a wide variety of sectors (for example, agriculture, construction, or commercial a concerted effort to move away from traditional perspectives that narrowly defined trafficking as the movement or recruitment of women or girls into the sex sector and toward a broader under- standing of the problem as also involving the exploitation of women, men, and children in non-sex sectors. Although trafficking into non-sex sectors arguably accounts for the larger proportion of trafficking activity, anti-trafficking laws and policies — both within the United States and abroad —have nonetheless remained focused on sex-sector trafficking and prostitution. This focus reflects the potent influence of prostitution-reform debates on the anti-trafficking movement. Those debates have embroiled anti- trafficking advocates and policymakers in a struggle over whether prostitution is inherently coercive, and therefore a form of trafficking, or whether the trafficking label should be applied only to instances of forced prostitution. The Bush Administration adopted the former position, marking the increasing influence of the “neoabolitionists”- an unlikely alliance of feminists, conservatives, and evangelical Christians who have used the anti-trafficking movement to pursue abolition of prostitution around the globe. …Through two discursive moves, this narrative redefines the putative victim population as linked to the sex sector—first, by focusing attention on sex-sector trafficking to the exclusion of non-sex-sector trafficking, and second, by conflating trafficking with prostitution. While in some sense all narratives are reductive, these particular discursive moves have set in motion a set of negative (however unintended) consequences. The reductive trafficking narrative oversimplifies the problem of trafficking from a complex human rights problem rooted in the failure of migration and labor frameworks to respond to globalizing trends, to a moral problem and crime of sexual violence against women and girls best addressed through an aggressive criminal justice response. In so doing, the narrative circumscribes the range and content of antitrafficking interventions proffered, feeding states’ preference for aggressive criminal justice responses. It overlooks, if not discounts, the need for better migration and labor frameworks or socioeconomic policies to counter the negative effects of globalizing trends that drive people to undertake risky migration projects in the first instance. *1702 Thus construed, trafficking is no longer the product of the disparties of wealth created by globalization, gendered labor markets, or in- adequate migration frameworks, but rather the result of the sexual *1703 proclivities of deviant individuals. The logic of this 27 representation suggests that to resolve the problem of trafficking, women should be rescued or deported back home, or prevented from traveling in the first place, and that governments should pass and aggressively enforce laws to punish these deviant elements…. Capitalizing on the “recycled” “tropes” of “violated femininity, shattered innocence, and the victimization of ‘women and children,” the neo-abolitionist campaign promotes, in Bernstein’s terms, a “militarized humanitarianism and carceral feminism” in its pursuit of social remedies. The neo-abolitionist approach thus feeds a border-protection and crime-control agenda by framing trafficking as a humanitarian issue that the “privileged” can combat by supporting efforts to rescue and restore victims and punish the depraved individuals who perpetrate the abuse…Notwithstanding multiple reports of failed rescues—where surprisingly high percentages of involuntarily “res- cued” women escaped the shelters in order to return to the brothels— the “rescue and restore” model has been enthusiastically embraced by faithbased and anti-prostitution feminist organizations alike, and lauded and generously funded by the U.S. government… .…The source of the harm thus lies not in institutions of corporate capitalism and the state but in “individual, deviant men: foreign brown men . . . or even more remarkably, African American men living in the inner city,” against whom the full power of law enforcement and criminal law must be brought to bear. Indeed, the “root cause” of much of the suffering in the developing world is not “hunger, homelessness, lack of education or disease” but “the failure of the criminal justice system to protect the poor from violence.” It is in this sense that neo-abolitionist constructions of the problem of trafficking hinder development of long-term strategies for combating trafficking. Assuming away agency on the part of female migrants obviates critical examination of the ways in which women turn to informal migration avenues and to the informal economy for work (including the sex sector). This, in turn, results in a fundamental failure to understand how restrictions on female migration, especially for semiskilled or un- skilled workers, actually make offers by third parties to facilitate their clandestine migration all the more attractive, thus increasing vulnerability to trafficking. Regrettably, the savior mentality avoids nuance in its quest for salvation and leaves little room for self- doubt. The fact that pursuing such raids brings in millions of dollars in federal funding, that shelters have a financial incentive to stay full (to justify their funding), and that governments rely on shelters as evidence of their efforts to combat trafficking (in response to the threat of U.S. anti-trafficking sanctions), adds to the disincentives for critical selfassessment. ….. [D]emand for trafficked persons is not simply about satiating sexual appetites or taking advantage of cheap migrant labor but deeply entwined with the trafficked person’s identity as a migrant “other.” The vulnerability and lack of choice that result from their migrant (and possibly foreign and undocumented) status foster the perception, if not the reality, that they are more “flexible” and “cooperative” with respect to poorer working conditions and more vulnerable to “molding” to the requirements of job. Moreover, their racial “otherness” makes it easier to “dress up a relation of exploitation as one of paternalism/maternalism” toward the impoverished “other.” 28 ______________________________________________________________________________ UNODC. (25 Nov. 2009). Human Trafficking Fuels Violence Against Women. Available at: https://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/frontpage/2009/November/human-trafficking-fuelsviolence-against-women.html ______________________________________________________________________________ As the world marks the International Day for the Elimination of Violence against Women, UNODC is drawing attention to how human trafficking fuels violence against women. In its Global Report on Trafficking in Persons UNODC revealed that two thirds of the identified victims of trafficking were women. In his message for the day, Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon stressed that whether the crime against women is rape, domestic violence, genital mutilation or trafficking for sexual exploitation, it is inexcusable and must be stopped. Human trafficking is, indeed, one of the worst forms of violence against women and girls. Traffickers may use violence to intimidate and subdue the victims. Once recruited, the women usually find themselves in situations with severely curtailed freedoms. Many times they suffer extreme physical and mental abuse, including through rape, imprisonment, forced abortions and physical brutality at the hands of their so-called "owners". The victims become isolated, losing ties with their former lives and families. With a better understanding of why women in particular are vulnerable to trafficking and how traffickers operate, and by providing the necessary legal and technical assistance to ensure that effective countermeasures are in place, this crime can be stopped. Violence against women does not only concern women. It concerns everyone, and the work to combat it must be done by all. Women around the world are the linchpin keeping families, communities and nations together. Eliminating gender discrimination and genderbased violence will enhance the dignity and human rights of women and girls and help prevent their being trafficked. Addressing human trafficking cuts across all fundamental issues. It is about human rights, peace and security, development and family health. In the most basic sense, it is about preserving the fabric of society. We all have a role to play, either in raising awareness, building partnerships, providing information, protecting victims or bringing the criminals to justice. 29 ______________________________________________________________________________ Wang, Di. 2020. “Jia, as in Guojia: building the Chinese Family into a Filial Nationalist Project” 5 (1) China Law & Society Review 1-32. Excerpts from pp. 2, 17-20 ______________________________________________________________________________ *2 China is not the only state with an interest in controlling its population and regulating reproduction. Yet Chinese family law and policy are a distinct example of how a strong state uses the law to shape its population of billions of people, reallocate resources among urban and rural families, and channel state repression through individual families. Indeed, one cannot understand Chinese law and society without understanding the Chinese family as a state project. To unpack this state-family project, this article asks how the patriarchal state constructs and manages the filial nationalist population to secure its authoritarian rule. Through the lens of emerging Chinese feminist and queer scholarship on families, this article also questions how this state-family project [p.3] has affected people and families who are intersectionally marginalized by gender, sexuality, class, the household registration [hukou 户口 ] system, and so on. *17 3.2 Filial Nationalism The first strategy that the Chinese state employs to legitimate its rule is filial nationalism, which Vanessa Fong (2004) defines as a kind of filial devotion to the state that builds on people’s unconditional loyalty to their parents. As previously discussed, the state has cultivated the one-child policy generation to change China’s economic fate (Greenhalgh 2010; Greenhalgh and Winckler 2005). These young people see themselves as competitive in the global economy, but they also see China as inferior to other, wealthier countries (Fong 2004). In addition, they have increased access to uncensored information about China, which makes them more likely to question the CCP’s accounts of historical events, from World War ii to the student-led democratic movement in the 1980s (Li and Li 2017; Zhao 2001). This awareness of critiques of China has made it more difficult for the state to imbue this generation with national- ism. For instance, research has shown that education in Chinese schools about the official history of the anti-Japanese war (1937–1945) has failed to develop nationalism in young students (Qian, Xu, and Chen 2017). In addition, since 2012 young feminist activists in the onechild policy generation have used social media to raise questions about the state’s unfulfilled promise of equality between men and women (Tan 2017; Wang and Liu 2020). *18 As it becomes more difficult to unite the new generation with glorified versions of the CCP’s history, the state strengthens people’s connections to, and dependence on, their families, combining the moral code of filial piety with state nationalist propaganda. As Eklund notes, in China, it is common to see propaganda billboards with slogans such as “Filial piety runs through the veins of the Chinese people” (2018, 296). As Fong (2004) finds, members of the one- child policy generation can maintain a strong sense of filial devotion to China by resolving their conflicting views of Chinese political and economic problems through the idiom of filial devotion. Instead of portraying China as admirable, these young people develop a strong sense of protecting the nation, especially against criticism from abroad, and responsibility for building the nation as a global power. Indeed, while young people are encouraged to love the nation as they love their parents, their increasing dependence on their families makes it much harder for them to break away from their parents’ control and the 30 nationalist state-family project. As Fong puts it, the powerful foundation of these young people’s nationalism is “the belief that they could no more cease to be ‘people of China’ than they could cease to be their parents’ children” (2004, 645). Although direct evidence of how the state uses filial piety is limited, activist observations of civil society provide meaningful insights into how filial piety and family relationships trouble people’s consciousness of their rights and sense of independence. Chinese feminist activists have articulated how families contribute to maintaining social stability. For example, in 2015 Zhao Sile, a feminist activist and writer, wrote an op-ed in the Oriental Daily News, a Hong Kong–based newspaper, observing that there are two tasks that Chinese families carry out to preserve social stability.18 The first task is to nudge their offspring to get married and have children so that they are structurally tied to the family. The second is to push them to work in stable careers. As Zhao pointed out, they do not have the option to be “an NGO worker, a journalist, a writer, an artist, and soon enough, being a lawyer will not be an option, either,” a reference to the July 9 crackdown on lawyers in 2015 when more than 200 Chinese lawyers and human rights activists were instigated by the state authorities (Fu 2018). The issues raised by the Chinese feminist movement show that instead of only focusing on cisnormative people in heterosexual relation- ships and with an urban hukou, more research should be done on how filial *19 nationalism affects the marriage and career decisions of marginalized people, such as lgbtq people, working-class people, and people with a rural hukou, as well as how Chinese activists of all genders view filial piety vis-à-vis both their families and the state. In addition, many questions have yet to be explored about how the two-child policy has influenced parental investment in a new generation that is more likely to grow up with siblings and how this change will affect intergenerational relations. 3.3 Relational Repression The second strategy the state uses to legitimate its rule is relational repression, which refers to the state’s mobilization of people’s strong and weak social relations to influence behavior and maintain social stability (Deng 2017; Deng and O’Brien 2013). In their studies of environmental protest (Deng and O’Brien 2013) and urban demolition (O’Brien and Deng 2015), Deng Yanhua and Kevin O’Brien found that some people withdrew from collective action because they were concerned that their participation in protests would cause family members to lose their livelihood or subject their loved ones to other kinds of punishment. Local state agents play on this fear by recruiting family members, close friends, and even superiors at work or school into thought-work teams [sixiang gongzuo xiaozu 思想工作小组], which are designed to deter individual protesters from resistance. In practice, these teams are more likely to gain cooperation from family members who are directly subject to state influence, such as local officers, public school teachers, and business owners with government partnerships. Similar incidents have been documented among people who petition the state (Biddulph 2015, 105) and religious protesters (Luo and Andreas 2016). Local state agents also mobilize neighbors and the surrounding community against dissidents, thereby using people’s fear of social ostracism to target entire families with “thought work.” As Deng Yanhua (2017) found in her work on “demolition and relocation” [chaiqian 拆迁], local state agents encourage all neighborhood residents to establish small committees and employ shame, guilt trips, and other marginalizing, and sometimes violent, strategies to harass recalcitrant homeowners, remove homeowners from their property, and 31 force them to obey state-approved chaiqian plans. In the name of respecting people’s selfdetermination about neighborhood development, the state forcibly implements its urbanization policy by relying on the neighborhood’s majority of people to police the minority and make their families vulnerable to neighbors’ shaming and attacks. This is a sophisticated social-control strategy that uses the weak social ties on which people’s well-being depends not only to hide the state from view in repressing popular protests but also to hijack democratic ideas such as community self-determination. *20 With the advent of a national LGBTQ movement and the increased visibility of LGBTQ people, the state’s practice of relational repression has started to incorporate homophobic tactics. Since 2015, local state agents have made it a frequent practice to “out” LGBTQ activists to their parents, on the assumption that doing so would neutralize their activist children.19 Unsurprisingly, such strategies “successfully” serve the state’s interests. In China, LGBTQ people cite their families as a top concern. It is not unusual for prominent Chinese LGBTQ activists to choose not to come out to their families, to use pseudonyms, and to rely on China’s censorship of LGBTQ rights issues to hide their activism from their families. Thus, after Chinese state agents learned that they could disrupt individuals’ family ties by “outing” them, they began to deploy this tac- tic to preserve “social stability.” For instance, on August 18, 2015, the first day of a new school year, Qiu Bai’s parents found out that their daughter was a lesbian after receiving a phone call from her university’s political ideology counselor. A college student activist, Qiu Bai had sued the Chinese Ministry of Education, challenging its inaction on homophobic school textbooks. According to Qiu, the university threatened to “out” her to her parents if she did not drop the case, and it finally made good on its threat when she refused to relent. Other incidents like this one suggest the need for systemic research on LGBTQ people’s unique vulnerability to the state-family project and the range of state tac- tics that target LGBTQ activists. Additionally, not all Chinese parents are homophobic, transphobic, or opposed to social movements. Future research should examine how parents and other family members refuse to pass down state messages as well as how parent-led alliance movements leverage their parental authority over their children’s reproductive decisions and social responsibility to resist state repression. 32