Encyclopedia of POWER Editorial Board Editor Keith Dowding Australian National University Advisory Board David A. Baldwin Princeton University Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland, Baltimore County Susan Fiske Princeton University David L. Swartz Boston University Mark Haugaard National University of Ireland, Galway Encyclopedia of POWER Edited by Keith Dowding Australian National University -6905-694(;065! :(.,7\ISPJH[PVUZ0UJ ;LSSLY9VHK ;OV\ZHUK6HRZ*HSPMVYUPH ,THPS!VYKLY'ZHNLW\IJVT Copyright © 2011 by SAGE Publications, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. :(.,7\ISPJH[PVUZ3[K 6SP]LY»Z@HYK *P[`9VHK 3VUKVU,*@:7 <UP[LK2PUNKVT :(.,7\ISPJH[PVUZ0UKPH7][3[K )04VOHU*VVWLYH[P]L0UK\Z[YPHS(YLH Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Encyclopedia of power/edited by Keith Dowding. 4H[O\YH9VHK5L^+LSOP 0UKPH :(.,7\ISPJH[PVUZ(ZPH7HJPÄJ7[L3[K 7LRPU:[YLL[ p. cm. — (A SAGE reference publication) Includes index. ISBN 978-1-4129-2748-2 (cloth : acid-free paper) -HY,HZ[:X\HYL :PUNHWVYL 1. Power (Social sciences)—Encyclopedias. I. Dowding, Keith M. HN49.P6E53 2011 303.303—dc22 2010032325 7\ISPZOLY! 9VSM(1HURL (ZZPZ[HU[[V[OL7\ISPZOLY! 4PJOLSL;OVTWZVU (JX\PZP[PVUZ,KP[VY! 3\J`9VIPUZVU +L]LSVWTLU[HS,KP[VYZ! +PHUH,(_LSZLU:HUMVYK9VIPUZVU 9LMLYLUJL:`Z[LTZ4HUHNLY! 3L[PJPH4.\[PLYYLa 9LMLYLUJL:`Z[LTZ*VVYKPUH[VY! 3H\YH5V[[VU 7YVK\J[PVU,KP[VY! 2H[L:JOYVLKLY *VW`LKP[VYZ! (SHU1*VVR9VIPU.VSK ;`WLZL[[LY! * 4+PNP[HSZ73[K 7YVVMYLHKLY! 2YPZ[PU)LYNZ[HK 0UKL_LY! 1VHU:OHWPYV *V]LY+LZPNULY! ,KNHY(IHYJH 11 12 13 14 15 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents List of Entries vii Reader’s Guide xi About the Editor xvii Contributors xix Introduction xxiii Entries A B C D E F G H I J K L 1 45 83 163 209 239 269 301 331 357 365 369 Index M N O P Q R S T U V W 725 395 435 457 471 543 549 585 657 677 683 701 List of Entries A Priori Unions. See Owen Value Ability Ableness Absolutism Adler, Alfred Adorno, Theodor Adverse Selection Agency Agency–Structure Problem Agenda Power Agenda Setters Alliances Althusser, Louis Anarchism, Power in Anarchy in International Relations Animal Groups, Power in Apparatus. See Dispositif Appeasement Arendt, Hannah Argument, Power of Aristotle Arms Race Authoritarian Personality Authority Autonomy Autonomy of the State. See Relative Autonomy of the State Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton Bakunin, Mikhail Balance of Power Banks Banzhaf. See Banzhaf Voting Power Measure Banzhaf Value Banzhaf Voting Power Measure Bargaining Bargaining in International Relations Barry, Brian Bases of Power Bicameral Legislature Biopower Blackmail Blocking Coalition Bourdieu, Pierre Bribe Index Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrats Bull, Hedley Bureaucracy. See Bureaucratic Power Bureaucratic Power Business and Power Cabal Capability Capital, Marxist Capital, Neoclassical Capture Theory of Regulation Carr, E. H. Cartwright, Dorwin Caste System (India) Castells, Manuel Causal Theories of Power Causation Central Intelligence Agency Chicken Games Civil War Clausewitz, Carl von Clegg, Stewart Coalition Theory Coercion, Analytic Coercion and Power vii Coleman, James S. Coleman Index Collective Action Problem Collective Goods. See Public Goods Community Power Debate Complex Equality (Walzer) Compliance (International) Computer Algorithms for Power Indices Consensual Power, Theories of Consent Constructivist View of Power in International Relations Control Conventional Deterrence Cooperation Coordination Core of a Game Core Parties Corporatism Corruption Coup d’État Cox, Robert W. Critical Theory Cuban Missile Crisis Dahl, Robert A. Decentering (of Subject, of Structure) Defensive Realism Deflected Wants Deliberation Deliberative Democracy Democracy Dependency Theory in International Relations Determinacy Determinism viii List of Entries Deterrence Theory Deterrent Threats Deutsch, Karl Dictatorship Diplomacy Discipline Discourse Dispositif Distributive Justice Domain Domhoff, G. William Dominant Parties Domination Dowding, Keith Eagly, Alice e-Governance Elections Elite Theories Empire Entrepreneurs Environmental Treaties Espionage Essentially Contested Concept Exchange Theory Exclusion Executive Power Exercise Fallacy Exit and Voice as Forms of Power Expectancy Confirmation, Power and Exploitation Extended Deterrence Fair Division False Consciousness Fascism Fear, Use of Federal Structure Felsenthal, Dan S. Female Leadership Among Mammals Feminist International Relations, View of Power Feminist Theories of Power First-Strike Capability Fiske, Susan Flyvbjerg, Bent Foucault, Michel Framing Free Market Free Rider. See Collective Action Problem Free Will Freedom French, John R. P., Jr Fungibility of Power Resources Imperialism Influence Intelligence Interdependence Theory Interests Internet and Power Invisible Hand I-Power Game Forms, Power in Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power Gender, Role of Power in Giddens, Anthony Global Cities. See World Cities Global Governance Globalization Governmentality Gramsci, Antonio Grand Coalition Granovetter, Mark Groupthink Growth Coalitions Growth Machine. See Growth Coalitions Gunboat Diplomacy Jessop, Bob Jost, John Jursidictions and StructureInduced Equilibria Justice Habermas, Jürgen Habitus Hall, Judith A. Harsanyi, John C. Haugaard, Mark Hegemonic Power Hegemonic War Hegemony Heresthetics Heterosexism, Role of Power in Hierarchy Hobbes, Thomas Holler, Manfred Homogeneous Weighted Majority Games Human Dominance Motivation Hunter, Floyd Idealism in International Relations Ideas Ideology Imperial Power Knowledge and Power Kropotkin, Peter Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal Language and Power Lasswell, Harold Leadership Leadership and Gender League of Nations Legislative Power Legitimation Lewin, Kurt, and Power Liberalism Loyalty Luck Luck, Brute Luhmann, Niklas Lukes, Steven Machiavelli, Niccolò Machine. See Dispositif Machover, Moshé Manipulation Mann, Michael Martin. See Martin Index Martin Index Marx, Karl Marxist Accounts of Power McClelland, David Mechanisms Media, The Michels, Robert Miliband, Ralph Miliband–Poulantzas Debate List of Entries Military in Government Mills, C. Wright Minimal Winning Coalition Mobilization of Bias Monopoly Power Moral Hazard Morgenthau, Hans J. Morriss, Peter Multinational Corporations Mutually Assured Destruction Nash Equilibrium Nationalism Neocorporatism. See Corporatism Neoliberalism Neorealism Networks, Power in Networks and Communities Nietzsche, Friedrich Non Decision Making Noncooperative Games Nonverbal Communication and Power Offense/Defense Dominance Offensive Realism. See Defensive Realism Opportunity Organization of the State Owen Value Paradox of New Members Parsons, Talcott Parties, Policy-Seeking Versus Power-Seeking Parties, Strong and Very Strong Paternalism Penrose Voting Power Measure Perceptual Symbols of Power Persuasion Pivot Player Pivotal Politics Pluralism Police State Policy Entrepreneurs Political Entrepreneurs. See Policy Entrepreneurs Political Legitimacy Political Parties Political Thinking as Power Post-Fordism Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Poulantzas, Nicos Power, Cognition, and Behavior Power as Control Theory Power as Influence. See I-Power Power as Prize. See P-Power Power Elite Power Indices Power Laws Power Motive Power To and Power Over Power to Initiate Action and Power to Prevent Action Power Transition Theory Power With P-Power Preference Versus Nonpreference-Based Concepts Prime Ministerial and Presidential Principal–Agent Relationship Prisoner’s Dilemma Propaganda Proper Simple Game Psychological Empowerment Public Goods Public Goods Index Qualified Majority Voting Quarreling Paradox Queer Theories of Power Racism, Role of Power in Rationality Raven, Bertram Realism in International Relations Realist Accounts of Power Referendums Regime Theory in International Relations Regime Theory in Urban Politics Relational Power Relative Autonomy of the State ix Religious Power Reputational Analysis Resources as Measuring Power Responsibility Revolution Revolutionary Cell Structure Rhetoric Right-Wing Authoritarianism Riker, William H. Riots Sabatier, Paul Scope Scott, James Sea Power Second Dimension. See Second Face Second Face Security Security Dilemma Separation of Powers Sexism, Role of Power in Shapley Value Shapley–Shubik Index Shareholder Voting Power Simple Games Small Worlds, Power in Social Breakdown Social Capital Social Dominance Theory Social Exchange Theory. See Exchange Theory Social Power Sovereignty Spatial Voting Analysis Spence, Janet Spiral Model Sprout, Harold Square Root Rules Status Strategic Interaction in International Relations Strategic Power Index Strength of Weak Links. See Strength of Weak Ties Strength of Weak Ties Striving for Superiority Structural Power Structural Suggestion Structuration x List of Entries Structure-Induced Equilibrium Submissive Subordination Substructure and Superstructure Swing Player. See Ability Symbolic Power and Violence System Justification Theory Systematic Luck Systemic Power Throffers Tijs Value Totalitarianism Trade Transactional and Transformational Leadership Transnational Corporations. See Multinational Corporations Trust Terror Regimes Terrorism Testosterone, Power and Third Dimension. See Third Face Third Face Threats Three Faces of Power Unicameral Legislature Unintended Consequences U.S. Electoral College, Power in Value of a Game Variable-Sum Games Vehicle Fallacy Veiled Women Veto Players Veto Power Vote-Maximizing Parties Voting Voting Paradoxes Voting Power Waltz, Kenneth War Weber, Max Weighted Majority Game Weighted Voting Wight, Martin Will to Power Wolfers, Arnold Women as Political Leaders World Cities Wright, Quincy Reader’s Guide Biography Adler, Alfred Adorno, Theodor Althusser, Louis Arendt, Hannah Aristotle Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton Bakunin, Mikhail Barry, Brian Bourdieu, Pierre Bull, Hedley Carr, E. H. Cartwright, Dorwin Castells, Manuel Clausewitz, Carl von Clegg, Stewart Coleman, James S. Cox, Robert W. Dahl, Robert A. Deutsch, Karl Domhoff, G. William Dowding, Keith Eagly, Alice Felsenthal, Dan S. Fiske, Susan Flyvbjerg, Bent Foucault, Michel French, John R. P., Jr. Giddens, Anthony Gramsci, Antonio Granovetter, Mark Habermas, Jürgen Hall, Judith A. Harsanyi, John C. Haugaard, Mark Hobbes, Thomas Holler, Manfred Hunter, Floyd Jessop, Bob Jost, John Kropotkin, Peter Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal Lasswell, Harold Lewin, Kurt, and Power Luhmann, Niklas Lukes, Steven Machiavelli, Niccolò Machover, Moshé Mann, Michael Marx, Karl McClelland, David Michels, Robert Miliband, Ralph Mills, C. Wright Morgenthau, Hans J. Morriss, Peter Nietzsche, Friedrich Parsons, Talcott Poulantzas, Nicos Raven, Bertram Riker, William H. Sabatier, Paul Scott, James Spence, Janet Sprout, Harold Waltz, Kenneth Weber, Max Wight, Martin Wolfers, Arnold Wright, Quincy Concepts Related to Power Ability Ableness Absolutism Adverse Selection xi Agency Agenda Power Agenda Setters Argument, Power of Authority Autonomy Bargaining Blackmail Bureaucratic Power Cabal Capability Capital, Marxist Causation Coercion, Analytic Coercion and Power Collective Action Problem Complex Equality (Walzer) Consent Control Cooperation Coordination Corruption Decentering (of Subject, of Structure) Deflected Wants Deliberation Determinacy Determinism Discipline Discourse Dispositif Domain Domination Entrepreneurs Exclusion Exercise Fallacy Exit and Voice as Forms of Power xii Reader’s Guide Expectancy Confirmation, Power and Exploitation Fair Division False Consciousness Fear, Use of Female Leadership Among Mammals Free Market Free Will Freedom Governmentality Habitus Hegemony Hierarchy Ideas Ideology Influence Interests Invisible Hand Leadership Legitimation Loyalty Luck Luck, Brute Manipulation Mechanisms Mobilization of Bias Moral Hazard Networks and Communities Nonverbal Communication and Power Opportunity Perceptual Symbols of Power Persuasion Pluralism Policy Entrepreneurs Political Thinking as Power Power Elite Power Motive Propaganda Public Goods Racism, Role of Power in Rationality Relative Autonomy of the State Responsibility Rhetoric Scope Second Face Social Capital Subjugation Submissive Subordination Systematic Luck Systemic Power Third Face Threats Throffers Trade Trust Unintended Consequences Vehicle Fallacy Will to Power Decisions and Game Theory Agenda Power Agenda Setters Banzhaf Value Banzhaf Voting Power Measure Bargaining Blocking Coalition Bribe Index Chicken Games Coalition Theory Coleman, James S. Coleman Index Computer Algorithms for Power Indices Core of a Game Dowding, Keith Fair Division Felsenthal, Dan S. Game Forms, Power in Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power Grand Coalition Gunboat Diplomacy Harsanyi, John C. Holler, Manfred Homogeneous Weighted Majority Games I-Power Jurisdictions and Structure-Induced Equilibria Machover, Moshé Martin Index Minimal Winning Coalition Mutually Assured Destruction Non Decision Making Noncooperative Games Owen Value Paradox of New Members Parties, Policy-Seeking Versus Power-Seeking Penrose Voting Power Measure Pivot Player Power Indices Power Laws Power to Initiate Action and Power to Prevent Action P-Power Preference Versus Nonpreference-Based Concepts Proper Simple Game Public Goods Index Qualified Majority Voting Quarreling Paradox Shapley Value Shapley–Shubik Index Shareholder Voting Power Simple Games Small Worlds, Power in Spatial Voting Analysis Square Root Rules Strategic Power Index Tijs Value U.S. Electoral College, Power in Value of a Game Variable-Sum Games Veto Players Veto Power Voting Paradoxes Voting Power Weighted Majority Game Weighted Voting Institutional Issues Agenda Power Agenda Setters Bicameral Legislature Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrats Bureaucratic Power Capture Theory of Regulation Central Intelligence Agency Corporatism Dominant Parties e-Governance Elections Federal Structure Internet and Power Reader’s Guide Leadership Media, The Organization of the State Political Parties Prime Ministerial and Presidential Principal–Agent Relationship Prisoner’s Dilemma Referendums Structure-Induced Equilibrium Unicameral Legislature U.S. Electoral College, Power in International Relations Alliances Anarchy in International Relations Appeasement Arms Race Balance of Power Banks Bargaining in International Relations Bull, Hedley Carr, E. H. Cartwright, Dorwin Chicken Games Civil War Clausewitz, Carl von Compliance (International) Constructivist View of Power in International Relations Conventional Deterrence Cox, Robert W. Cuban Missile Crisis Defensive Realism Dependency Theory in International Relations Deterrence Theory Deterrent Threats Deutsch, Karl Diplomacy Empire Environmental Treaties Espionage Executive Power Extended Deterrence Feminist International Relations, View of Power First-Strike Capability Gunboat Diplomacy Hegemonic Power Hegemonic War Hegemony Idealism in International Relations Imperial Power Imperialism Intelligence Lasswell, Harold League of Nations Military in Government Morgenthau, Hans J. Multinational Corporations Mutually Assured Destruction Neoliberalism Neorealism Offense/Defense Dominance Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Power Transition Theory Realism in International Relations Regime Theory in International Relations Sea Power Security Security Dilemma Separation of Powers Sovereignty Spiral Model Sprout, Harold Strategic Interaction in International Relations Terror Regimes Terrorism Waltz, Kenneth War Wight, Martin Wolfers, Arnold Wright, Quincy Interpersonal Relationships Agency–Structure Problem Authority Caste System (India) Chicken Games Deliberative Democracy Gender, Role of Power in Heterosexism, Role of Power in xiii Hierarchy Interdependence Theory Leadership and Gender Power as Control Theory Psychological Empowerment Submissive Veiled Women Intrapersonal Matters Agency Agency–Structure Problem Autonomy Bases of Power Free Will Gender, Role of Power in Interdependence Theory Leadership and Gender Psychological Empowerment Submissive Key Debates Agency–Structure Problem Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton Barry, Brian Bourdieu, Pierre Community Power Debate Consensual Power, Theories of Critical Theory Dahl, Robert A. Defensive Realism Deliberative Democracy Dependency Theory in International Relations Discourse Domhoff, G. William Domination Dowding, Keith Elite Theories Essentially Contested Concept Free Will Freedom Global Governance Hunter, Floyd Liberalism Luck Miliband, Ralph Miliband–Poulantzas Debate Mills, C. Wright xiv Reader’s Guide Mobilization of Bias Neoliberalism Neorealism Non Decision Making Organization of the State Pluralism Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Poulantzas, Nicos Power as Control Theory Power Elite Power To and Power Over Psychological Empowerment Queer Theories of Power Rationality Realism in International Relations Regime Theory in International Relations Regime Theory in Urban Politics Relative Autonomy of the State Resources as Measuring Power Second Face Social Dominance Theory Spiral Model Structural Power Structural Suggestion Structuration Three Faces of Power Transactional and Transformational Leadership Methodological Issues Adverse Selection Agency–Structure Problem Community Power Debate Essentially Contested Concept Exercise Fallacy False Consciousness Fungibility of Power Resources Mechanisms Pluralism Power Elite Power Laws Preference Versus Nonpreference-Based Concepts Principal–Agent Relationship Rationality Realism in International Relations Realist Accounts of Power Reputational Analysis Resources as Measuring Power Systematic Luck Third Face Three Faces of Power Political Science Agenda Power Agenda Setters Authority Banzhaf Value Bicameral Legislature Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrats Bureaucratic Power Business and Power Capital, Marxist Capital, Neoclassical Capture Theory of Regulation Central Intelligence Agency Civil War Coalition Theory Collective Action Problem Community Power Debate Core Parties Corporatism Coup d’État Dahl, Robert A. Democracy Dictatorship Dominant Parties Dowding, Keith e-Governance Elections Executive Power Fascism Federal Structure Global Governance Globalization Governmentality Grand Coalition Growth Coalitions Heresthetics Hierarchy Hunter, Floyd Intelligence Internet and Power Jursidictions and StructureInduced Equilibria Lasswell, Harold Leadership Legislative Power Liberalism Lukes, Steven Martin Index McClelland, David Michels, Robert Military in Government Mills, C. Wright Minimal Winning Coalition Morris, Peter Nationalism Organization of the State Parties, Policy-Seeking Versus Power-Seeking Parties, Strong and Very Strong Pivotal Politics Pluralism Police State Policy Entrepreneurs Political Parties Post-Fordism Power Elite Power To and Power Over Prime Ministerial and Presidential Principal–Agent Relationship Realist Accounts of Power Referendums Relative Autonomy of the State Revolution Revolutionary Cell Structure Right-Wing Authoritarianism Riker, William H. Riots Second Face Social Capital Social Power Spatial Voting Analysis Structural Power Structural Suggestion Structure-Induced Equilibrium Terror Regimes Terrorism Testosterone, Power and Totalitarianism Reader’s Guide Unicameral Legislature U.S. Electoral College, Power in Veiled Women Veto Players Vote-Maximizing Parties Voting Voting Paradoxes Voting Power Weber, Max Weighted Voting Women as Political Leaders Political Theory Agency–Structure Problem Anarchism, Power in Authority Barry, Brian Bourdieu, Pierre Capital, Marxist Capital, Neoclassical Castells, Manuel Deliberative Democracy Democracy Dispositif Distributive Justice Domhoff, G. William Dowding, Keith Freedom Global Governance Globalization Governmentality Gramsci, Antonio Habermas, Jürgen Hobbes, Thomas Hunter, Floyd Jessop, Bob Justice Liberalism Lukes, Steven Macchiavelli, Niccolò Marx, Karl Michels, Robert Miliband, Ralph Mills, C. Wright Morriss, Peter Nationalism Nietzsche, Friedrich Paternalism Pluralism Political Legitimacy Post-Fordism Poulantzas, Nicos Power Elite Power To and Power Over Power With Sabatier, Paul Scott, James Second Face Social Capital Social Power Sovereignty Structural Power Structural Suggestion Will to Power Social Psychology Adler, Alfred Authoritarian Personality Bases of Power Deflected Wants Eagly, Alice Expectancy Confirmation, Power and Fiske, Susan Framing French, John R. P., Jr. Granovetter, Mark Groupthink Hall, Judith A. Human Dominance Motivation Interdependence Theory Jost, John Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal Lewin, Kurt, and Power Power, Cognition, and Behavior Power as Control Theory Power Motive Psychological Empowerment Rationality Raven, Bertram Social Dominance Theory Status Striving for Superiority System Justification Theory Transactional and Transformational Leadership Social Theory Agency Agency–Structure Problem Biopower Caste System (India) Clegg, Stewart Decentering (of Subject, of Structure) Deliberation Flyvbjerg, Bent Foucault, Michel Free Will Giddens, Anthony Governmentality Groupthink Habermas, Jürgen Habitus Haugaard, Mark Jessop, Bob Luhmann, Niklas Lukes, Steven Mann, Michael Michels, Robert Miliband, Ralph Mills, C. Wright Morriss, Peter Nationalism Parsons, Talcott Perceptual Symbols of Power Post-Fordism Propaganda Rationality Realist Accounts of Power Revolution Rhetoric Right-Wing Authoritarianism Scott, James Second Face Small Worlds, Power in Social Breakdown Social Capital Substructure and Superstructure Status Strength of Weak Ties Structural Power Structural Suggestion Structuration Subjugation Trust Veiled Women xv xvi Reader’s Guide Weber, Max Will to Power Theories of Power Animal Groups, Power in Causal Theories of Power Coercion and Power Collective Action Problem Community Power Debate Elite Theories Exchange Theory Feminist International Relations, View of Power Feminist Theories of Power Marxist Accounts of Power Neoliberalism Neorealism Post-Fordism Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Power as Control Theory Power To and Power Over Queer Theories of Power Realism in International Relations Realist Accounts of Power Relational Power Social Power Striving for Superiority System Justification Theory Third Face Three Faces of Power Types of Power Animal Groups, Power in Consensual Power, Theories of Constructivist View of Power in International Relations Critical Theory Defensive Realism Deterrence Theory Elite Theories Exercise Fallacy Exploitation False Consciousness Female Leadership Among Mammals Fungibility of Power Resources Hegemonic Power Hegemony Heterosexism, Role of Power in Human Dominance Motivation Ideology Imperial Power Influence Invisible Hand Knowledge and Power Language and Power Legislative Power Manipulation Media, The Military in Government Mobilization of Bias Monopoly Power Networks, Power in Networks and Communities Nonverbal Communication and Power Perceptual Symbols of Power Persuasion Pluralism Police State Political Thinking as Power Power, Cognition, and Behavior Power as Control Theory Power Motive Power To and Power Over Power Transition Theory Power With Prime Ministerial and Presidential Propaganda Psychological Empowerment Regime Theory in International Relations Relational Power Relative Autonomy of the State Religious Power Revolutionary Cell Structure Rhetoric Sea Power Second Face Sexism, Role of Power in Social Capital Social Dominance Theory Social Power Striving for Superiority Subjugation Symbolic Power and Violence Systematic Luck Systemic Power Terrorism Testosterone, Power and Third Face Threats Three Faces of Power Throffers Transactional and Transformational Leadership Will to Power Urban Studies Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton Castells, Manuel Community Power Debate Dahl, Robert A. Domhoff, G. William Dowding, Keith Elite Theories Flyvbjerg, Bent Growth Coalitions Hunter, Floyd Lukes, Steven Mobilization of Bias Non Decision Making Pluralism Post-Fordism Power Elite Regime Theory in Urban Politics Sabatier, Paul Systematic Luck Systemic Power Third Face Three Faces of Power World Cities About the Editor Keith Dowding is Professor of Political Science in the School of Political Science and International Relations, Research School of Social Science, and Director of Research for the College of Arts and Social Science at the Australian National University. He has published extensively in political science, political philosophy, social choice theory, public administration, public policy, and urban politics in journals such as American Political Science Review, American Journal of Political Science, British Journal of Political Science, European Journal of Political Research, Journal of Politics, Public Choice, Public Administration, Rationality and Society, and Urban Studies Quarterly. He has published two books, Rational Choice and Political Power (1991) and Power (1996), and many articles on the subject of political power. He is on the boards of the Journal of Power and British Politics. In 2009, he coedited the fourvolume Rational Choice Classics for SAGE as well as The Selection of Ministers in Europe for Routledge, published under the auspices of the network of scholars Selection and De-Selection of Political Elites (SEDEPE), which he chairs. He has been coeditor of the Journal of Theoretical Politics since 1996. xvii Contributors Kate Allison University of Manchester André Azevedo Alves London School of Economics and Political Science Joseph Angolano London School of Economics and Political Science John Breuilly London School of Economics and Political Science Ian Carter University of Pavia Philip G. Cerny Rutgers University Andreas Antoniades University of Sussex Zsuzsanna Chappell London School of Economics and Political Science Stuart Astill London School of Economics and Political Science Brian D. Christens University of Wisconsin– Madison David A. Baldwin Princeton University Philip Cunliffe University of Kent Alex Bavister-Gould University of York Douglas J. Dallier Western Carolina University Coral Bell Australian National University Jennifer L. Berdahl University of Toronto Cesarino Bertini University of Bergamo Malgorzata Olimpia Bielenia Technical University of Gdansk Tanja A. Börzel Freie Universität, Berlin William Bosworth Australian National University Michael Dalvean Australian National University Philip H. J. Davies Brunel University Rekha Diwakar Goldsmiths College Andrew M. Dorman King’s College London Keith Dowding Australian National University Matthew Braham University of Groningen Lindy Edwards Australian Defence Force Academy, Canberra Steven J. Brams New York University Lina Eriksson Adelaide University xix Dan S. Felsenthal University of Haifa Jennifer Filson University of Minnesota Bryan Finken University of Colorado at Denver Susan Fiske Princeton University Michael Freeden University of Oxford Gianfranco Gambarelli University of Bergamo Azar Gat Tel Aviv University Peter Glick Lawrence University Dogan Göçmen University of London Gregg J. Gold Humboldt State University Brooke C. Greene Columbia University Catia Gregoratti Lund University Penny Griffin University of New South Wales Ana Guinote University College London Vsevolod Gunitskiy Columbia University xx Contributors Stefano Guzzini Danish Institute for International Studies & Uppsala University Judith A. Hall Northeastern University Mark Haugaard National University of Ireland, Galway Paul ‘t Hart Australian National University Mary Hawkesworth Rutgers University Jonathan Hearn University of Edinburgh Paul Henman University of Queensland Andrew Hindmoor University of Queensland Manfred J. Holler University of Hamburg Li-Ching Hung Overseas Chinese University György Hunyady Eötvòs Loránd University, Budapest Marc Kilgour Wilfrid Laurier University Helen Margetts University of Oxford Ruth Kinna Loughborough University Aaron Martin Australian National University Andrew James Klassen Australian National University Mathias Koenig-Archibugi London School of Economics and Political Science Edward A. Kolodziej University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign Bernd Lahno Frankfurt School of Finance & Management Valentino Larcinese London School of Economics and Political Science Dennis Leech University of Warwick Liane J. Leedom University of Bridgeport Chris Lewis Australian National University Robert H. Lieshout Radboud University Oliver James University of Exeter Johnson Y. K. Louie Australian National University Bob Jessop Lancaster University Melissa Lovell Australian National University Peter John University of Manchester Debra Lucas D’Youville College Christer Jönsson Lund University Moshé Machover University College London Jonathan Joseph University of Kent John Madeley London School of Economics and Political Science John T. Jost New York University André Kaiser University of Cologne Martín A. Maldonado Universidad Católica de Córdoba Alem S. Kebede California State University, Bakersfield Siniša Maleševic´ National University of Ireland, Galway Matt Matravers University of York Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland, Baltimore County Patit Paban Mishra Sambalpur University Maria Montero University of Nottingham Peter Morriss National University of Ireland, Galway Vanessa E. Munro University of London, King’s College Stefan Napel University of Hamburg Sik Hung Ng City University of Hong Kong Hannu Nurmi University of Turku Rosemary H. T. O’Kane Keele University Adam Packer Australian National University Pamela Pansardi University of Pavia Fioravante Patrone University of Genoa Hans Peters University of Maastricht Bertram H. Raven University of California, Los Angeles Ingrid Robeyns Erasmus University Rotterdam Contributors Daniel Rubenson Ryerson University Caryl E. Rusbult Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Kevin Ryan National University of Ireland, Galway Lawrence Sáez London School of Economics and Political Science Izabella Stach AGH University of Science and Technology, Krakow Steven J. Stanton University of Michigan Bernard Steunenberg Leiden University Kennedy Stewart Simon Fraser University xxi Bert van den Brink Utrecht University Jan-Willem van der Rijt University of Groningen Jojanneke van der Toorn New York University Peter van der Windt Columbia University Ignacio Sánchez-Cuenca Juan March Institute David Strecker Friedrich-Schiller-Universitaet Jena Stephen Van Evera Massachusetts Institute of Technology Michael Saward Open University Doug Stuart Dickinson College Paul A. M. Van Lange Free University Amsterdam Darrow Schecter University of Sussex Gita Subrahmanyam London School of Economics and Political Science Bertjan Verbeek Radboud University Nijmegen Ralph Schroeder University of Oxford Oliver C. Schultheiss Friedrich-Alexander University Len Scott University of Wales, Aberystwyth Maija Setälä University of Turku Ngai-Ling Ivin Sum Lancaster University David L. Swartz Boston University Patricia Lee Sykes American University James Stacey Taylor College of New Jersey Andreas Warntjen University of Twente Patricia A. Weitsman Ohio University David West Australian National University Garrath Williams Lancaster University Jeffrey D. Wilson Australian National University Julia Skorupska University of Oxford Jessica Templeton London School of Economics and Political Science Cary Stacy Smith Mississippi State University Geoffrey Till King’s College London Peter Wilson London School of Economics and Political Science Mark Snyder University of Minnesota Jacob Torfing Roskilde University David G. Winter University of Michigan Arthur Spirling Harvard University John Uhr Australian National University Chris Wyatt University of Brighton Introduction Power is a ubiquitous theme in the social sciences, not only as a topic in its own right, but also as an issue that underlies many debates and questions that do not explicitly address it. I believe this is the first Encyclopedia of Power to be found in the social sciences; it continues the SAGE Encyclopedia series providing a comprehensive coverage of disciplines and themes in the social sciences. The encyclopedia includes entries from political science, international relations, public administration, public policy, urban studies, sociology, social psychology, cultural studies, some also from the viewpoint of economics and studies of animal behavior. Encyclopedias typically offer summaries and discussions of topics rather than the cuttingedge research presented in a handbook. Nevertheless, many of our entries are by leading scholars in their respective fields, and they have been encouraged to give their own take on the issues as well as summarizing the current state of knowledge. In addition to the longer entries, in keeping with the SAGE series we also have numerous shorter entries. Some of these expand on concepts touched on in the longer entries, and others offer insights into key concepts related more generally to the field of power. Many encyclopedias in the SAGE series are fields of study—Geography, Social Theory, Political Science, and so on—whereas this one is concerned with a specific concept within social science. However, as the entries herein demonstrate, that concept has been treated quite differently within different fields of study, while we find similar controversies and debates about the concept across fields of study. Providing a single encyclopedia where these contrasting or converging debates and ideas are laid out supplies a ready source of knowledge for scholars working in different fields. Ideas from different fields of study can be “taken for a walk” into new areas for mutual benefit and innovation. Although all of the relevant social sciences are covered in their accounts of power, the bulk of the entries relate to political science (and related subdisciplines such as public administration and urban studies), international relations, and sociology. I make no apology for that fact because power lends itself to those disciplines more directly than to others, and there has been far more debate explicitly about power in those three. We also have a large number of formal entries concerned with decision- and game-theoretic measures of power. One reason for the large number in this field is the subtleties of the concept of power that have been formalized and applied particularly in economics, politics, and international relations, though there has also been some application in sociology. Some of these entries provide shorter definitions of technical terms that appear in longer formal entries. I will begin with a general introduction to the idea of power in the social sciences that introduces the types of debates that we find in all fields of study. I will then discuss the organization and use of the encyclopedia, explaining the rationale of the listing in the Reader’s Guide. Main Themes in the Study of Power Power can be personal, social, or institutional. It can involve conflict where one forces another to behave in ways the second does not wish, or can be consensual where agents achieve more together than they could alone. It can be thought of as a property of people, or of institutions or other social objects. For some, it can be measured and analyzed; for others, it is a concept that will forever remain partly mysterious and always qualitative. In some areas of social science, the concept of xxiii xxiv Introduction power has almost completely disappeared, reduced to component parts such as resources, or analyzed in terms of strategic interaction where the term power has become redundant. I will briefly consider 10 interwoven and overlapping debates or controversies that cut across many fields of study. A major debate concerns the issues of whether power is a property of agents—whether these are people or institutions—or a property of the relations between agents, the structure of society or groups. Much discussed in sociology and political science, the issue also concerns social psychology where questions about the nature of agency perform a key role. To what extent can we predict agency by influences around people and subtle influences outside of their ken, and how far are people in control? These issues shade into a second question about the nature of autonomy and free will. Even if we see power as a property of people, their actions might still be determined by the environment around them. In many disciplines, the nature and scope of constraints upon action and the causes of beliefs and actions constitute important elements in explanation of social outcomes. Power then can be seen as personal or institutional or as agency-based or structural. Another theme that pervades all disciplines is whether power is exclusively a descriptive or positive term, or whether it is normatively implicated. In cultural studies, sociology and political theory especially, how far it is possible to produce theory-free or nonnormative accounts of power is hotly disputed. In international relations too, the types of theories that are used to describe and explain relationships between nations are normatively implicated in how theorists view power. Here, for example, realists believe that power relations can be objectively defined in terms of the strategic concerns of nations, whereas constructivists believe that we construct the nature of the conflict, which determines actions, and different nations might construct the international system differently. See the entries on realism and constructivism for a much more nuanced and careful study of these theories. The normative nature of power means that it is implicated in different theories in different sorts of ways, and this partly explains different conceptions. The normative force of concepts such as power helps explain another set of concerns. Some analysts see power in terms of one set of agents’ power over others (or the power of structure over people); others see that form of power as a subset of power that is descriptive of what people can achieve. Thus, “power over” versus “power to” is a theme running through many debates. In a related sense, some writers concentrate on power as a notion concerning conflict. Where agents have interests at variance with each other, they come into conflict and here power plays out to the advantage of the strongest. Others see power more in consensual terms where working together leads people to achieve more than they could on their own. The reader should read different accounts of power in terms of power to and power over, conflictual or consensual, or in terms of both. Some believe that power, being a somewhat mysterious notion, is impossible to quantify. Others believe that it can be quantified, if only roughly, often in terms of the resources that agents bring to situations of conflict or consensus. The mathematical and decision-theoretic formalizations of power are attempts to quantify theoretically and have been applied most thoroughly to voting power. Strategic considerations also enter into such formalizations through game-theoretic interactions of agents. Taken to its extreme, power can disappear from social scientific analysis if it is reduced to resources and strategies in games—or rather, the term power disappears, reduced to other, more quantifiable and measurable entities. The purpose of such analysis will reveal power even if the term does not appear in the analysis itself. Many other concepts in the social sciences are related to power, though they are neither reducible to power nor is power reducible to them. Freedom, ability, and capability are three such concepts. Many entries here discuss the relationship between power and such terms, as well as discussing the role of power in grand social scientific theories, whether they be normative, such as liberalism, or positive, such as pluralism. The Reader’s Guide The encyclopedia has 381 entries ranging from about 400 words to 4,000 words in length, written by 157 authors from 17 countries (Australia, Canada, Denmark, Finland, Germany, Hungary, Introduction India, Ireland, Israel, Italy, the Netherlands, Poland, Spain, Sweden, Taiwan, the United States, and the United Kingdom). We have a very broad coverage of the field, and no area, I believe, has been ignored, though the difficulty of finding authors to provide entries on some topics means that some entries I would like to have included have had to be omitted. The editorial board of five each assisted the editor in selecting topics, authors for those topics, and in some cases helped edit the entries. Of the board members, Nicholas Miller deserves special mention for his extensive work in editing the decision- and game-theoretic entries to ensure consistency in algebraic formulation throughout the work. I am deeply appreciative of his help. I have developed a guide to assist readers in their examination of entries and will explain the rationale behind it. The groupings are not mutually exclusive, and many entries appear in more than one category. Some categories are relatively straightforward: Biography, International Relations, Key Debates, Political Science, Political Theory, Social Psychology, Social Theory (whose disciplinary home largely is sociology), and Urban Studies are largely self-explanatory. In Biography, we have a fairly long list of names of major figures in power studies, again dominated by those in politics, international relations, and sociology. Key Debates lists entries that are devoted to a specific debate—some between a relatively limited set of authors, others more general. The other categories just listed are all entries that are discipline-based. Some entries will occur under several of those categories: what constitutes Political Science, Political Theory, or Social Theory is somewhat fluid, with some entries belonging exclusively to one category but others being discussed across all three disciplines. International Relations and Social Psychology tend to contain more exclusive entries, whereas many of those under Urban Studies are also listed under Political Science. Other categories are not disciplinary but themebased. Under Concepts Related to Power, we have entries on concepts that are subsets of power, such as “Bureaucratic Power” or “False Consciousness.” Some are terms closely related to power, such as “Coercion, Analytic” or “Systematic Luck.” Others are technical or quasitechnical terms that denote ways of considering power or are used in xxv the explanation of a particular approach to power; “Ableness” is a good example. Others have more tenuous connections to power itself but are important in ways of looking at power and are usually mentioned in longer entries; “Adverse Selection” and “Dispositif” are examples of such terms. Others still are broader concepts and the way in which one views these concepts will affect how one conceptualizes power; for example, “Rationality.” Institutional Issues entries refer to organizations or ways of organizing the state and how this affects power—such as “Federal Structure” and “Media, The”—or they refer to power relations that are affected by institutions—“Bureaucratic Power” and “Internet and Power,” for example. The Interpersonal Relationships category refers to power relations between people; for example, “Interdependence Theory” is about how relations between people affect power and the ways in which people look at themselves; although Intrapersonal Matters entries are those that come largely though not exclusively from social psychology, and refer to entries that affect individuals’ abilities to do what they want—or whether their wants are a reflection of something else in society; thus, “Agency” and “Psychological Empowerment” are included in this category. Methodological Issues is a category for methodological issues in power studies or sometimes specific models or ways of looking at power relations that affect how we view power. Two of the categories are Theories of Power and Types of Power. The former is concerned with grand theories about the power structure or midrange theory or models that examine specific aspects of power. An example of the first is “Feminist Theories of Power”; an example of the second is the “Collective Action Problem.” Types of Power is concerned more with specific means by which power is generated, thus “Exploitation” makes its home in this category, as does “Manipulation.” Again, however, the entries are rather fluid and some are contained within both of the categories. The Decisions and Game Theory category is a vital one for this encyclopedia. Formal writers have mathematically defined the nature of power within voting games and committees. These entries try to formalize power for clarity and quantification. Many of these entries appear only xxvi Introduction in this section. Merely because the notion of power has been formalized mathematically does not mean that controversy over the concept can be overcome. Many of the issues that arise in less formalized approaches remain. Issues arise over whether power should be defined in terms of what can be done no matter what actors’ preferences are, or whether it should be defined in terms of what agents’ actually are. Structural and agential issues arise here too. Some have tried to take the formalized account of power out of the context of voting within committee and across parties within parliaments and apply their results to society more widely. This is a dynamic and growing program. The Encyclopedia of Power covers most aspects of power in society as a whole. Undoubtedly some issues have been left aside and some covered in more depth than others. That will always be the case with an enterprise such as this. However, the encyclopedia provides the reader with all the major and central debates and covers all the main issues with regard to power in society. Happy reading. Acknowledgments This project has taken longer than originally projected, not helped by my move from the London School of Economics and Political Science to the Australian National University. I would like to thank members of the SAGE team in California who have kept the encyclopedia on track while I was distracted and have ensured its steady transition from drafts to final copy, including Diana Axelsen, Alan Cook, Robin Gold, Leticia Gutierrez, Laura Notton, Yvette Pollastrini, Kate Schroeder, and especially Sanford Robinson. I have already mentioned the sterling support provided by Nick Miller of the editorial board. I would also like to thank Lucy Robinson who first approached me to run this project and Rolf Janke who together with Lucy discussed the project in the early stages and commissioned it. I would also like to thank Anne Gelling who helped me at the first editing and checking stage of the entire set of entries. Keith Dowding Australian National University A Yet, typically, abilities are the sorts of things that can be exercised: they require a choice. It is up to you whether to read. But, when you choose not to, you retain the ability. This sometimes creates difficulties in deciding whether an ability is present or not because an ability claim is of the form that you could have done X, not that you did do X, and establishing the truth or falsity of such statements is more difficult than it is for statements about what did happen. But, difficult or not, it has to be done and can be done. The ability approach to power can apply to both power to and power over. Although it is more normally associated with power to (because that is what Morriss concentrated on), someone who has power over someone else also has a particular sort of ability. Thus, if a master has power over his or her slaves, the master can get the slaves to do a large range of things, some of which are mutually incompatible; it is up to the master which of this range of things he or she gets the slaves to do. Power as an ability is thus different from two other concepts. First, as a dispositional concept, power as an ability is different from the action of exercising power. Second, it is different from a pure disposition or “natural power”—one that is not subject to the actor’s choice, such as the capacity to perform reflex actions under appropriate stimuli. It follows that when we consider the power of nonhuman actors (such as institutions or countries), only those that can be said to form intentions and make choices can have power-as-ability. A PRIORI UNIONS See Owen Value ABILITY Often when we talk of a person’s power, we are simply referring to what they can do or have the ability to do. This is the idea behind the ability approach to power, which is associated with Peter Morriss. Abilities are capacities, or dispositions. This means that they exist over an extended period. During the period that they exist, they may remain unexercised for much, or even all, of the time. Thus, you (probably) have the ability to read English. If you were to spend the next year doing anthropological fieldwork in deepest Borneo, you might not exercise this ability (because there is nothing there in English for you to read), yet you would retain the ability to read English. Abilities are also acquired and lost. When you were 3 months old, you did not have the ability to read English; you subsequently acquired it. Conversely, after you had spent 30 years with that tribe in Borneo, you might well have lost the ability to read English. But losing an ability is very different from not exercising it. On the ability account of power, what matters is what abilities you have, not what abilities you are exercising. Peter Morriss 1 2 Ableness See also Ableness; Exercise Fallacy; Morriss, Peter; Power To and Power Over Further Readings Morriss, P. (2002). Power: A philosophical analysis (2nd ed.). Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. ABLENESS The term ableness was introduced into the literature by Peter Morriss to describe a refinement in the ability account of power. The idea is that there is an ambiguity in how we normally talk of abilities. Abilities can refer to what you can, in general, do: you can, let us say, read English. But we are often interested, not in such generic abilities, but in what you can do now. Or more generally, we are often interested in your abilities at some specified time, t. What you can do at time t will depend on the particular circumstances that exist at t, and those circumstances might be unusual. So, although you are able (generically) to read English, you would not be able to do so at time t if, at that time, you do not have your reading glasses with you. Without your glasses, let us suppose, you are not able to read anything. To mark this distinction, Morriss used the word ability to refer to the generic sense, and ableness for the time-specific sense. So, without your glasses, you have the ability to read, but lack the ableness. Confusion can arise if we do not mark this distinction. If, at a time when you do not have your glasses, someone were to ask you if you are able to read, you might not know how to reply: if the questioner is conducting a literacy survey, he or she will be enquiring after the ability to read, but if he or she needs you to read something right now, then he or she is asking after your ableness. Here the context makes clear which is meant; in more abstract academic work, there is no context, and so clarity requires us to state which sense is to be understood. Similarly, lack of power can be either lack of ability or lack of ableness. The poor have the ability to dine on caviar and champagne (because they could consume them if they were provided), but they lack the ableness (for they are not provided, and the poor cannot get them). This example suggests that for most political purposes, ableness is more important than is ability: usually what people are able to do with the goods they do have is what interests us, rather than what they would be able to do with a “standard” allocation of goods. This example shows why Morriss used the term ableness rather than time-specific ability. For the distinction does not rest on whether a time is specified: the poor can never afford champagne. What the distinction does rest on is that ableness refers to a set of actually existing background conditions, whereas abilities are established by reference to some set of hypothetical, standardized, background conditions. Peter Morriss See also Ability; Morriss, Peter Further Readings Dowding, K., & van Hees, M. (2008). Freedom, coercion and ability. In M. Braham & F. Steffen (Eds.), Power, freedom and voting. Berlin: Springer. Morriss, P. (2002). Power: A philosophical analysis (2nd ed.). Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. ABSOLUTISM In the 17th and 18th centuries, various European monarchs claimed absolute powers within their states. Monarchs claimed a divine right to rule with their subjects having no claim to limit their powers. The Danish “King’s Law” of 1665 states that the monarch was the most perfect and supreme person and stood above all human laws, having no judge above him apart from God. Louis XIV of France is claimed to have stated, “L’État c’est moi” (“the state is me”). The Russian tsars Ivan III, Ivan IV, Peter the Great, and Catherine the Great all had absolute powers; Russia had no parliament until 1905. Even in the 1906 constitution, the tsar is described as an autocrat. Similarly, absolute monarchs ruled in Austria, Portugal, Prussia, and Sweden. The term absolutism is thus often used to describe the nature of the state in these countries at Adler, Alfred this time. These monarchs had great formal powers, which in practice extended to closing down other power centers, emasculating parliaments, creating powerful bureaucracies and standing armies, and generally centralizing power to a greater extent than previously happened. This was the time when many European nation-states were formed, though not all had absolutist rulers. The English Civil War was caused by Charles I’s attempt to assert absolutist powers. The idea of a single supreme sovereign power was an influential doctrine given rational rather than religious justification by Thomas Hobbes, precisely because of the fear that divided sovereignty would lead to discord, strife, and civil war. Even Hobbes, though, argued that sovereigns cannot arbitrarily take the life of subjects: that is one power too far because undivided sovereignty is justified by the security it brings. The power of these monarchs can be overemphasized. Certainly there were other centers of power, notably the churches and nobility, though absolutist monarchs attempted to enfeeble the latter by requiring them to work with state officials on their lands. Although the idea of absolutism was established at this time, it is not clear that the absolute rulers had significantly greater power than other rulers. Absolute rulers still needed to negotiate with barons and with the church and were beholden to powerful figures within their palaces and bureaucracies. Keith Dowding See also Bureaucratic Power; Hobbes, Thomas Further Readings Anderson, P. (1974). Lineages of the absolute state. London: Verso. Mettam, R. (1988). Power and faction in Louis XIV’s France. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Miller, J. (1990). Absolutism in seventeenth-century Europe. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. ADLER, ALFRED (1870–1937) Alfred Adler is known as the founder of a school of individual psychology. He was born into a 3 Jewish family on February 7, 1870, in Penzing, a suburb of Vienna, and at an early age decided to become a physician. After graduating in medicine from the University of Vienna in 1895, he became an ophthalmologist, but soon switched to general practice, in which he began to study the linkage of illness and physical deformities to personality development. In 1902, he was invited to join a discussion group that had been initiated by the pioneering Viennese psychoanalyst Sigmund Freud (1856–1939). Adler, Freud, and two other psychoanalysts met on Wednesday evenings initially, and the group came to be known Mittwochsgesellschaft (Wednesday Society). Adler’s book, Study of Organ Inferiority and Its Physical Compensation, was published in 1907. He became the coeditor of the society’s newsletter and, in 1910, Adler was named president of the Vienna Psychoanalytic Society. Adler’s perception of human behavior and personality differed from Freud’s. Adler challenged Freud’s concept of ego and id and Freud’s belief that sexuality was the root cause of neurosis; Adler contended that the social realm, or exteriority, was as important to psychoanalysis as any internal realm, or interiority. Adler promoted the importance of perceiving an individual holistically, rather than reductively. In 1911, Adler parted company with Freud and his circle and, along with nine of his associates, established the Society for Free Psychoanalysis, shortly thereafter renamed as the Society for Individual Psychology. In 1912, Adler published his seminal treatise, The Neurotic Constitution, describing his main ideas. During World War I, Adler served as a doctor in the Austrian army on the Russian front. Later, Adler wrote numerous books on psychology and organized counseling centers in the Vienna schools. As a theorist of human psychology, Adler dealt exhaustively in psychotherapy, personality theory, and social action. Between 1907 and 1937 he developed theories regarding the inferiority complex, superiority complex, and psychological compensation as well as the relationship between body, mind, and spirit. Adler believed inferiority and superiority complexes were two sides of the same coin. The feeling of superiority was the fruit of a striving whose roots lay in the inferiority complex. Moreover, each human emotion found expression in one’s body language, a manifestation of the 4 Adorno, Theodor close connection between mind and body. Adler’s social theory arose from his conviction, based on observation, that to be understood, an individual must be viewed within a social context. Adler’s psychotherapy agenda included information about the lifestyle of patients, self-explanation of patients, and encouragement of the patient’s social interests. Adler thought it important to avoid conveying an authoritarian attitude. His method was to speak face to face with the patient, unlike the Freudian method in which the patient lay on a couch and the analyst sat in a chair not directly facing the patient. In 1934, Adler emigrated to the United States following the forced closure of his clinics under Nazi policies that targeted Jews and those of Jewish heritage for persecution. While on a European tour in 1937, he died of a heart attack én route to a lecture at Aberdeen University in Scotland. Among those on whom Adler’s work has exerted an enormous influence are the American psychologists Abraham Maslow (1908–1970), Rollo May (1909–1994), and Albert Ellis (1913–2007). Patit Paban Mishra See also Striving for Superiority; Submissive Further Readings Adler, A. (1956). The individual psychology of Alfred Adler: A systematic presentation in selections from his writings. New York: Basic Books. Crandall, J. E. (1981). Theory and measurement of social interest: Empirical tests of Alfred Adler’s concept. New York: Columbia University Press. Grey, L. (1998). Alfred Adler, the forgotten prophet: A vision for the 21st century. Westport, CT: Praeger. Rattner, J. (1983). Alfred Adler. New York: F. Ungar. ADORNO, THEODOR (1903–1969) Together with Max Horkheimer, Theodor Weisengrund Adorno was the main representative of the critical social theory of the Frankfurt School. As a theorist of power, Adorno is perhaps best characterized as an early post-Marxist. As a scholar, his aim was a critical theory of modern society that analyzed its social pathologies from an evaluative standpoint inspired by emancipatory, utopian interests. All this he shared with Karl Marx. Different from Marx, Adorno analyzed pathological power relations in terms of the dominance of a one-sided instrumental rationalization of modernity that leaves no room for genuine self-government and self-realization. According to Adorno, capitalistic economic relations are just one instantiation of this deeper social pathology of modernity. Bureaucratic power and the culture industry are two others. The control, discipline, social categorization, and amusement they offer reconcile people with the reifying functional requirements of capitalism and stand in the way of genuine freedom. Adorno inherited his focus on rationality and reason rather than on socioeconomic issues from German idealism, most importantly from Georg Wilhelm Friederich Hegel. In its sociotheoretical consequences, Max Weber’s influence is strong. With Horkheimer, Adorno developed a critique of instrumental rationality in Dialectic of Enlightenment. Their main thesis is that in striving for enlightenment—individual and collective freedom through the use of reason—humans are doomed to lose the very freedom they are after. Immediate and uncontrolled desires, bodily experience, and aesthetical awe for nature have to give way to instrumentalizing forms of control by means of which we preserve and govern ourselves. This control is power. It forces us to objectify ourselves, others, and nature and thus reify ourselves, others, and nature. We need to exercise power in our struggle to be free, but in exercising power we necessarily alienate ourselves from the non-instrumentalizing relations to self, others, and nature that are a precondition of genuine freedom. As in the writings of Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche and Weber, Adorno’s rationalized modern person has lost all orientation in life. In the 1930s and 1940s, Adorno, who with most of his colleagues from Frankfurt had to flee Nazi Germany, lost all socialist hopes of a revolution of the proletariat against failed modernity. He understood National Socialism as the disappointed masses’ escape into a quasi-mythical system that promised to restore the meaning and sentient freedom that modernity had destroyed. Adorno noted that the proletariat happily accepted this devastating Adverse Selection modern myth. He explained the Holocaust as part of this quasi-mythical struggle against failed modernity, of which the Jews were presented as the main architects. Adorno never developed a systematic theory of nonpathological rationalization, or productive power, as his junior colleague and later successor in Frankfurt Jürgen Habermas did in his Theory of Communicative Action (1981). For glimpses of freedom from arbitrary power, Adorno rather set his hopes on an extra-theoretical form of ethical reflection (Minima Moralia, 1974), a critique of identity thinking, deconstructing the power that generalizing concepts have over our particular experience of the world (Negative Dialectics, 1966), and an understanding of the aesthetical experience as a last resort for a critique of rationality. “The falsehood opposed by art is not rationality per se but the fixed opposition of rationality to particularity” (Aesthetic Theory, 1970). Bert van den Brink See also Critical Theory; Habermas, Jürgen; Weber, Max Further Readings Adorno, T. W. (1973). Negative dialectics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Original work published 1966) Bernstein, J. M. (2001). Adorno: Disenchantment and ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press. Honneth, A. (1993). The critique of power. Cambridge: MIT Press. Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. W. (1972). Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Allen Lane. (Original work published 1944) ADVERSE SELECTION Gresham’s law states that bad money drives out good and is the classic expression of adverse selection. In the days when coins were composed of real silver, their holders might shave a small sliver off before using the coin in exchange. Everyone realized that any coin one received might have been shaved in this manner, so people were not prepared to exchange as much for any coin as they 5 would for a coin they knew had not been shaved. Knowing this, those who held unshaved coins would then not spend them or would shave them before using them. Bad money drives out good. The idea of adverse selection is now a key aspect of economic theory. George Akerlof reintroduced the idea of adverse selection in his classic article based on the used-car market. In his version, every car owner knows whether his car is a good one; however, the buyer is unsure. Good cars are worth a high price to both buyer and seller, but because buyers do not know if used cars are good or bad, they will only pay the amount of a bad car. Thus, good cars will not come on the market. Adverse selection in the health market, for example, will come about because those who know that they have or are likely to have health problems are those who are keenest on getting health insurance. The problem arises because, as in the coin and car examples, there is asymmetry of information: one contractor knows more about himself or herself than does the other. However, the other contractor can realize that there is this informational asymmetry and respond. Insurance companies need to price their products on the assumption that there will be adverse selection, making insurance in the health case more expensive for those who are not so likely to have health problems. Of course, insurance companies can also attempt to gain information, by running health checks on applicants, and making their customers pay a certain percentage of health costs on top of their insurance premium. The idea of adverse selection is used as part of the principal–agent problem, a problem of contracting. In the principal–agent problem, adverse selection occurs because those least qualified for a job are also those most keen to attain it. At any level of remuneration, those least qualified are likely to gain the most in comparison to the job they already have and thus be more eager to get the job. They will sell themselves more and work harder to secure the position. Adverse selection only occurs where there is heterogeneity in the population of qualified candidates, and those with some characteristics that the principal does not want are most likely to be those who come forward. In general, we can see adverse selection as an informational problem that gives one person some power over another to the latter’s disadvantage. In 6 Agency that sense, this is an example of the idea that “knowledge is power.” agency. Collective agency is therefore discussed toward the end of this entry. Keith Dowding See also Knowledge and Power; Moral Hazard; Principal–Agent Relationship Further Readings Akerlof, G. (1970). The market for lemons: Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84(3), 488–500. AGENCY Agency plays a central role in social science and yet, outside of ethical theory, it is rarely discussed except in the context of the agency–structure problem. Agency has an obvious relationship to certain understandings of power. Agents have effects on the world through their actions. Outcome power is often defined as the extent to which agents could affect the world. In that sense, the degree of individual agency specifies an agent’s outcome power. However, delving deeper into the concept of agency itself raises questions about how those agents’ actions are determined. The extent to which agency is constrained by others, and the extent to which individual agency is caused by environmental or structural factors, limits what we see as individual agency. We can see immediately why agency is so often discussed only in relationship to structure. Issues of free will and autonomy are also therefore implicated in discussions of agency. The bulk of the discussion here will be concerned with human agency. In many social science applications, however, collective agents appear. Social science often describes organized collectives—such as political parties, firms, or governments—as agents. In some applications, unorganized collectives such as social classes and factions are considered agents. One of the problems in discussing human agency is seeing inside the person (the issue of free will or autonomous behavior), so considering collective agency where the “inside” is easier to perceive might help us understand some aspects of human Norm-Based Versus Instrumental Rationality We can define action as a contemporary event embedded in an environment informed by the past and oriented to the future. In such a definition, we give credit to the causal aspects of agency: that is, the past is implicated in current agency, either through rational calculation or causal determination, and we give credit to the fact that acts are directed at changing the world in some sense. They are future-oriented. Historically, a great deal of debate about agency is normative in the sense that what constitutes agency is thought to define human agency. Some argue that human agency needs to be seen as rational will driven by norms of appropriate behavior. Others argue that agency is best seen as instrumental rationality where people rationally choose their actions given the information they have about the world. The first sees certain goals as being rational; the second does not question the goals that people might have: rational action is only concerned with the best way of attaining those goals. The former approach can be traced to a Kantian idea that freedom is normatively grounded within the human will governed by categorical imperatives. Agents choose to act based on their will within a rationalized moral framework; they do not act out of material necessity. On the other side, some see freedom as individuals rationally choosing actions based on their desires and goals. Such instrumental rationality is often seen in purely selfinterested or material terms, though modern accounts of instrumental rationality deny the distinction and suggest that goals can be equally value-based as self-interested. This distinction between norm-based and instrumental rationality should not be confused with habitual versus autonomous action. Habitual Versus Autonomous Action A great deal of modern sociology from Talcott Parsons to Anthony Giddens, from structuralists to poststructuralists, uses a norm-based approach to agency. However, the norm-based accounts here Agency are not Kantian as such but rather based on notions of habit, which owe more to stimulus response than to normatively grounded rational will. Parsons believed humans create understandings of themselves in the roles they play in society by internalizing the standards expected of that role as they see them within their environment. Their conformity to those roles then has that same effect on others. In a similar fashion, Pierre Bourdieu uses the concepts of field, habitus, and capital to explain action in terms of conformity to expectations. A field defines a set of roles and relationships that develop over time and their worth or capital is given by the differential rewards and status afforded to those roles by the fields. Actors develop values based on the reward systems within each field. Each agent thus internalizes a set of values that is expected of him or her, and these form the agent’s habitus. Neither Parsons nor Bourdieu denies autonomy, but they emphasize habit as a learned environmental response. Giddens, despite claiming he transcends the dualism of structure and autonomy, also places routine at the heart of his account of structuration where rules and resources ensure the replication of structure. Agency in these habitual accounts is explained by dispositions or habits, themselves explained in terms of the environment or structure that causes them. These habits are not simply learned responses but also include the actors’ own interpretations of their responses in terms of their values. Here, the Kantian norms seem to be explained not through rational reflection and free will, but through socialization. It appears that on these accounts autonomous action can only be identified through the fracturing of habits, when individuals break away from their roles and values. It might appear that instrumental accounts of agency do not suffer the determinism of habitual accounts. If every action that an agent takes is based on the agent’s aims and objectives—directed at some future gain—and based on the agent’s own beliefs and desires, and we model that action as based on instrumentally rational reflective action, then we seem to be assuming autonomy. Many writers who work with the tradition of instrumental action assume individuals are autonomous and rationally decide their actions through free choice. However, those very beliefs and desires might have come about through stimulus response, 7 through habit; modeling human action as though it is instrumental and reflective is not to say that action is instrumentally rational and reflective. In other words, modeling the world in terms of instrumental rationality in the manner of rational choice theory or economics does not demonstrate agency; it merely posits a particular way in which we can view social processes. The Evolution of Human Agency If stimulus response is not considered to be agency, then we need to consider how we move from stimulus response to agency. Although animals, and indeed plants, act on the world in some way— grazers eat grass, bees pollinate flowers, and so on—their behavior with regard to the external world is generally modeled as stimulus response. The right kinds of external stimuli lead a bee to a plant; the right kind of stimulus leads to fight-orflight responses in animals. Agency is thought to be beyond such simple stimulus response. It might be related to Kantian norm-driven behavior or might result from instrumental reasoning, but it is not a straightforward stimulus response. That is not to deny, of course, that humans react to the world both habitually and through learned responses, but their behavior is more self-reflective than simple stimulus response. Self-reflectivity thus looks like a candidate for the “internal” aspect of agency. How does self-reflectivity evolve? Simple organisms track their environment through simple cues. Simple cues can, however, be exploited by other organisms. For example, some fireflies are exploited by predators that use the fireflies’ signals as lures. Any creature whose behavior relies on simple cues is fragile. More complex creatures develop multiple cues for their stimulus–response reactions, allowing more robust responses within strategic environments of competing creatures. Apes monitor the body language, facial expressions, and relative location of rival apes using three complex cuing systems. These might still be considered stimulus–response mechanisms, but the important aspect for considerations of agency is how creatures start to predict the behavior of their fellows. One philosophical tradition suggests that the apes, including humans, develop a theory of mind. They track what other apes are going to do through examining their 8 Agency behavior and imagining what they would do under those circumstances. Human children start to develop such a theory of mind from the age of three. In some experiments, a toy is placed in a box. An adult then leaves the room, and the child sees the toy being removed from one box and put in another. The adult comes back. The child is then asked where the adult thinks the toy is. Young children assume the adult will know what they know, that the toy has been moved. Older children realize that because the toy was moved when the adult was out of the room, the adult will think it is in the original box. The change marks the ability to think of the other as having a mind. The child develops a theory of mind and can make inferences about what that other person could know given the information that person has. Apes seem to have a theory of mind of other apes. After conflict, chimpanzees seek reconciliation, which seems psychologically important. There are standard cues for this, such as putting out a hand, but there are multiple responses. Reconciliation gestures can be strategically refused, perhaps by an ape demanding the other demonstrate inferiority. In other words, we do not have simple stimulus response—a conflict, a sign of reconciliation, and then a stimulus response to that. Rather, a whole suite of cues exists, and the chimps are not stimulus-bound to respond to them in the same way. Instead, the chimps respond to the mental states of others, tracking what those states are by the cues, but being able to grasp that the behaviors are only signals of the state, and not the state itself. Assuming some sort of inner life and interpreting behavior in terms of reasons for action is named “the intentional stance” by Daniel Dennett. The intentional stance occurs when we posit teleology or intentional action to agents. Thus, we can suggest that a dog can bark up the wrong tree, because we assume the dog wants to bark up the tree with the cat in it, and we know the cat is in a different tree. By saying the “dog wants” to bark up the tree with the cat in it, we are positing desires (to bark at the cat) and beliefs (the cat is in this tree) to constitute a reason for the act. To what extent a dog has reasons in this manner (and the barking is not simply a stimulus response) is not necessarily a concern for Dennett. What is important is that imputing reasons to creatures for their actions allows us to predict and (through prediction) explain their actions. Positing an internal world of thought is an efficient means of predicting what is around us. We can take the intentional stance with all sorts of things, including plants (the flower wants to follow the sun) without actually positing an internal world. However, the more complex the cuing of behavior is, the more useful and efficient the intentional stance is. With simple stimulus response (flowers following the sun), positing intentionality does not bring any real efficiencies; with complex behaviors it does. The next step in intentionality is to posit the intentional stance with regard to our own behavior. Our reasons for acting as we do are simply our own interpretations of our actions. The intentional stance in this way is sometimes described as compatibilist because it is compatible with strict determinism. Even if our behavior is strictly determined, we might still more efficiently predict our own and others’ behavior by positing the internal world. Of course, you might say, “But I know I have an internal world! I have my thoughts and plans and so on.” However, having them does not show they are really causal; one’s behavior might be caused by elements outside of oneself, and all one’s thoughts are still interpretations of the actions, just as they are for others. The only difference is that we are with ourselves more often than we are with others; hence, our interpretations of our own behaviors are more secure. However, we might still get a stronger agency out of this view. Self-Reflection and Agency If our reasons for action are our interpretations of our behavior caused in some manner, those reasons might still be implicated in further behavior. As we narrate our lives, we impose a structure on our actions. That structure might affect our behavior just as any other structure constrains and opens possibilities for action. We can return to the idea of habitual behavior here. Our narration of our own lives gives us a prediction for how that story will continue. Our own narration will be built on what we have learned, the roles or habitus that we have formed through the expectations we have engendered via the expectations of others. Thus, our own reasons for action are constituted by sets of external meanings, though they are still our reasons for Agency action. Our past behavior need not always be a good guide for future behavior. Sometimes, notably in strategic situations, we want our behavior to be unpredictable. We might even randomize our behavior in certain contexts precisely to fool equally strategically minded opponents. Either way, however, our own interpretations of our actions correlate with our behavior whether or not those interpretations, in the sense of meaningful propositions, can be said to cause our actions. (Our actions might be preceded by neuronal activity, but such neuronal activity does not itself constitute meaningful propositions without the interpretation that is given to the action. Indeed it is unlikely that we will find specific neuronal activity that correlates precisely with meaningful propositions, even if those meaningful propositions correlate directly with behavior.) The interpretative stance gives us a way into agency by suggesting that agency, as opposed to behavior or stimulus response, is composed of interpretations of action. We can interpret the behavior of creatures in terms of reasons for action. In that sense, we treat animals (or even plants, robots, or animated characters in computer games) as agents. However, the agential form is composed of the imposition of our interpretation on their behavior rather than on their own. In that sense, the animals or animations are agents, but not their own agents. We, however, can also interpret our own behavior, and that self-reflection makes us agents in our own right. Losing Agency So we are agents because we have our own reasons for action, and these predict our behavior. Can we be wrong in our assertion of reasons for action? If some observer were to better predict our behavior by asserting reasons for our actions different from our own, then we might think that those reasonsfor-action are superior to those we give to ourselves. And that is not unusual. After all, many people can realize through discussion with a friend or psychoanalyst that perhaps they did have ulterior motives in some action of which they were unaware. Hypnotists can lead people into crazy behavior, and when asked to justify that behavior, the subjects come up with plausible reasonsfor-action that observers realize are specious. One 9 way in which we lose agency is to lose the ability to predict our own behavior. Strong emotions such as anger or jealousy, drugs and chemicals, or hypnosis might lead to unpredictability. In other cases where we have been indoctrinated or fall under another’s sway, that person is better placed to predict our behavior. He or she becomes the agent. All of these considerations are outside of the free will versus determinism debate. They show, however, that the interpretative stance allows us to determine agency compatible with either free will or determinism. Collective Agents Collective agents such as firms, political parties, or governments have rules and procedures for making decisions. Here, the meaningful propositions by which we can view their agency are observable. The more rule-bound an organization is, the more predictable its behavior is and the more it seems to be an agent in its own right. For example, an organization whose chief executive could overturn any decision made at a lower level seems to be an agent only in the sense that the chief executive is. (Though if we have a chief executive who never overturned decisions, then the organization would gain collective agency again.) For that reason, organized collectives seem more like collective agents than unorganized ones such as social classes. Indeed the latter are only collective agents in the sense that individual agents work as one. The explanation of how a social class will act in concert is also the explanation of how each of its members acts. With organized collectives, the explanation of each individual member’s behavior adds to the collective agency together with the rules and procedures by which the collective makes decisions and so acts. In that sense, collective agency is easier to comprehend than is individual agency because its internal rules are more observable. Nevertheless, because individual human agents act through socially meaningful avenues, our behavior is structured, through roles, through habitus. However, that does not detract from our agency; indeed, socially meaningful activity adds sense to our agency. For completely random, uninterpretable behavior could not be agential. Keith Dowding 10 Agency–Structure Problem See also Agency–Structure Problem; Autonomy; Bourdieu, Pierre; Free Will; Freedom; Interests; Parsons, Talcott; Power To and Power Over; Rationality Further Readings Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom evolves. London: Allen Lane. Emirbayer, M., & Mische, A. (1998). What is agency? American Sociological Review, 1003, 962–1023. AGENCY–STRUCTURE PROBLEM Most theories of power either assign power to agents—which could be individuals, collectives such as classes or groups, or organizations—or see power as a pervasive element of the structure of society that operates outside the control of agents. The agency–structure problem concerns how we assign power to one or the other, or how much importance we place on either agency or structure. Agents act. Indeed, part of the very definition of agency is that it is carried out by agents. The most obvious agent is the individual. If we assign power to an individual, we are asserting that, with regard to the scope of the power claim, the agent can bring about some outcome. In some definitions, that power is the power to do some x; in others, it is the power of the agent over some other agent. In some definitions, power is simply seen as what an agent can do; in others, it is what an agent can do despite the resistance of others. Essentially, assigning some power to an agent is to claim that the agent could be causally efficacious in bringing about some result. In that sense, the power seems to be a property of the agent. However, people do not act in a vacuum; they act for reasons, and those reasons might be determined by external forces that act on them. What people attempt to do is constrained by what they see as feasible and enabled by what they want to do. Indeed, what people want is constrained by what they see as feasible. Hence, we do not need to reject any claim that (only) agents act to see that the ultimate cause of some outcome might be external to the agent himself or herself. If the external constraints fully determine the individual’s wants, for example, we can tell a completely deterministic story about the way in which the social world operates that needs mention the individual agent as barely more than some causal bearer of structural features of society. What is a structure? There are many different definitions. Structures can be seen as recursively organized sets of rules and resources that enable and constrain people. Structures enter into people, so to speak, by conditioning their thought processes through conventional activity, by copying others, and through belief systems engendered through interacting with other agents and the external world. A simple definition of structure is the relationship of the constituent parts of something. So the structure of a bridge is the relationship between bricks, mortar, and girders. The structure of society is the relationship between individuals and organizations. The same bricks, mortar, and girders could build different bridges as defined by the structure. The same genetic individuals could bear different social relationships constituting very different social structures. In the latter case, however, those different relationships might have a very different effect on the individuals. Indeed, different relations will affect the very matter of genetic individuals. A society with high social mobility will enable different sets of people to marry and bear children than will one with low social mobility. The very physical nature of people will thus be conditioned by social structure. Other agents such as organizations or classes are also defined by the structure itself. Again, structure enters into the very fabric of agents and thus seems to dominate our account of power. One way of viewing the agency–structure problem is to note that we can still maintain that power is a property of agents without denying the structural conditioning we have been describing. Agents act, but one agent’s actions are part of another agent’s structure. The overall interaction of agents constitutes the social structure. A shallower form of structural power explanation states that the environment around actors affects their strategies. A deeper form argues that the environment around people not only suggests strategies to actors given their aims, but gives them their aims in the first place. The customs, habits, beliefs, and so on of Agenda Power the community we live in decide our beliefs and desires for us even as these customs suggest the strategies we need to adopt to promote our aims. Where we have little or no choice in our aims as well as our strategies, we might be subject to a system of domination. We are dominated in our lives. This, though, might simply be the claim that there is no individual autonomy and our very thoughts are dominated. This brings to mind the idea of memes that infect our minds and cause us to take on attitudes. Concentrating on individual agents’ (whether these are people or organizations) power for some types of questions—such as whether the developers or local voters dominate in a particular conflict over development—can lead to focusing on the actors concerned. However, a more complete explanation of why developers might dominate more often than do voters would examine the structural factors that enable and constrain both the actions and the interests of the agents concerned. This explanation suggests why people might take on the interests of others in their actions, even though to an external observer the interests of each side seem to be in conflict. Such an approach does not assign part of the power we examine to agents and part to structure; rather, it assigns power to agents so they can answer some questions, but recognizes that those powers can be explained at another level by examining the structures that engender, constrain, and even define the powers of those agents. Keith Dowding See also Determinism; False Consciousness; Habitus; Miliband–Poulantzas Debate; Non Decision Making; Structural Power; Structural Suggestion; Structuration; Structure-Induced Equilibrium; Substructure and Superstructure; Systematic Luck; Systemic Power Further Readings Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Dowding, K. (2008). Agency and structure: Interpreting power relationships. Journal of Power, 1(1), 21–36. Foucault, M. (1977). The subject and power. Critical Inquiry, 8, 777–795. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. 11 AGENDA POWER Formally, agenda power is the capability of an agenda setter to manipulate the specific order in which N voters will consider J alternatives being offered. Contingent on the particular preferences of the voters, this facilitates indirect control over the outcome of the votes, the alternative(s) actually chosen by the decision process. Agenda power is typically discussed in the context of majority rule and pairwise comparisons. More generally, it refers to the ability to organize legislative business in parliamentary settings. A (classic) example is as follows. Consider three voters voting on three alternatives x, y, and z. Suppose that voter 1 has preference xP1yP1z, voter 2 has preference zP2xP2y, and voter 3 has preference yP3zP3x (where “P” stands for “strictly prefers to”). This produces a Condorcet paradox: x is majority preferred to y, y is majority preferred to z, and z is majority preferred to x. Suppose now that an individual—say voter 2—has agenda power in that he or she can decide the order in which the alternatives will be considered. By making the first vote between x and y (x wins) and the second vote between x and z (z wins), voter 2 can attain his or her preferred outcome. This example holds, with changes made, for x and y as first preferences too. Notice that voting cycles are necessary but not sufficient for agenda power. Consider the following example, devised by Peter Ordeshook: suppose that there are N 3 voters with preferences over J 8 alternatives denoted a, b, c, d, e, f, g, h given by Table 1. For the preferences described in Table 1, there is a cycle through the alternatives {a, b, c} and a cycle through the alternatives {d, e, f, g, h}, and any alternative from the first set would beat any alternative from the second. So someone with agenda power could obtain a, b, or c, but could not obtain, say, g. Technically, we say that {a, b, c} are in the top cycle. Agenda power as described exists only when there is no Condorcet winner. A Condorcet winner is an alternative that can beat every other alternative in a pairwise vote. If a Condorcet winner exists, the voting cannot be ordered such that the social preference moves away from it. The almost certain absence of a Condorcet winner in an alternative space of three or more dimensions or in a 12 Agenda Power Table 1 Not all cyclical social orders facilitate agenda power Preferences Voters 1st 2nd 3rd 4th 5th 6th 7th 8th 1 a d b f c e g h 2 c e a h b g d f 3 b g c h a d f e continuous space (as demonstrated in Richard D. McKelvey’s chaos theorem) implies that whoever controls the order of voting can achieve any point in the space as a final voting outcome. McKelvey’s result (like the previous examples) requires that voters vote sincerely, but they might vote in a strategic fashion. If voters know each other’s preferences (or at least the majority preference between every pair of alternatives), they can “look down the agenda tree and reason back” to see which alternatives will be paired later in the voting process and decide how to vote at the outset. They can vote strategically to defeat any attempt at agenda manipulation. As an example, suppose that there are two stages to voting: first, on an amendment to a bill, versus the original text of the bill; second, on the bill versus the status quo. The comparison to the status quo in the last stage is actually the method used in the U.S. Congress. Assume that a legislator prefers the amended bill to the unamended bill, and prefers the unamended bill to the status quo. Suppose the legislator is also aware that the amended bill would lose to the status quo, but that the original bill would win against it. Then he or she has a strategic incentive to vote against the amendment when it faces the original bill, but for the original bill when it subsequently faces the status quo. Hence, the legislator does not vote sincerely when considering the amendment. A seeming exception to this logic is presented by the case of “killer amendments.” Killer amendments are added to bills that would otherwise pass to ensure that they will now fail in a majority vote. Though hardly common, their very existence is puzzling precisely because the majority of (rational) voters who support the unamended bill should also reject the attempt to amend it. The art of crafting successful killers is part of a more general concept of political manipulation denoted heresthetics by William Riker. Successful killers require that herestheticians find an important second dimension such that voting on the amendment is sincere (for at least some legislators). In the U.S. context, this dimension has often been race. In any case, the dictatorial power that the chaos theorem implies is rarely enjoyed by agenda setters in practice. In the study of U.S. politics, scholars have investigated agenda power empirically, especially for the U.S. House of Representatives. Much work has focused on the power of the majority party, which selects organizational leaders such as the speaker and committee chairs and timetables legislation. Gary Cox and Mathew McCubbins argue that the majority party’s agenda power is of two different kinds: first, the party has negative agenda power that allows the party to keep issues away from the House floor that would generally displease its members, and hence, the majority party can preserve its past gains. This power is said to be unconditional in the sense that it does not depend on the unity of the party members’ views of public policy. By contrast, positive agenda power is the ability to propose changes to existing policy but requires some similarity among the preferences of the party. Cox and McCubbins construct a cartel agenda model and show that the key personnel of the majority party possess agenda power. In a parallel to literature on industrial organization, the authors contend that the busy world of legislating compels the majority party to institutionalize its central authority and that this cartel is generally responsive to its members. This theory and finding contrast starkly with earlier accounts that posited that the legislator who is the floor median enjoys direct or indirect agenda power. This power is used in two ways: first for the bills that are actually Agenda Setters considered during the legislative session; second, for the debate and amendments to those bills. Arthur Spirling See also Agenda Setters; Heresthetics; Leadership; Riker, William H. Further Readings Cox, G. W., & McCubbins, M. D. (2002). Agenda power in the U.S. House of Representatives, 1877–1986. In D. W. Brady & M. D. McCubbins (Eds.), Party, process, and political change in Congress: New perspectives on the history of Congress. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press. Ordeshook, P. C. (1995). Game theory and political theory: An introduction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman. AGENDA SETTERS Formally, agenda setters are actors who control which alternatives (in addition to the status quo) other players may vote for and (if there is more than one) the order in which these votes will take place. Depending on the extent of their control, and contingent on the preferences and behavior of the other players, agenda setters may possess agenda power. In political science, the identity, role, and power of agenda setters have been investigated in at least two scenarios: legislative voting and approval of agency budgets, either by (local) public referenda or by executive branch “sponsors.” We illustrate the role of agenda setters with examples from the second. William Niskanen argued that senior bureaucrats have goals that are functions of their agency’s budget: therefore, they seek to maximize their budgets. They are in a strong position to do so because the bureau is a monopoly supplier of its output (such as national defense or education); officials have an informational advantage over their sponsors (they know more about the agency’s internal costs, and direct monitoring of the quantity/quality of its output is difficult); and, 13 crucially, the bureaucrat can make a take-it-orleave-it budget proposal. The bureaucrat here is an agenda setter with a binary agenda presenting a choice between his or her preferred budget proposal and some other budget reduced to some inappropriate or unacceptable level to politicians. Thomas Romer and Howard Rosenthal posited a model (which they later tested) based on this logic. The empirical case in point is the Oregon school budget process. In that state, each school has a maximum budget fixed by law but can expand the upper limit by a referendum at an annual meeting. If the new budget fails to be approved by at least 50% of voters, then the budget reverts to that of the previous year. Consider Figure 1, which displays the utility as a function of budget level for the median voter who will be decisive in the electorate for the referendum. The curve is centered at Bmed, which is the median voter’s preferred level of school spending. When the reversion point is Brev1, the voter—and thus the electorate—will accept anything in the reflection of Brev1 about Bmed. So, for example, they will approve anything up to Bprop1. Notice though, that an Brev1 Bmed Brev2 Figure 1 Bmed Bprop1 Bprop2 Agenda setter’s power is contingent on reversion point 14 Alliances agenda setter does best in terms of maximizing his or her budget when the reversion level is most threatening. When the reversion level is higher, such as at, for example, Brev2, the reflection allows less expansion: only up to Bprop2 will be approved. Romer and Rosenthal find empirical evidence in Oregon that is consistent with their theoretical model. It is possible to reframe the Romer and Rosenthal model for any bureaucrat–sponsor relationship, although evidence is more difficult to come by. In general, weakening the ability of the agenda setter to make take-it-or-leave-it offers significantly reduces the agenda setter’s power relative to the sponsor. Arthur Spirling See also Agenda Power; Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrats; Bureaucratic Power Further Readings Niskanen, W., Jr. (1971). Bureaucracy and representative government. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton. Romer, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1978). Political resource allocation, controlled agendas, and the status quo. Public Choice, 33(4), 27. ALLIANCES Premier among strategies in a state’s arsenal to advance its policy agenda is the capacity to form a military alliance with one or more other states. A military alliance may be defined as a formal or informal agreement between two or more states that is intended to advance militarily the national security of the participating states. It is a continuing security association among member states with an element of forward planning and understanding to aid member states militarily or, at a minimum, through benevolent neutrality. These security arrangements may take several forms, with varying degrees of institutionalization and commitment levels. For example, one of the most significant military alliances in the world today is the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), which has a high degree of integration regarding its command structure, and a high degree of commitment by the allies, via Article V, which deems an attack on one signatory shall be deemed an attack on all members. Other military alliances might call for less concerted action in the event of casus foederis being met, perhaps merely the observation of benevolent neutrality in the event that one of the signatories finds itself at war with a third party. Alliance Motivations Military alliances are conventionally understood as an important avenue for states to augment their power capabilities. In other words, states are motivated to join alliances to add the power of other states to that of their own. This will help them counter threats they might face in the international system. Kenneth Waltz described this motivation for forming an alliance as balancing—states form alliances to balance the capabilities or threats facing them in the international system. Stephen Walt later argued that states do indeed balance, but against threats, not power capabilities alone. From this perspective, NATO was formed by its original signatories to counter the capabilities and threats posed by the Soviet Union and the Eastern bloc powers. Although capability aggrandizement is indeed a central role alliances play, it is by no means the only one. Scholars such as Paul Schroeder sought to understand the conflict management role of these institutions. Elaborating on this perspective, Patricia Weitsman argued that another motivation for a military alliance to be forged might contain an adversarial relationship, that is, states tether their enemies to them to neutralize the threat. From this point of view, alliances function as other international institutions do, to enhance transparency, increase the costs of defection, and make cooperation cheaper, and, therefore, more likely. Viewing alliances as institutions generates insights into the ways in which threats within an alliance are managed. Thus, in the words of its first secretary general, Lord Ismay, NATO was originally formed “to keep the Soviets out, the United States in, and the Germans down.” Examining NATO purely as a balancing response to the Soviet Union misses the important dynamics that exist within the alliance. Both Greece and Turkey are members of the NATO alliance even though they are mutual enemies; they do not add the other’s Alliances power to their own within the context of the alliance. Nonetheless, they might gain important institutional advantages from being allied adversaries, in transparency and conflict management functions. One unintended consequence, however, of effective tethering alliances is that although they are formed to manage conflicts among signatories, they might appear threatening to nonmembers, heightening the level of threat and uncertainty in the international system. Weitsman calls this dynamic the alliance paradox and argues that it culminates in an overall higher probability of war. A third motivation for states seeking to form an alliance is to protect themselves from a powerful and threatening enemy. Here, states bargain with the threatening state, capitulating to it to ensure survival. Randall Schweller argues that “bandwagoning” behavior may be viewed as what small states do for strategic gain, given their inability to counter the power capabilities of a strong state. Although bargaining behavior occurs more rarely than balancing, the logic is used often to explain or justify certain foreign policy objectives. For example, the fear of “dominoes falling” uses bandwagoning logic—the belief that a hostile state will reap allies through victory culminating in a snowball effect. A final motivation for states seeking to ally under conditions of threat is hedging. Weitsman describes this as low-commitment-level alliances with states to draw them into one’s sphere of influence to allow the initiating state to consolidate its power, shut off avenues of expansion to potential adversaries, but not prove overly provocative to rivals. Hedging alliances allow states more freedom of action in the international system and may set the stage for enhanced cooperation among signatories in the future. As Michael Jacobson has written, one such alliance of note in the current international system is the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, which includes China and Russia among its signatories. In seeking to enhance power capabilities in the international system, states might seek to arm themselves or form alliances. How states select their alliance partners is an important question. Although some scholars argue that regime type and ideology matter, others write that geostrategic concerns dominate. If states seek to ally, they face the dilemma of a fear of abandonment by their 15 partners versus a fear of entrapment in a conflict in which they do not want to be involved. This is what Glenn Snyder has termed the alliance security dilemma. Furthermore, states seeking to ally face a trade-off between their heightened security and their autonomy in action in the system. The extent to which this is true, however, depends on the commitment level of the alliance, and the type of alliance it is: balancing, bargaining, tethering, or hedging. The higher the commitment is, the more restricting the commitment is for autonomy. Alliances can be bilateral or multilateral. The number of states in the alliance has an important effect, too, on the autonomy of the partners. In multilateral alliances, such as NATO, the alliance must be reduced to its dyads to understand the motivations that coexist within it. Such analysis also helps explain the autonomy of the signatories in projecting their influence in the system. Alliance Cohesion The ability of states in an alliance to agree on common goals and strategies is an indication of its cohesion. The ability of signatories to coordinate strategies and tactics will be a critical determinant of its effectiveness. Effectiveness is essential for a military alliance to manifest power. For example, the cohesion of the Central Powers—Germany and Austria–Hungary—during World War I was quite limited. As a consequence, its military effectiveness was inadequate. In contrast, the Triple Entente was relatively cohesive; as such, it was able to prevail militarily over its adversarial counterpart. Maintaining the cohesion of an alliance is essential to advancing the objectives of the signatories. It is also necessary for the successful exercise of power. Alliance cohesion is most often a derivative of threat levels. Threats may emanate from outside the alliance to the signatories in a symmetrical way. In this case, states will have an important unifying cause that will facilitate their coordination of goals and strategies. Thus, balancing alliances will have the highest cohesion levels of any type of alliance. If threats emanate from outside the alliance, but not in a symmetrical or uniform way, it will be harder for states to agree on goals and strategies. Some threats may be complementary; others may be divisive. When states are 16 Alliances driven to ally with one another because of the threats they face from each other, then the principal threat to the alliance exists within it. Here cohesion is almost impossible to maintain. Tethering alliances, therefore, will be the least cohesive. Peacetime Versus Wartime Alliances Military alliances are often concluded to deter or counter aggression from hostile states. Consequently, alliances must be examined during both peace and war. During peacetime, alliances serve principally as deterrents and conflict management devices. Power capabilities are an important component of alliances, but during peacetime that power is usually employed coercively, to compel or deter. States in an alliance will use their collective power to try to compel an adversary to do something or stop doing something or to prevent an encroachment on core values. During wartime, however, the requirements for effectiveness are dramatically different. States must coordinate goals and strategies even more carefully. During wartime, for military operations to be successful, joint planning, coordination, and communication are critical. Asymmetries in power capabilities that might not matter for effective peacetime alliance operations might become a source of tension during wartime as burden-sharing concerns become paramount. Acting in concert in an alliance presents the same collective action problems that dominate other spheres of activity in international relations. Furthermore, although alliances tend to be more cohesive when there is a shared external threat during peacetime, during wartime the relationship between external threats and cohesion is more complex. Alliances that are losing a war confront greater threat levels than do those that are winning, and yet alliances that are losing wars do not experience an upswing in cohesion as a consequence of this heightened threat environment. Alliance politics during wartime are closely related to the dynamics of coalition warfare. Analytically, coalitions differ only slightly from alliances. Coalitions are generally defined as collections of states that come together to implement specific military operations. Examples include the Desert Storm coalition in the Persian Gulf War in 1991, which included more than 23 nation-states, and the Operation Iraqi Freedom (OIF) multinational operation that began in 2003 to remove Saddam Hussein from power and stabilize Iraq politically in the aftermath of regime change. The OIF coalition comprised 34 countries, including 11 NATO members. These ad hoc coalitions were forged with precise missions in mind. Their cohesion rested on the ability of the signatories to agree on the goals of the mission as well as on strategies to attain those goals. The Desert Storm coalition had more limited objectives than did the OIF coalition, but had a coordinated strategy to achieve those objectives. The primary goal was to eject Iraqi forces from Kuwait. The strategy was implemented through an integrated force structure for U.S., U.K., and French troops, and integrated Arab forces under the Saudi commander of the joint forces theater of operations, with the two structures linked in the Coalition Coordination, Communication and Integration Center. Its cohesion, as a consequence, was quite high. In the OIF coalition, divisions within the coalition about its continued mission rendered the coalition less effective and less cohesive than its predecessors. Several countries dropped out of the coalition after the operation began in 2003. Coalition warfare has a long history. States frequently opt to embark on war with other states at their side rather than on their own. In other words, states frequently choose to resolve their military conflicts by force multilaterally rather than unilaterally. This is especially true in the present day. The United States, in particular, has increasingly sought to forge coalitions in advance of pressing forward with military operations in the post–cold war era. The United States embarked on 12 multilateral operations between 1900 and 1982 and 12 operations from 1991 to 2005. In addition, the size of these coalitions has been on the rise. Part of this is because there are more states in the international system now than there ever have been, and part of this is the diminishing legitimacy of unilateral military operations. As coalition size grows, traditional problems of alliance management, such as burden sharing and the alliance security dilemma, grow as well. Intra-alliance dynamics are always important for optimal performance, but this becomes especially important during wartime. Command, control, and communication failures during joint wartime operations have potentially lethal effects. Althusser, Louis Collective Defense Versus Collective Security Although most alliances function as collective defense organizations—that is, they provide mutual defense arrangements for the signatories—some security institutions may be put into place to provide collective security. Collective security agreements are pacts among all states to counter aggression whenever and wherever it occurs. The point of a collective security arrangement is not to defend any one state but to defend the order of the system as a whole. The distinction between collective defense and collective security is an important one; a true collective security arrangement would actually mean the end of competing alliances. All states would, in essence, be allied together to defend the order of the system. Historically, collective security has been difficult to achieve. The most important attempts have followed major power wars of some significance: the Concert of Europe following the Napoleonic Wars; the League of Nations following the World War I; and the United Nations in the aftermath of World War II. In design, the League of Nations was the closest to a true collective security organization, and that played a significant role in the organization’s paralysis and subsequent demise. The United Nations has been more successful as an organization, but does not truly operate as a collective security institution. This is why in the event that defense of the system is required, coalitions must be put into place in an ad hoc fashion, as was done during the Persian Gulf War of 1991. Alliances are a key component of the workings of the international system. They play an important role in determining systemic stability and the frequency of major power war. They play an essential role in determining who prevails in military conflict. They also are an essential component of the foreign-policy-making tools in the arsenal of any state. Alliances are a powerful tool of statecraft, both historically and in the present day. Patricia A. Weitsman See also Anarchy in International Relations; Balance of Power; Coalition Theory; Hegemonic War; Realism in International Relations; Riker, William H.; Security; Waltz, Kenneth; War 17 Further Readings Schroeder, P. W. (1976). Alliances, 1815–1945: Weapons of power and tools of management. In K. Knorr (Ed.), Historical dimensions of national security problems (pp. 227–262). Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. Schweller, R. (1994). Bandwagoning for profit: Bringing the revisionist state back in. International Security, 19(1), 72–107. Snyder, G. H (1984). The security dilemma in alliance politics. World Politics, 36(4), 461–495. Walt, S. (1987). The origins of alliances. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Waltz, K. N. (1979). Theory of international politics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Weitsman, P. A. (2003). Alliance cohesion and coalition warfare: The Central Powers and the Triple Entente. Security Studies, 12(3), 79–113. ALTHUSSER, LOUIS (1918–1990) Louis Althusser was a French structural Marxist and professor of philosophy at the École Normale Supérieure. His work evolved over time, especially because he was subject to the dictates of the Communist Party, of which he was a lifelong member. He defended a version of Marxism that opposed the humanist turn in Marxist thought that came about, especially in France, after the death of Joseph Stalin. Althusser’s work is most relevant to the concept of power in his account of ideology. In Althusser’s account, ideology represents an artificial or illusory relationship between individuals and the real conditions of their existence. Ideology also has a material existence beyond ideas that exist within human minds. The first part or “thesis” is a version of the familiar Marxist claim that human exploitation is hidden from people by the ideology under which they live. In Althusser’s hands, the relationship between individuals and the real conditions of their existence is complex. Rather than claiming that there is a real material existence, and then there is our representation of that existence—the latter perverted by ideology— he argues that our existence is a consequence of social practices such that individuals are created in the image of the society in which they live. People take on roles determined by their place in the socioeconomic structure and behave in these roles 18 Anarchism, Power in as they are expected to, given the nature or function of the role. Our broader values and desires, however, are implanted in us by ideology that creates people as subjects. The entire ideology is a collection of institutions Althusser calls ideological state apparatuses, which include the family, religious organizations, social networks, the media, and the educational establishment. Different societies have different ideological state apparatuses, but they all create individuals as “subjects.” He illustrates this by suggesting we become subjects when we react to how others treat us. Our total reaction to social practices is what creates us as a subject. In this sense, it is not that we misperceive a reality: what we perceive of our society is what it is. However, through that perception we do not notice the exploitation and true relations between agents. Althusser believes that this represents the true account of Marx’s later vision of the dialectic that breaks the distinction between subject and object. The second aspect or thesis of ideology is its material existence. The first aspect is designed to privilege structure over agency by making agents— individuals—the creation of society or structures. The second is to take ideology out of the minds of the individuals whose perceptions it perverts and place it into the structure of society itself. Ideology in the material form is composed of the actions of people governed by the state apparatus. In that sense Althusser is a strong determinist: our actions are caused by the structure of society and are then interpreted by us through the roles we are called on to play. Sometimes individuals or classes pose threats to the dominant structures of society; at such times, what Althusser calls the repressive state apparatus comes into play through systems of law and order, which become increasingly repressive as people attempt to break out of the ideological state apparatus through social disorder and revolution. Althusser was very influential in continental philosophy, influencing Pierre Bourdieu and Michel Foucault, among others. Keith Dowding See also Agency; Agency–Structure Problem; Bourdieu, Pierre; Determinism; False Consciousness; Ideology; Marx, Karl; Marxist Accounts of Power; Structural Power Further Readings Althusser, L. (2010). Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (notes towards an investigation). In I. Szeman & T. Kaposy (Eds.), Cultural theory: An anthology. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. Elliott, G. (1987). Althusser: The detour of theory. London: Verso. ANARCHISM, POWER IN Power is a central issue in modern anarchist thought. Whereas anarchism was traditionally linked to authority—or its rejection—anarchists now talk in terms of power and counterpower. The change in emphasis is linked to the emergence of “postanarchist” theory: anarchism that draws on postmodern and poststructuralist thought, associated with Todd May, Lewis Call, and Saul Newman. The leading figures of 19th- and early 20thcentury anarchism—Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Mikhail Bakunin, Peter Kropotkin—were not unconcerned with power. On the contrary, even Proudhon, often regarded as the most individualist of the three, talked enthusiastically about the collective power of the workers. And many others defined anarchism as the abolition of power. But the concept was not made subject to sustained analysis—in contrast to law, authority, God, and science, for example. When they talked about power, 19th-century writers usually had one of two things in mind: the repressive machinery of the state or the liberating potential of collective actions. These two aspects of power were typically counterposed such that collective actions were believed to hold the key to the destruction of the state’s capacity to repress. What was important in this analysis was the image of power that it captured. On this account, power was about struggle against physical force (or as Max Weber would put it, the state’s monopoly of physical violence). Thus, the power of the state was typically equated with police, armed forces, prisons, torture, corporal and capital punishment—later on, surveillance—and the power of the oppressed was variously identified with barricades, terrorist or guerrilla actions, spontaneous revolt, the organization of peasants and workers in syndicates, ethical change, and the development of other nonhierarchical grassroots Anarchism, Power in organizations. In the 1870s and 1880s, when memories of the Paris Commune were still very fresh and optimism about the prospects for European revolution high, the association between power and physical force was strong (though Tolstoyan anarchists always rejected the necessity and justifiability of this link). The same was true in the early 20th century, when anarchists were again engaged in revolutionary war. Nestor Makhno, who led anarchist resistance against counterrevolutionaries and Bolsheviks in the Ukraine during the civil war, characterized revolutionary action as a capacity to conquer or exterminate oppressors. The power of revolutionaries depended on overt coercion. In the latter part of the 19th century and again after the defeat of the Republicans in the Spanish Civil War, the emphasis shifted to the ethical and communitarian aspects of collective power: the ability of oppressed groups to find ways of living, organizing, and behaving—often explicitly nonviolent—that did not mimic the repressive practices of the state. This way of thinking about power was resurgent in the 1960s in the work of such anarchists as Colin Ward, George Woodcock, and Paul Goodman. Capturing the change, Woodcock described the old-style anarchists as “bellicose barricaders.” The new anarchists, he suggested, “had forgotten Spain and had no use for the romanticism of the dynamitero. . . . They were militant pacifists” (Woodcock, 1992, 45–46). One of the premises of postanarchist thinking is that classical anarchism (Woodcock’s old and new anarchists) has a narrowly structural idea of power and wrongly considers that power can and must be abolished. May distinguishes between “strategic” and “tactical” philosophical approaches to power. The first—which captures the classical anarchist position—assumes that power refers to the central problematic, that it derives essentially or for the most part from the site on which that problematic focuses (the economic system, the state, etc.). In contrast, tactical political philosophy suggests, “there is no center within which power is to be located.” Power might conglomerate around particular sites, but these points of concentration are not points of origin, and power extends to multiple sites as well as to the interplay between them. Like May, Call draws on Michel Foucault to elaborate his idea. Finding classical anarchists guilty of an obsession with 19 capital and the state, Call rejects the simplistic top-down model of power to argue that it is present in any social relation. Power, he adds, always implies resistance. But resistance, counterpower, or antipower is nothing like the struggle of the classical anarchist, which was motivated by ideas of emancipation and wrongly assumed the existence of a human subject with free will. Why? Because on the one hand, postanarchists characterize the repressive nature of capitalism in novel ways, taking their lead from surrealists and situationists, and on the other hand, they deny the possibility of achieving a condition of liberation. Resistance, then, is about experimentation in everyday life and escaping the deadening discourses and consciousness of bourgeois capitalism through permanent resistance or, following Gilles Deleuze, rhizomatic action. The difference between the classical and the postanarchist positions should not be exaggerated. Although postanarchists challenge the rationalist epistemology of much 19th- and 20th-century anarchist thought, the political significance of the revision is not as great as sometimes claimed. Insofar as arguments about power are concerned, the comparison between the two positions is misleading. Postanarchists have accurately characterized the 19th-century conception of power, but overlooked the analyses of related concepts—notably authority— in which the relational issues so central to contemporary thought were first probed. Ruth Kinna See also Bakunin, Mikhail; Collective Action Problem; Foucault, Michel; Kropotkin, Peter; Revolution; Revolutionary Cell Structure Further Readings Call, L. (2002). Postmodern anarchism. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. May, T. (1994). The political philosophy of poststructuralist anarchism. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Newman, S. (2001). From Bakunin to Lacan: Antiauthoritarianism and the dislocation of power. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. Woodcock, G. (1992). Anarchism revisited. In Anarchism and anarchists (pp. 41–58). Kingston, Ontario, Canada: Quarry Press. 20 Anarchy in International Relations ANARCHY IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Anarchy—from the Greek a (no) and archè (dominion/authority)—in international relations refers to the situation that the international system lacks an agency that if necessary can force the members of the system, even the most powerful ones, to abide by the rules and keep their promises. Like all anarchical systems, the international system is a self-help system: it does not have bailiffs. Anarchy and Sovereignty Although circles of friends or gangs of criminals are also examples of anarchical systems, the presentday system of states is without doubt the bestknown example of such a system. This system originated on the European continent and is the outcome of an evolutionary process that took about 500 years. It started at the end of the 13th century, with the conflict between King Philip IV (the Fair) of France and Pope Boniface VIII concerning the right claimed by Philip to impose taxes on the churches in his kingdom without the pope’s prior consent, and symbolically ended with the dissolution of the Holy Roman Empire in 1806. The old, medieval order under the spiritual and secular authority of the pope and the emperor was gradually replaced by a new one that was based on territorially separate units that recognized one another as sovereign equals. Sovereignty means that the states do not attempt to exercise authority on another state’s territory and do not recognize any authority above them. This latter “external” aspect of sovereignty implies that anarchy and sovereignty are two sides of the same coin. They are mutually constitutive. Sovereignty as a property of the state cannot exist without anarchy as a property of the structure of the system of states. An anarchical system is therefore necessarily identical with a self-help system—a system, that is, in which no authority exists that can bring redress where one party has been wronged by another party. It has become part of the “unproblematic background knowledge” in the study of international relations that the ground rules of the states system were laid down in the Peace of Westphalia of October 1648, which ended the Thirty Years’ War. For this reason, the states system is very often referred to as the Westphalian system. Andreas Osiander has quite recently exposed this as a myth. The peace consisted of two treaties, the Treaty of Münster between the French king and the German emperor, and the Treaty of Osnabrück between the queen of Sweden and the German emperor. These treaties settled many questions, but they did not constitute a break with the past or establish a new international order based on the principle of sovereignty. Rather, they confirmed the ancient rights and liberties of the estates of the empire—including their right to conclude alliances with “strangers” for their preservation, provided these were not directed against the emperor or the empire—but made no mention of the estates being sovereign or having sovereign rights. Anarchy and the State of Nature Anarchy constitutes what John Ruggie has called the “deep structure” of the states system. Many students of international relations have concluded that the absence of a central authority must therefore explain why wars are endemic in the international system. But anarchy never can be the only factor that explains why states go to war because states can also coexist peacefully in anarchy. The history of the states system shows that states can be unreliable partners, continuously engaged in war or the preparation for war, as well as faithful allies cooperating with one another quite extensively. The European integration process since the 1950s moreover makes clear how far cooperation can go between states, the anarchical nature of the states system notwithstanding. One should also realize that organized acts of violence in the form of civil wars are a recurrent feature of hierarchical systems. Nevertheless, it can hardly be claimed that anarchy increases the chances of successful cooperation between actors in a system. In an anarchical system, conflict is more likely to lead to violence to settle the issue than in a hierarchical system where actors can appeal to an agency that can adjudicate between them and enforce a settlement. As a result, the anarchical structure of the states system has led many authors to describe life in that system in the gloomiest terms. The image they evoke of the situation the states find themselves in largely corresponds with Thomas Hobbes’s famous depiction of Anarchy in International Relations the state of nature in his Leviathan. Like Hobbes, these authors argue that anarchy implies that every state is the potential enemy of every other state and therefore must lead to a relentless security competition, that a division of labor—and consequently, prosperity—is impossible to realize, and that the life of states can be no more than “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” No matter how much this depiction appeals to the imagination, or how strongly it appears to be confirmed by the horrors of the countless wars the international system has experienced since its inception—particularly those of the two world wars in the last century—it is not correct. As Alexander Wendt has pointed out, states in the Westphalian system do not see one another as Hobbesian enemies, but as Lockean rivals. A division of labor is also possible in the states system, and the states that are part of it are able to cooperate with one another in all kinds of projects. Moreover, both Louis Henkin and Hans Morgenthau have emphasized that, although violation attracts attention, the scrupulous observance of the law and of obligations has been the rule in the system of states. Two factors in particular help explain why the Hobbesian logic of the state of nature does not apply to the states system. The first is that states need to protect their credibility. States are very anxious to prevent a situation in which one state can establish hegemony over the others. To avoid such hegemony, states enter alliances with other states to form a counterbalance against the potential hegemon. Such alliances can only form to the extent that the states have the reputation of keeping their promises and carrying out their threats. The reputational element in the states system enables cooperation even though the states system lacks an agency to enforce cooperation. Hobbes might actually have agreed with this, considering his refutation of the so-called argument of the fool. The fool argues that, in the state of nature, every person is concerned only with his or her own conservation, and therefore, that it is not against reason for a person not to keep his or her part of a covenant if this is to the person’s benefit, even though the other party has performed already. According to Hobbes, however, reason dictates that this person should fulfill his or her part, because in the state of nature no person has any hope of defending himself or herself without the 21 help of others and therefore should not deceive those on which his or her survival depends. Hobbes seems, however, not to have realized that this understanding would have made life in the state of nature less miserable and hopeless than he himself thought. Other things being equal, the more credible the commitment that states can make, the stronger the alliances they can form. Consequently, more credible states will be stronger and survive more easily than will less credible ones. Thus, the more weight a state attaches to its credibility, the greater the probability it will act in accordance with the rule that constitutes the basis of all international law, namely pacta sunt servanda (“agreements must be kept”). This holds true even when states, for whatever reason, regret having entered into an agreement and would be very glad to get out of it. In this way, the states’ desire for credibility ensures a level of predictability in their mutual relations, which increases the possibilities for cooperation and lays the foundation for regulation of their relations. The more importance the states attach to their credibility, the more the international system will have in common with Hedley Bull’s anarchical society: a society of states in which they recognize that they have common interests, and accept that in their dealings with one another they are bound by certain rules, even when they exercise force against one another. The proposition that the individuals who find themselves in the state of nature are more or less equal in strength is of vital importance for Hobbes’s characterization of this situation, where “every man is enemy to every man.” This proposition fortunately does not apply to the states in the states system because great differences in power exist between them. This is the second factor that helps explain why anarchy should not be equated with the state of nature. The more powerful one state is compared with the other states, the more prudent those other states will be in their dealings with it. And thus, the less necessary it will be for that state to consider how the other states will behave. On the one hand, this makes life in the states system simpler. The interests of the great powers are the ones that count—those of the smaller powers can be ignored. This is what the Athenian representatives try to make clear to the council of the Melians when, according to Thucydides, they argue that the stronger power 22 Animal Groups, Power in does what it can while the weaker one suffers what it must. On the other hand, this observation implies that the states falling within the reach of power of one of the most powerful states in the states system will think twice before deciding to break a promise, whether it be to one another or to the great power in question, out of fear of incurring the latter’s displeasure. Just like any other state, a great power tries as much as possible to organize the states system according to its own wishes. To the extent that it succeeds—which is naturally a direct function of the power preponderance of the great power relative to the other states—a great power may feel more responsible for the way things run within the states system. It will be anxious to stop being dragged into a conflict with some other great power by the actions of the less powerful states within its sphere of influence. The great powers devise the rules to be followed by the lesser states and may have both the capabilities and the will to maintain these rules. An important implication of this is that the fewer the great powers and the greater their influence, the more the great powers will act as managers of the states system. Most authors who equate anarchy with Hobbes’s state of nature are of the opinion that there exists only one method to banish war from the international system, and that is by establishing a world government. Immanuel Kant is one of them. In his Perpetual Peace, he agrees with Hobbes that states, because of their independent status, find themselves in a state of war and that this situation can only be remedied if the states merge into one under a central authority. Kant nevertheless prefers a situation of anarchy to one of “universal monarchy” because the remedy may be worse than the disease. A world government will lead to ossification, and possibly tyranny. Moreover, a world government will not be able to prevent civil war. In line with the argument developed here, Barry Buzan has emphasized that the choice between anarchy and world government is not one between insecurity and security. Anarchy and hierarchy provide different types of security, where the anarchical type of security has much to recommend it. World government may achieve more order and security, but liberty is more secure in anarchy. Robert H. Lieshout See also Bull, Hedley; Realism in International Relations; Sovereignty; Waltz, Kenneth; War Further Readings Bull, H. (1977). The anarchical society: A study of order in world politics. Houndmills, UK: Macmillan. Buzan, B. (1991). People, states and fear: An agenda for international security studies in the post–cold war era. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Lieshout, R. H. (1995). Between anarchy and hierarchy. A theory of international politics and foreign policy. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar. Wendt, A. (1999). Social theory of international politics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. ANIMAL GROUPS, POWER IN Power processes in animal groups are strikingly similar to those in human groups. In both animal and human contexts, power is an individual’s relative capacity to modify others’ states by providing or withholding resources or administering punishments. Power is contingent on the actual resources and punishments an individual can deliver to others but is also much more. Social species vary with regard to the complexity of power relationships. In many higher mammals, individuals have the cognitive capacity to recognize one another as individuals and to remember relative power differentials between group members. These animal groups can consist of 30 or more members. Thus, cognitive resources are directed toward the negotiation of power relationships. Dominance motivation is defined by the drive to gain power. Dominance relationships build on information gathering about the power of opponents. It is important to distinguish power, dominance motivation, and dominance behavior. Individuals with high dominance motivation are sensitive to cues of rank, seek out opportunities to influence others, and engage in more behaviors aimed at gaining and maintaining power, including ingratiating, competitive, and agonistic behavior and alliance formation. Such behaviors, though, may vary in their success in achieving power. Thus, although distinct, dominance motivation often predicts dominance behaviors, Animal Groups, Power in which in turn predicts attaining power if used effectively. Dominance behavior is distinct from aggressive behavior, which is defined by intent to inflict harm. Dominance behaviors can involve aggressive strategies for taking resources and threatening subordinates, and so dominance motivation and aggressive behavior often co-occur. Nonetheless, prosocial strategies, such as reciprocity and cooperation, can also reflect dominance motives. Indeed, in primates, prosocial strategies, such as trading favors and allocating resources justly, appear to be necessary for establishing power. Dominant individuals have species-specific strategies for signaling their power to other group members. Group members are influenced by these signals and by their prior interactions with each other. Resources and Power Power is defined by the ability to control resources. But, what kinds of resources do animals seek to control? Resources are the substrates of survival for both the individual and the species. Important resources include territory, food, water, and shelter. However, several resources are social in nature. The group itself is a resource that tends to benefit higher-ranking individuals more. It is therefore incumbent on dominants to act in ways that encourage other group members to stay in the group because defecting individuals could become rivals. Influence in the group or social attention is a sought-after resource, as is political support and the opportunity to mate. Dominant animals are the focus of attention in social groups and have privileged access to mates. In cooperatively breeding animals, reproduction is skewed markedly in favor of dominant animals that monopolize reproductive resources. In these societies, harsh environmental contingencies make group participation advantageous to subordinates even in the face of reproductive skew. In human economies, resources are exchanged based on their perceived value. Rhesus macaques will trade rewards for being able to view images of high-status troop members, but insist on compensation for viewing images of low-status individuals. Power therefore is indexed by the ability to gain both social attention and material resources. Chimpanzees have been observed to trade mating 23 opportunities for political support. Grooming is another commodity traded for food, mating, and political support in various species. Selection has favored individuals with the intelligence and memory capacity required to negotiate the power dynamics of the social world. The Basis of Power in Animal Groups Six bases of power have been defined in human organizations. Individual recognition and advanced cognition are required for these bases of power, which are 1. Informational—power based on provisioning of information that causes an individual to decide to adopt a particular behavior 2. Reward—power that stems from the ability of an individual to offer a resource 3. Coercion—power that stems from threats of punishment 4. Legitimate—power based on others just accepting the right of another to control a resource 5. Expertise—power based on others accepting that an individual has some superior insight or knowledge 6. Referent—power that stems from others identifying with an individual, or using that individual as a model All six bases of power are seen in animal societies. Reward and coercive power are the most commonly discussed and are unique in the requirement for policing or surveillance by the powerful. Deception is common in societies with this surveillance, and policing can become difficult in large groups. Mothers especially wield informational, expertise, and referential power. Leadership in animal groups (e.g., elephants) is usually the prerogative of older dominant individuals who have knowledge of resources and travel routes that others do not possess. Legitimate power is seen in many hunting predators where individuals often retain the right to their own kill and the decision to share is at the discretion of that individual 24 Animal Groups, Power in regardless of rank. (Legitimacy is common in chimpanzee society.) Alliances as Bases for Power An alliance is a joint effort by two or more individuals. Alliances are common in social mammals and are theorized to have evolved from group hunting practices in species such as wolves, lions, and hyenas. However, alliances in agonistic interactions occur in species such as monkeys with no history of group hunting. Agonistic alliances are potentially costly to individuals, who expend energy and risk injury when they intervene to support another, and are potentially beneficial to recipients, who obtain valuable support against opponents. In primate groups, support is primarily but not completely limited to kin. In the social economy, support may be exchanged for other resources. Researchers have used statistical models to predict alliances within groups. Several interesting findings have emerged from these models that also have been substantiated by direct observation of alliance behavior in many species. These models assume that an individual’s probability of future wins and losses is influenced by the outcome of past interactions; for example, that “winner” and “loser” effects are in operation. Winning tends to beget winning and losing tends to beget losing as winner effects enhance the probability of winning, whereas loser effects enhance the probability of losing. Under certain conditions, winner and loser effects both favor coalition formation as they factor into the equation that determines the risks and benefits of an agonistic encounter. Because dominants benefit most from the status quo, they are likely to intervene to maintain it. Many studies have also found that subordinates are often the victims of agonistic alliances. This is because of an increased probability of winning against an individual who has previously demonstrated weakness. Similarly, third-party intervention on the behalf of dominants is common as dominants are more likely to win. There are conditions under which subordinates will gang up on and usurp a dominant. Dominants who win later retaliate, so subordinates rarely act against a dominant unless victory is certain, as is the case if the dominant has been injured and is disabled. Homicide at the hands of an individual’s own group members is an important cause of death in adult males of many primate species. Such homicides nearly always happen when one male is outnumbered by an alliance. Homicide by alliance also occurs in the context of animal warfare as discussed later. Alliance behavior is not strictly the purview of males. Females in a number of species do participate in agonistic alliances against other females and against males. Females may also participate with males in an agonistic alliance. Females who are members of losing parties can expect to be physically punished by dominant males. However, dominant males have an interest in keeping breeding females in the group and garnering their favor. Decisions about punishing subordinates are therefore calculated. Animal Warfare In animal species, power may be held by individuals and by groups of individuals as resources are held by both individuals and the collective. When resources are held and defended by a collective, the stage is set for war or agonistic encounters between groups. The laws that govern agonistic encounters within a group also govern agonistic encounters between groups. These encounters are more likely when one group perceives itself to be relatively more powerful than another. Groups therefore may advertise their presence to each other visually and vocally as a way of deterring costly attacks. Warfare is most likely when one group has a numerical advantage over another. Wolves, lions, hyenas, and primates are most likely to attack when they encounter a lone member of another group. Coalitions may patrol the boundary of the group’s territory in search of rivals to attack. If enough members of a rival group are killed, the offensive troop can take possession of another group’s territory. Correlates and Consequences of Power in Animal Groups The correlates of power in animal groups are essentially the correlates of dominance. Dominant males often have higher testosterone and may have lower glucocorticoid levels, depending on the species and Appeasement the stability of the hierarchy. Higher glucocorticoid levels in subordinates may contribute toward a dominant’s basis for power (legitimacy) because high hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal (HPA) activity may physiologically facilitate an individual’s acceptance of the submissive role. Dominant males have more mating opportunity and reproductive success, especially when elevated HPA activity in subordinates inhibits reproduction (e.g., some cooperative breeders). Dominant females have greater fecundity and greater offspring survival. Dominants signal their status and willingness to defend it with both visual and auditory displays. Dominants are sought-after partners for social interactions and are more frequently groomed by and tend to do less grooming of other individuals. Power emboldens animals that possess it because powerful individuals are free to act without punishment from other group members. The behavior of the powerful is, however, checked by the need to maintain favor with subordinates to prevent their participation in coalitions and by the need to keep subordinates in the group. Small groups are subject to attack by other, larger groups; in many species, it can take years to replace an adult male group member. The need to have a critical number of males places constraints on the practice of homicide in species where males stay in their native groups and cannot be recruited from outside. Conclusion Power is defined similarly in animal and human groups. Strategies for achieving power are also similar in animals and humans. There is support for the notion that negotiating power dynamics is cognitively demanding and may have contributed to the evolution of intelligence. The correlates and consequences of power are no less prominent in animal societies. Animals commit murder and go to war in the service of power. These activities are a significant part of group life for the species that engage in them. Through studying power dynamics in animal societies, we learn that these dynamics are not part of what make humans uniquely Homo sapiens. Liane J. Leedom See also Bases of Power; Female Leadership Among Mammals; Raven, Bertram 25 Further Readings Bergmüller, R., Johnstone, R. A., Russell, A. F., & Bshary, R. (2007). Integrating cooperative breeding into theoretical concepts of cooperation. Behavioural Processes, 76(2), 61–72. Byrne, R. W. (2007). Ape society: Trading favours. Current Biology, 17(17), R775–776. Keltner, D., Gruenfeld, D. H., & Anderson, C. (2003). Power, approach, and inhibition. Psychological Review, 110(2), 265–284. Raven, B. H. (2008). The bases of power and the power/ interaction model of interpersonal influence. Analyses of Social Issues and Public Policy, 8(1), 1–22. Wrangham, R. W. (1999). Evolution of coalitionary killing. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, Suppl 29, 1–30. APPARATUS See Dispositif APPEASEMENT The term appeasement still carries negative connotations associated with the failure of Britain and France to contain Adolf Hitler’s Germany and stop the onset of war. Appeasement was a respectable term almost until the outbreak of World War II, signifying the pursuit of peace. Many believed World War I had been an avoidable conflict caused by an arms buildup and lack of understanding between nations of their grievances. Accordingly, appeasement was the policy of the British and French governments with respect to German and Italian territorial ambitions. Italy aimed to take over Abyssinia (now Ethiopia) in Africa; Germany laid claim initially to the demilitarized Rhineland, then to Sudetenland in Czechoslovakia. Many believed that Germany had been harshly treated in the Versailles Treaty and, though they did not trust Hitler, felt that German claims over the Rhineland were reasonable. When Hitler’s troops entered (under orders to withdraw if France responded), he was asked to negotiate, and he proposed a nonaggression pact, though no such pact was ever signed. The Sudetenland had a 26 Arendt, Hannah large German population and Sudetenland Nazis demanded autonomy that was virtually granted by the Czech government. However, this did not satisfy the Nazis, and Germany began to demand that the Sudetenland be incorporated into Germany. In September 1938, British Prime Minister Neville Chamberlain negotiated directly with Hitler in a meeting in Munich with the leaders of France (Édouard Daladier) and Italy (Benito Mussolini). A peace treaty was signed between Britain and Germany, allowing Chamberlain on his return a famous photo opportunity, flourishing a paper and claiming “peace for our time.” After more concessions to Germany, Britain finally declared war on September 3, 1939, after Germany had entered Poland 2 days earlier. The fate of the term appeasement was sealed. The appeasement of Germany has been blamed on Chamberlain personally, but the policy was popular at the time, and historians now argue that there was little other course for Britain than to try to contain Hitler, though France and the United Kingdom could have taken a stronger line at certain times. Britain did rearm during the 2 years before the outbreak of war, so alongside appeasement went the policy of preparing for war. Modern historians thus look much more favorably on Chamberlain and his policies than did those in the immediate postwar period, though appeasement as a concept will probably never regain its once positive connotations. Keith Dowding See also Balance of Power; Defensive Realism; Extended Deterrence; Fascism; Realism in International Relations Further Readings Neville, P. (2006). Hitler and appeasement: The British attempt to prevent the Second World War. London: Continuum. Taylor, A. J. P. (1961). The origins of the Second World War. London: Hamilton. ARENDT, HANNAH (1906–1975) The political philosopher Hannah Arendt’s conception of power is distinctive. It is rooted in a political philosophy that celebrates the public realm of freedom that emerges when people act with others as citizens or political equals. Arendt believed power is actualized where people act together to sustain or to change the world they share with one another. Her fundamental claim is that power is consensual, referring to humans acting in concert. Power is never the property of an individual but of the groups acting together. Arendt is quite self-conscious in rejecting standard assumptions about power, arguing that political scientists and theorists have obscured its nature ever since Plato. Regardless of political orientation, thinkers have assumed that the first question of politics is, “Who rules whom?” Arendt’s rejection of this assumption may seem idealistic, utopian, or simply incredible. It is, however, offered by an author whose first major work was a three-volume study of totalitarianism, a work that entertains no illusions about violence, terror, and domination and that remains one of the landmarks of 20th-century political science. Nevertheless, in developing her account of power, Arendt firmly insists on James Madison’s maxim, “All governments rest on opinion”—and not, therefore, on qualities that we more often associate with power, such as rulership or coercion. She even claims that violence is a “marginal phenomenon” in the political realm, which may look like a reductio ad absurdum of the claim that “opinion” forms the basis of government. Though seemingly eccentric, these claims are based on profound reflections about the nature of politics. Arendt’s basic criticism of the political science of her day concerned its failure to make distinctions. Accordingly, she distinguishes power from a series of concepts that political science often refers to under that name—violence, rulership, and authority (not to mention force and sheer strength). Although these concepts may appear functionally alike, inasmuch as each may involve one person doing something that another wants or expects that person to do, Arendt nonetheless discerns crucial differences. The next part of this entry considers her thoughts on power rather than violence, before turning to the more elusive notion of authority. (More elusive partly because Arendt’s most obvious discussion of authority [“What is Authority?”] is largely historical and fits awkwardly with her later comments in “On Violence.” This entry touches only on the latter.) Arendt, Hannah Arendt draws two main contrasts between power and violence. Although power is, in a sense that we will return to, “an end-in-itself,” violence is primarily instrumental. That is, violence is justified in human relations as a means to secure particular ends, and it is more justifiable as a means, the nearer and more certain those ends are. However, Arendt continually underlines the unpredictability of political action, violent and nonviolent, and the role played by sheer accident in human affairs. Thinking of Plato’s metaphors of rulership—the philosopherking who “makes” the ideal republic as the craftsperson makes a table—she writes, “Since the end of human action, as distinct from the end products of fabrication, can never be reliably predicted, the means used to achieve political goals are more often than not of greater relevance to the future world than the intended goals” (1972, p. 106). Thus, Arendt does not deny that violence may have many effects on the political realm, but trenchantly observes that the most likely change violence makes is to a world where the exercise of violence becomes more usual. No matter how limited, strategic, or effective violence may be, its instrumentality sharply marks it off from power. “Far from being the means to an end, [power] is actually the very condition enabling a group of people to think and act in terms of the means-end category” (1972, p. 150). That is, there is power wherever people cooperate to pursue shared ends and wherever they address the question, What ends will we act in concert to pursue? As Arendt contends, any answer to the question, “To what end is power a means?” will either be vacuous (“to enable men to live together”) or dangerously utopian (“to promote happiness or to realise a classless society”—1972, p. 150f). Thus for Arendt, power does not call for any justification because it is bound up with the very existence of political communities. A second key contrast: Arendt argues that power cannot be centralized whereas violence must be, if it is to be effective. Again, the point is easier to see with regard to violence. Unless it is to spell mayhem or warfare, violence requires a relatively small number of people to be tightly organized, who may then dominate others. Power, by contrast, arises where many people broadly share political goals, or invest authority in shared institutions, laws, or holders of political office. Of course, even the community that is most powerful in 27 Arendt’s terms—for instance, where government is seen as legitimate, where institutions remain alive through the combined initiative of many persons— employs violence. But this is as a sanction against lawbreakers, understood as criminals who enjoy no support among their fellow citizens. (Of course, violence also remains as a strategic means that may be used against those outside the community’s boundaries.) In this way, we can see why Arendt claims that violence is marginal to a political realm. Such limited uses of coercion are a far cry from systematic violence against those who are courageous or foolhardy enough to challenge a more or less tyrannical government—one that most subjects obey only for fear of coercive sanctions. This second contrast has an important corollary. Violence will be the more necessary, the less a government enjoys the real consent of those governed. Arendt argues that violence becomes more tempting to rulers, the more they feel that support is ebbing away from their regimes and the less ready their “subjects” are to cooperate in their rule: “rule by sheer violence comes into play where power is being lost” (1972, p. 152). Although obedience may be obtained from the barrel of a gun, power—active support for a mode of government, its laws, and officeholders—cannot. Further, Arendt emphasizes that massive technological developments in the means of violence did not prevent the revolutions of the 20th century (nor did they decide the outcome of a war such as that in Vietnam). Rather, increasingly powerless rulers found that the arms changed hands and that armies and police forces no longer acted on their behalf. (Nicolae Ceauescu’s fall in 1989 is exemplary here.) Power in Arendt’s sense does not require unanimity of opinion—as she stresses, that is never to be found in human affairs. But it does require a consensus on certain goals, aims, or principles of organization, and the latter may give rise to authority. Despite the suspicion of utopianism sometimes felt by her readers, Arendt’s own examples of concerted action are entirely familiar to political science (and indeed, often involve the exercise or threat of violence): revolutionary uprisings (e.g., Hungary, 1956, and Czechoslovakia, 1968), the U.S. civil rights movement and the student movements of the 1960s, even the French resistance against the Nazis. Such movements are relatively short-lived, however. Consensus on constitutional 28 Argument, Power of principles and modes of organization is a more durable and equally important source of power. In this case, common support invests laws and institutions with authority. Arendt stresses that such power and authority are compatible with a “division of powers”; indeed dividing power by checks and balances can actually be a source of power. Think, for instance, of the role a loyal opposition plays within representative democracy: power is kept alive through differences of opinion mediated by shared institutions that embody political authority. Arendt reinterprets the idea of a social contract—where political communities are understood as based on a contract among citizens—to stress the power that arises from mutual promise. Thus, a group of people may bind themselves to a constitution and associated institutions, as in one of her favorite examples from the American Revolution where she claimed power was understood consensually as reciprocity and mutuality rather than the power used by princes or aristocrats that is based on coercion. In conclusion, recall the slogan that Arendt appropriates from Madison, “All governments rest on opinion.” This may, indeed, be the “opinion” of a small, well-organized minority or elite that uses systematic coercion to dominate others—in particular, to prevent others from acting together and hence gaining power to challenge the existing power structure. But concerted action and organization remain essential preconditions for the effective use of political violence. Thus, Arendt is adamant that although violence may destroy power, it can never become a substitute for it. At this fundamental level, even tyranny and totalitarianism rely on the power that arises from joint action—for example, by the apparatus of a secret police. Despite enormous variations in kind and degree, then, all forms of political community have the same basic requirements of power—which rests on shared opinion— and authority—which resides in shared institutions. Garrath Williams See also Coercion and Power; Consensual Power, Theories of; Cooperation; Freedom Further Readings Arendt, H. (1965). On revolution (Rev. ed.). New York: Viking. Arendt, H. (1972). On violence. In Crises of the republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Arendt, H. (2004). The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Schocken Books. (Original work published 1951) Issac, J. (1998). Oases in the desert: Hannah Arendt on democratic politics. In G. Williams (Ed.), Hannah Arendt: Critical assessments of leading political philosophers (Vol. 2, pp. 130–154). London: Routledge. Kateb, G. (2000). Political action: Its nature and advantages. In D. Villa (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Hannah Arendt (pp. 130–148). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Ricoeur, P. (2006). Power and violence (Trans. R. Hausheer). In G. Williams (Ed.), Hannah Arendt: Critical assessments of leading political philosophers (Vol. 3, pp. 389–407). London: Routledge. Waldron, J. (2000). Arendt’s constitutional politics. In G. Williams (Ed.), Hannah Arendt: Critical assessments of leading political philosophers (Vol. 3, pp. 135–153). London: Routledge. ARGUMENT, POWER OF Argument is the provision of reasons to justify a conclusion. One alternative is bargaining where the interested parties “cut a deal” so that they all satisfy at least some of their interests. Another alternative is assertion, where willfulness is sufficient justification for proposed action. Assertion goes straight to the conclusion, bypassing the process of justification. Why is justification important? The answer takes us to the power of argument: justification disconnects judgments of the legitimacy of the proposal from the quantum of power of the proposer (“do it or else”) and reconnects them to the qualitative merits of the proposal (“I accept your reasons”). This entry deals mainly with the public power of argument in managing social and political conflict, but says little about the pure power of logic or the framework of fallacies of bad argument treated in philosophical analysis. Argument involves claims about evidence and usually stops short of conclusive demonstration. Argument is usually part of a process of debate with different sides contending for different propositions. The frequency of references to “a good argument” conveys this debating dimension to argument, with different sides contending “for” or Argument, Power of “against” the main propositions or even the very agenda of business. As a result, many “good arguments” are inconclusive; at the end of the day, there is no agreement among contending parties about the right conclusion or sometimes even the right debating process. So why bother with argument if the prospect of agreement is low? Belief in the value of argument rests on two sets of views of the power of argument. The first set relates to the power of argument “in theory” and the second set relates to this power “in practice.” The former deals with the capacity of argument to contribute to philosophical debate, whereas the latter deals with the contribution of argument to practical debate over political and social affairs. These two sets of theory and practice are related in the same ways that theoretical and practical reasoning are related. Theoretical reasoning can be seen as the primary form of argument and practical reasoning the secondary form. Thus, the power of argument in theoretical discourse provides one venerable standard for assessing the available powers of argument found in practical discussion. The more open public decision making can be made to the norms of argument, the more likely it is that conflict will be resolved impartially through due processes of decision making—that is, with decisions based on the merits of the argument as distinct from decisions reflecting the interests of those engaged in argument. Democracy is historically associated with the belief in the power of argument. Classical Athens had its moment of high democracy, and Thucydides’ History provides portraits of decent public argument marshaled by rare leaders such as Pericles (e.g., Thucydides II, 34–46) and case studies of moving public debate involving contending arguments by such rhetorically gifted speakers as Cleon and Diodotus (e.g., Thucydides III, 36–50). The best case for this inspiring world of democratic argument is probably that left by Aristotle, whose Politics pays due respect to public reason but whose Rhetoric lays out the real power of argument in the public sphere. And here we see the limited nature of practical argument when compared with the philosophy standard. Political argument is an exercise in rhetorical as well as philosophical power, adapting theory to the demands of rhetoric to get the required assent. Think of this as a theory of the second best: the power of argument in public 29 affairs is less than the ideal available in pure theory, but the ideal is not practically feasible. The lesson from Aristotle is that the operational power of practical argument comes down to the blend of three elements: the ethos or perceived character of the argument maker, the pathos or mood of the audience, and finally (and perhaps least powerfully), the merits of the logos or core reasoning of the argument. Aristotle occupies only one end of the political spectrum. For every Aristotelian realist, there are many other democratic idealists with greater hopes for the power of argument. But can the imperfect world of practical affairs really be modeled on the rigors of impartial philosophical argument? Plato’s Republic sketches one famous answer, with its thesis that philosophers must become kings. But what about the real world as we know it, where political power is exercised by nonphilosophers: how can the potential power of argument be realized? Believers in the pure power of argument often become despondent in the face of persistent social conflict. If only those engaged in conflict would lay down their arms and instead take up arguments and agree to abide by an impartial arbitration of the issues on the merits. The everyday realities of power seem to imply that argument might be pure but it is powerless if left to itself. Argument needs friends, notably a friend at court where real power rests in the hands of those who rule, typically without any obligation to rule impartially or engage in open argument. Among those who have championed the power of argument in practical affairs are some of the most influential makers of modernity, particularly the architects of liberal constitutionalism such as Benedict Spinoza, John Locke, and Immanuel Kant. Their constitutional design principles included many devices that protect the power of argument by dispersing political power away from traditional concentrations (such as unlimited monarchies) in favor of the rule of law through a formal separation of ruling powers into several distinct branches of government. The separation of powers strives to promote argument in political life through checks and balances to blunt the power of assertion and willfulness in ways that promote open argument over the use and abuse of public power. Two examples can round out this discussion. Contemporary democracy honors the power of 30 Aristotle argument in two important ways. First, democratic theory celebrates “deliberative democracy” as a regulatory ideal where equality of opportunity to engage in political argument is matched to procedural norms of engagement inspired by an “ideal speech situation” of honest argument, as though all must now meet the high standard of argument set by Pericles. A deliberative democracy reinforces argument through fair discussion processes. Second, over recent decades, the practical world of public policy analysis has taken “an argumentative turn” and embraced the power of argument, with the result that policy analysis itself has become part of the wider argument about ends and not simply an instrument of policy delivery. Democratic policy analysts are thus encouraged to inject themselves into the deliberative domain through analysis about argument as well as argument about analysis. In both these developments, argument has become central to the action of contemporary democracy. John Uhr See also Aristotle; Authority; Bargaining; Discourse; Persuasion Further Readings Barry, B. (1965). Political argument. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Garver, E. (2004). For the sake of argument: Practical reasoning, character and the ethics of belief. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Majone, G. (1989). Evidence, argument and persuasion in the policy process. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. ARISTOTLE (384–322 BCE) Aristotle was a Greek philosopher of Macedonian descent. His studies of physics, biology, psychology, metaphysics, logic, rhetoric, poetics, economics, and other subjects made him the most outstanding thinker of his age, if not of all time. His ideas about power, especially about political power, have influenced thinkers up to the present day. In ontology, Aristotelian power is synonymous with potency, which has three aspects: as a source of change, as a capacity for performance, or as a condition making a thing unchangeable. His thinking on this matter was standard fare until the Enlightenment, when Thomas Hobbes rejected the latter two criteria and redefined the first, to see power only as the source of motion. In psychology, Aristotle thought of power in terms of capacity for performance, defining, for example, talent in rhetoric as the power (dynamis) to discern what will be persuasive in each domain. Psychological powers can be active or passive, operative or receptive, and immediate or remote. Hobbes altered this definition, so that psychological power or faculty was a capacity to make or receive change. Like his teacher, Plato, Aristotle took politics to be the most important subject in human life. The art of statecraft is the highest art because it affects the entire social environment, including every art practiced within it. As a subject matter, politics is the study of humans in groups, whereas ethics is the study of the individual in isolation. Only “a beast or a god” can actually live in isolation, and thus humans are social animals. They are also rational animals, and their rationality chooses ends from among possible ends and in doing so attempts to realize a share of human nature by choosing the best or the better from among any set of proposals. Political studies are the most important studies partly because they can improve the art of statecraft, and partly because they enable us to realize our natures as choosers of the better in the highest and weightiest affairs. The only kind of state Aristotle discusses at length was the city-state or polis. Nation-states, that is, states having more than one population center, were too large for their members to be addressed by a single herald in a single assembly and, hence, were too large to be effectively governed. In addition, the population centers were bound to differ in their religious observances, leading to strife. The polis is a natural result of human association. The basic unit of association is the family. Families associate together to form villages, and the polis results from the association of villages. Each association aims at achieving some end thought of as good, and thus, the polis is an Arms Race association aiming at a good. This definition has always left open the question of whether Aristotle is more conventionalist or contractarian. It has also allowed his thinking to influence both schools. The fact that the chief goods for which the polis aims are self-sufficiency and stability—two cognates of power—allows his thinking to influence other theorists, such as Niccolò Machiavelli, who see the accumulation of power as the aim of the state. Political power corresponds to the position of command in a command–obey relationship. The command–obey relationship is a natural phenomenon, likely to emerge wherever two or more persons join in a common endeavor. Hence, any association, no matter how temporary, might feature it. The position of command can be used in two ways: either in the interests of the whole, which accords with justice; or in the interests of those who rule, which accords with despotism. Although there are two ways to rule, there are three forms of rule according to Aristotle. The forms are rule by one, by a few, or by all. Each form of rule realizes a better or worse result depending on how often its agents exercise power justly or despotically. Hence, the good form of rule by one is monarchy, in which the ruler frequently takes action, or is perceived as taking action, for the sake of all. The degenerate form of rule by one is tyranny, in which the ruler acts despotically. The good form of rule by the few is aristocracy; its degenerate form is oligarchy, in which the ruling class acts despotically in its own interests. The good form of rule by the whole is called polity, in which the demos (the whole population) acts in the interests of the whole. The degenerate form is called democracy, in which the mob rules in favor of itself, which usually means stripping the rich of their wealth and the better of their honors. The polis is an imitation of the family and village, and so, because they are monarchic, it too was originally monarchic. However, it soon became susceptible to all forms of rule. Degenerate forms of rule are unstable because they create opponents of the state. States are defined by their constitutions. Regardless of the form of rule, the chief causes of instability are inequality and injustice. In either case, a segment of the population feels it is not receiving from the state what it deserves. Radical change of constitution, that is, revolution, could proceed from two 31 likely sources, from a despotic administration, or from a segment of the population anxious to change the state for its own sake, or both. The classes most likely to seek revolution were the rich and the poor. The rich feel that existing laws hold them back. The poor feel that existing laws hold them down. Only the middle class feels that existing rules work to its advantage and are worth preserving. Hence, the secret of stability, a variety of power, was a large middle class able to collectively resist resentment of the state whether it emanated from the rich or the poor. Bryan Finken See also Ability; Authority; Hobbes, Thomas; Machiavelli, Niccolò; Persuasion; Power To and Power Over; Rationality; Rhetoric Further Readings Aristotle. (1984). Politics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Kraut, R., & Skultety, S. (Eds.). (2005). Aristotle’s politics: Critical essays. New York: Rowman & Littlefield. ARMS RACE The term arms race can be used to describe any competitive situation where the goal of each competitor is to stay ahead of the others. The phrase came into common parlance in descriptions of the causes of World War I, where it has been suggested that the major European protagonists— Austria–Hungary, France, Germany, Russia, and the United Kingdom—increased their armed forces to match what they saw their rivals doing. It has been argued that the massive increase in those forces and the tensions between the states over trade and empire inevitably led to war. In more recent times, during the cold war, a nuclear arms race developed between the two superpowers—the United States and the Soviet Union—as each eyed the other’s nuclear weapons, and both increased their first-strike capabilities. Similar arms races with both conventional and 32 Authoritarian Personality nuclear weapons can be seen in different parts of the world: between India and Pakistan, between Israel and Arab nations in the Middle East, between North and South Korea, and at various times between neighboring African and South American countries. Lewis F. Richardson mathematically modeled arms races. He suggested three motives led nations in peacetime to increase or decrease their armaments. First, revenge or hostility to another nation; second, fear; and third, working in the opposite direction to reduce weapons to economize. Tension and past hostility obviously increase the probability of an arms race. Richardson’s work has been studied extensively by mathematicians, economists, and others and applied to arms races between nations and to firms in competitive markets. The term arms race is now also extensively used in evolutionary contexts to describe the dynamic evolution of aspects of plants and animals. For any two species that compete in a given environment, any improvement in one species will lead it to have an evolutionary advantage over its rival. Thus, if the rival species is not to decline to extinction, it must also improve in some respect. Thus, two different grass-grazing animals must each increase their ability to drive off the other from scarce grassland. The prey must match an increase in the speed or agility of a predator. Over time, a species might lose some of the features that made it more competitive: it might become less agile, but expend its resources on other features, perhaps stronger bones or warmer coats, that advantage it in other ways. The evolution of reproduction is an important consequence of arms races and enables species to evolve more swiftly. In evolutionary biology, this has been termed the red queen hypothesis, after the Red Queen’s dictum (in Lewis Carroll’s Through the Looking Glass) that one must keep running to stay in the same place. In evolutionary terms, this translates to finding that the probability of any species surviving over geological time remains constant (outside of major environmental changes) despite its constant improvement in its members’ ability to compete. Coevolutionary processes are not arms races, but can improve “cooperating species” against other species. The evolutionary finding can then be applied back to markets where firms must keep improving products to give themselves the same chance of surviving, and countries must keep improving their weapons to keep the same probability of winning future battles. As with coevolutionary processes, cooperation between firms can enable them to keep their market positions without improving, whereas countries might tie their futures together through trade, thus reducing the probability of future conflict and, consequently, of arms races. Thus, we can see arms races have both advantages and disadvantages. Keith Dowding See also Conventional Deterrence; Deterrence Theory; Deterrent Threats; Spiral Model Further Readings Richardson, L. F. (1960). Arms and insecurity: A mathematical study of the origins and causes of war. Pittsburgh, PA: Boxwood Press. Ridley, M. (1996). The red queen: Sex and the evolution of human nature. New York: Penguin. AUTHORITARIAN PERSONALITY The term authoritarian personality was first coined during the early 1940s as a means of describing such individuals as Adolf Hitler and Benito Mussolini—that is, a specific set of behavioral characteristics was mapped out for people with political beliefs that were both extremist and antidemocratic. Abraham Maslow, the famed humanistic psychologist, first used the term, but Erich Fromm, the German psychoanalyst, wrote about the “authoritarian character.” However, the seminal The Authoritarian Personality, by Theodor W. Adorno and his colleagues at the University of California at Berkeley, put the term into the lexicon of everyday use. In 1950, the Nazi Holocaust had only been public knowledge for 5 years, and many in academia and government wanted to understand how such a tragedy could have occurred. Many felt that if one could quantify the psychological basis for antiSemitism, it might be possible to prevent the same thing from ever happening again. Freudian psychoanalysis was, during that era, the primary Authoritarian Personality tool used in explaining the dynamics of the human personality. Some of the key qualities of the authoritarian personality included the following: 1. Conventionalism—a personality construct where one tended to accept and obey all social norms, especially the rules of authority figures. 2. Aggression—the exhibition of aggression toward groups or individuals the state did not like. This is especially true for specific groups that threatened the state’s values and morals. In addition, it is an aggressive attitude toward people or organizations that the state finds particularly noxious. 3. Submission—when one submits to those in authority. 4. Anti-Intraception—when an individual thinks that subjective attitudes are bad, and “public” and “objective” are exalted. 5. Substitution—instead of rational beliefs, superstition and fatalistic determinism are the norm. 6. Power and Toughness—a heavy identification with those in power, as well as an excessive emphasis on citizens acting in a “tough” manner. 7. Destructiveness and Cynicism—one should not feel compassion or empathy toward individuals or groups considered enemies by the state. 8. Projection—the tendency to believe in the existence of evil in the world and to project unconscious emotional impulses outward, especially to individuals demonized by the state, for example, the Jews in Germany, the intellectuals in China, or the Kulaks in the Soviet Union. 9. Excessive Conformity—the belief that one should comport oneself in a manner that never diverges from the socially accepted norm. 10. Insecurity—the fear that if one ever shows any “weakness,” then one is compromised; thus, one must remain strong at all times. 11. Sex—exaggerated concerns regarding “appropriate” sexuality. According to Adorno, individuals who admire fascist ideologies tend to think and act in a manner 33 highlighting their dysfunctional views. This often results in a close match between thought and behavior, with anti-Semitism and ethnocentrism standing in close connection with this particular personality structure. For instance, Nazis saw Jews as subhuman, and thus, Jews were treated as beneath contempt and, though not to the same extent, so were homosexuals, Slavs, and Gypsies and those regarded as “enemies” of the state. If this theory is accepted, then fascistic behavior is nothing more than the expression of personality structure; that is, if an individual with authoritarian personality lives in a “right-wing” society, then the government usually supports his or her racist behavior. Generally speaking, authoritarian personality has usually referred to right-wing thought and behavior; however, after the fall of communism in 1991, the term was also used to encompass such individuals as Vladimir Lenin, Joseph Stalin, and Mao Tsetung. Their absolute lack of empathy for others, and their cruelty and spite toward anyone not agreeing with their political views were strikingly similar to the behavior exhibited by Hitler. On average, authoritarian personality is still used primarily for ultraconservatives such as religious fundamentalists, military dictators, theocrats, and so on. Adorno felt that two distinctive behavior patterns coexisted within each authoritarian personality: submissiveness and aggression. At first glance, the two are diametrically opposed, but they actually work together. The authoritarian wants to fit into a chain of command and to be told what to do (submissive to a superior), and similarly, will accept no discussion when giving orders to those in the hierarchy below. At the same time, he or she is often highly aggressive toward others, especially those considered lesser in some way (not as intelligent, not as strong, not as cultured). For instance, individuals from a different race or ethnicity and individuals professing a different religious faith (or atheism) are often considered subhuman. Authoritarians also enjoy being bossed (think of Heinrich Himmler’s devotion to Hitler) as much as they enjoy telling others what to do (Himmler with his adjutant Reinhard Heydrich). One primary factor thought to be needed for the formation of the authoritarian personality was a pattern of strict and rigid parenting, in which obedience is instilled through physical punishment and harsh verbal discipline (as found in both Hitler’s 34 Authoritarian Personality and Stalin’s lives). In this scenario, almost no parental praise or affection is shown, independence is discouraged (the child should seek the parent’s permission for most things), and the child’s behavior is expected to meet a set standard (if it does not, punishment may result). Significantly, such parents instill in their children obedience to their parents but also a sense of loyalty to a social hierarchy, entailing obedience to all persons of higher status (once again, Hitler with Paul von Hindenburg, and Stalin with Lenin). Once adulthood is reached, authoritarian individuals tend to exhibit their accumulated hostility and anger by forming negative stereotypes and discriminating against or overtly persecuting any group or individual thought to be beneath them; for instance, showing prejudice against those from a lower socioeconomic status, education, or family background. The use of projection (placing one’s own perceived or actual weaknesses on a group or individual that is less likely to fight back) is also considered a primary trait in the authoritarian personality. Other traits include depending on authority and rigid rules, with little to no deviation from social values and admiring individuals in power. Robert Altemeyer developed the Right Wing Authoritarianism (RWA) scale, an assessment instrument based on Adorno’s conception of authoritarian personality. Altemeyer proposed that just 3 facets of the authoritarian personality (not 10 as originally conceptualized by Adorno) were significant (in a statistical sense): conventionalism, authoritarian aggression, and authoritarian submission. Conventionalism is defined as one accepting and obeying social conventions and laws espoused by those in power, whereas authoritarian aggression is aggression aimed at anyone or anything disliked by the authorities. In essence, the RWA scale gauges the following: 1. Faulty reasoning—RWAs are more likely to c c c c Make many incorrect inferences from evidence. Hold contradictory ideas leading them to “speak out of both sides of their mouths.” Uncritically accept that many problems are “our most serious problem.” Uncritically accept insufficient evidence to support their beliefs. c c Uncritically trust people who tell them what they want to hear. Use many double standards in their thinking and judgments. 2. Hostility toward out-groups—RWAs are more likely to c c c c c c c Weaken constitutional guarantees of liberty such as the Bill of Rights. Show harsh punishment toward “common” criminals in a role-playing situation. Admit they obtain personal pleasure from punishing such people. Be prejudiced against racial, ethnic, nationalistic, and linguistic minorities. Be hostile toward homosexuals. Volunteer to help the government persecute almost anyone. Be mean-spirited toward those who have made mistakes and suffered. 3. Profound character attributes—RWAs are more likely to c c c c c c c Be dogmatic. Be zealots. Be hypocrites. Be absolutists. Be bullies when they have power over others. Help cause and inflame intergroup conflict. Seek dominance over others by exhibiting competitive destructiveness in situations requiring cooperation. 4. Blindness to their own failings and to the failings of authority figures whom they respect—RWAs are more likely to c c c c Believe that they are right in almost everything. Never learn anything helpful from past failings. Exhibit a self-righteous attitude. Use religion to take away any feelings of pity toward others, that is, doing what God wants. The etiology of authoritarian personality begins in childhood. Sigmund Freud felt that one’s personality values came primarily from the father (it should be remembered that in psychoanalysis, most workings of the mind are unconscious), and that these social norms and mores were internalized Authoritarian Personality during the child’s development. As the child attempts to understand his or her ultra-strict father by behaving in a manner pleasing to the parent, the superego is produced. In essence, Freudian theory states that the child realizes that one’s desires and wishes must be submerged and continually held in abeyance; otherwise, the child will face the crushing punishment from a very unforgiving father. In other words, we can never show our true feelings because they are at odds with society. In addition, Freud felt that an individual with unresolved unconscious conflicts would ease his or her personality problems by projecting fears, drives, and aggression onto other people. Two examples illustrate this principle: someone with latent homosexuality projects his or her yearnings onto confirmed homosexuals, stating they are wicked and immoral. A person who feels that he or she may have the “blood” of a hated minority feels that minority members are “dirty,” “racially impure,” or “unfit for life.” In general, ethnic, political, or religious minorities are selected as a screen for these projections because they are members of a class of social undesirables; thus, one need not fear any social sanctions, such as the need to worry about criminal charges if one beats up a member of a minority group. On the other hand, if charges are filed, there is little need to fear a prison sentence. Another psychoanalytic perspective comes from Alfred Adler. Adlerian therapy is concerned primarily with the individual gaining superiority over his or her environment, and in an authoritarian personality, this striving for transcendence over others is a neurosis, usually emerging as an aggressive need to overcome one’s neuroses (“I must be cold and hard to that person for if I am not, people will know how weak I am”). Authoritarians need to keep control and prove their innate ability over others is rooted in a mental world full of enemies, no equality or empathy, and no mutual benefit. Wilhelm Reich, another renowned psychoanalyst, postulated that middle-class fathers may have had to accept abuse from the ruling class, but at home, the fathers were the kings and masters, forcing their families to exhibit the obedience they showed in the workplace. In essence, this social structure yielded generations of individuals who never questioned why they were subservient to an 35 entire class of people; that is, it was natural to show submission to one’s “betters.” Within the family, the father held the same position that his boss held over him in the production process, and he reproduced this subservient attitude toward authority in his children, particularly in his sons. From such social conditions, allegiance to the “leader” became standard behavior, that is, showing passivity and servility to authority figures. Hence, it was hypothesized an authoritarian personality arose in a family where the father ruled everyone with an iron hand, and the mother exhibited deference toward her husband. The father was very strict, punishing the child at the slightest transgression of the rules the father had established. In this environment, children learned that they could not fight those in power because they were too strong. Instead, the children quickly realized that it was smarter to express their aggression toward weak individuals, or those who were also victims of their father’s heavy-handedness. Possible victims were usually individuals or groups that the father hated; thus, aggression against them was both tolerated and sanctioned. Scholars quit using psychoanalysis as a means of plumbing the depths of authoritarian personality decades ago, primarily because it is impossible to verify Freud’s notions regarding the conscious and unconscious. Authoritarianism may also be described as a government emphasizing social control that is exemplified by strict obedience to the state’s authority, with control being maintained by the harsh use of oppressive measures. Authoritarian regimes are renowned for being hierarchical. In other words, citizens must obey state authority in different areas in their lives, and if they do not, they run the risk of facing trouble. For instance, being able to move to a new city within one’s state or country, without conferring with authorities, is a right taken for granted in the West. However, relocating without permission within some countries is a grave offense—with the offending individual receiving hefty fines or worse. It has been shown that a link exists between authoritarianism and collectivism (in the Soviet Union, the People’s Republic of China under Mao, and other communist states). In both cases, individual rights and goals are subjugated to group goals, expectations, and conformities. Individuals with authoritarian personality are attracted to these types of governments. 36 Authority Instead of focusing on a specific personality type or syndrome, some scholars feel that authoritarianism occurs in specific situations and that the authoritarian personality has two primary facets: the desire for life to remain the same, and a strong dislike for change or difference. Conformity, respect for tradition (though not in all cases), and the use of coercion when necessary to ensure conformity are important values to those with authoritarian personality. Perceiving potential threats triggers this trait, though accounts vary regarding what causes fear in authoritarians. Scholars wonder whether authoritarianism is a type of personality or a trait/disposition, with both having implications. If authoritarianism is a static personality type, its effect should remain constant over time (or if changing, negligibly). Conversely, if authoritarianism is a situational-sensitive phenomenon, a premise more consistent with a disposition, its effect might differ depending on the circumstances. That is, the impact of authoritarianism on individuals tends to wax and wane depending on the specific context or situation, especially levels of threat—not just any threat, but one that unconsciously triggers authoritarianism. Cary Stacy Smith and Li-Ching Hung See also Adorno, Theodor; Power, Cognition, and Behavior; Right-Wing Authoritarianism Further Readings Adorno, T. W., Frenkel-Brunswik, E., Levinson, D. J., & Sanford, R. N. (1950). The authoritarian personality. New York: Harper & Row. Altemeyer, R. (2007). The authoritarian specter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. AUTHORITY The concept of authority is closely related to that of power. However, many writers suggest that it is possible for an agent to have power without authority or, conversely, authority without power. Thus, power and authority are two entirely different concepts. Authority, unlike power, is usually thought to have greater normative force. That is, if someone is in authority, this gives that person some legal or normative right to issue commands and be obeyed. Those under the authority of another have a duty to obey the authoritative commands of the person in authority. Of course, those with legal authority might overstep their rights in issuing commands or issue commands that are immoral. Furthermore, if a legal system is itself immoral, then we might not consider the legal authorities to be legitimate in issuing commands. However, neither of these points detracts from the point that the idea of authority itself gives normative force, and the concept is one imbued with rights and duties. The central question concerning the concept of authority is why people should subordinate themselves to it. The question itself presupposes some liberal notion that people are free and relinquishing that freedom requires justification, but this does not make the central question any less important. A distinction often made in the literature is between a person in a position of authority and a person who is an authority. Someone who is an authority is a person considered knowledgeable or expert in some area. We consult people who are authorities in this sense to gain advice and information. Thus, one academic might consult another on a subject about which the latter is deemed particularly knowledgeable. We turn to doctors for advice regarding medical conditions or to lawyers for legal advice. These people can be considered authorities in their particular areas. And they too can recognize other actors as more authoritative than they: so doctors and lawyers refer patients and clients to specialist practitioners. We take the advice of those who are authorities in this sense because we believe they know better than we do in the areas in which we consult them. However, we are not obliged legally or morally to follow it through, though in most cases we choose to do so because we believe it in our best interests to do so. We might recognize that advice to be sage—good doctors and lawyers will explain why we should follow their advice— but even when we do not understand the reasoning behind it, we might choose to follow the advice of an expert. When we act in this way, we are said to act for “content-independent” reasons. That is, although we feel justified in carrying out those actions because we trust the expert has good reasons for directing us thus, we do not understand what those good reasons are. Our own reason with Authority regard to the justification of the action itself is “contentless”: “because the expert said so.” We shall see that the concept of content-independent reasons is important for understanding the moral force of authority. Max Weber’s views on authority have been influential in the social sciences. Weber made a distinction between three different types of authority: traditional, charismatic, and rational– legal. Traditional authority is bestowed on an agent because of some convention or long and hallowed tradition that this person is the authority. Kingships traditionally follow the male line, and in many communities, figures such as witch doctors or religious leaders derive their authority hereditarily. Conventions and ways of behaving or documents handed down through the generations might be seen as authoritative simply by tradition. Charismatic authority occurs where the exceptional abilities of a person cause members of a community to obey or follow that person as their leader. Those abilities are not simply some superior physical size, which means that others follow by force or simple fear of the consequences, but rather they perceive it right that the charismatic person leads. The right to lead, or some legitimacy bestowed on an agent, really distinguishes authority either as some subset of power or as a separate component. This is seen more clearly in Weber’s final category, which he defines as characteristic of modern societies. The rational–legal authority of an agent gives that person a right to command and expect compliance because of the office or role the person fills in society. People might be chosen for those roles because of their personal characteristics, but the role or office they hold, rather than those characteristics, defines their authority. Rational–legal authority simply follows the rights bestowed on the holder to make authoritative judgments in given cases. We could see this authority as being bestowed merely because it is efficient for a modern society to have people fulfilling certain roles. However, Weber’s legal–rational category also needs to be placed in the context of his arguments that bureaucrats need to be chosen on merit and to be educated and trained in the role. In that sense, we can see legal–rational authority as being “an” as well as “in” authority. The important element, however, is that the holders are constrained 37 by the rules and principles of their office. Perfect rational–legal authority would leave no room for discretion. In practice, of course, discretion is required for reasons of efficiency. Understanding the importance of the office or role in rational–legal authority also leads us to distinguish different concepts of authority. Someone might have the rights of some role, but not be effective in that role. Teachers at a school have the authority over their pupils given to their position. However, if the teachers do not command the respect of their pupils, either in a disciplinary sense or as enlightening pedagogues, then the teachers may have no authority in another sense. Lacking the respect of their pupils means pupils do not legitimate the teachers’ commands and do not respect their knowledge. Thus, the teachers will have little influence over the pupils. We can make the distinction between de jure authority—one has the right to command—and de facto authority—one actually commands. The important difference between de facto authority and power is that the former is based on reasons for obeying or following the authority. Power might include de facto authority but is a broader concept that encompasses coercion. The distinction between de jure and de facto authority is similar but not identical to that between being an authority and being in authority. We can see that the content-independence of authority also extends to those in authority. Accepting tradition, one might follow the advice of the oracle or the witch doctor even though one does not understand it (perhaps it is not understandable!). One follows the charismatic leader even if one does not know the leader’s plans. The general expects his or her soldiers to follow orders even when they do not know the general’s battle plans. The football coach expects his or her players to follow his or her instructions even if they do not understand his or her tactics. Followers of Islam do not need to know why they are forbidden pork: it is enough to know that they are. We follow conventions and traditions even though we may have no understanding of why we should follow them. The content-independence of authoritative commands is probably its defining feature though enduring authorities are likely to endure because the commands can be justified. One is not likely to continue to follow the advice of a lawyer or a 38 Authority doctor if one sees that others do better following the advice of other doctors or lawyers. We tend to look askance at witch doctors today, but they are unlikely to endure as authorities in their fields if they do not confer some advantage or at least confer no disadvantage over others or over those who never consult them. Conventional forms of behavior are not likely to endure if those communities that follow those conventions or traditions fare less well than communities following different ones. The general who wins battles and the coach who wins matches will command more de facto authority over those below them than will similar generals or coaches who tend to lose. Thus, we define those who are in authority de jure by the rights and duties they derive from their role; we define de facto authority and the authority of the laws and rules governing de jure authority by the content-independence of the rules and the content-independence of the commands given by those in authority. Similarly, we recognize as an authority someone whose views we respect content-independently of our own opinions of those views. But in all cases, the continued respect and legitimacy we place on the authority is liable to be affected by its overall contribution to our interests. We might finally see this in the case of a coordination or collective action problem. We might all recognize that it is best if we all pull in one direction— if we all coordinate our actions toward some specified end rather than following our individual wishes. Imagine cooking a dinner for a large group of people. It might not be advisable for us each to put in the pot our favorite foods and spices; that is the recipe for culinary disaster. However, we find we cannot agree on our precise aim—what dish we should cook—or how to achieve it—which particular recipe we should follow for the dish we do decide on. In such a case, we might all agree that it is best that one person decide what dish should be cooked and allow that person to choose the precise recipe. Even if we all think our own dish is preferable to the one cooked, we can agree that the one cooked is preferable to the dish that would follow from all trying to cook their favorite dishes in the same pot. In choosing one chef, we have given that person authority over our meal for that evening. There need be nothing special about that person— he or she is not charismatic, nor a notably good cook—but there is a role, that of the chef, that we have bestowed on that person. We can rationally give authority to a specific agent, be that an individual or an organization, and follow their commands because we believe that it is in our best interests to do so. Where we believe that an agent is an authority, we might simply feel that they are better suited to making decisions in the agent is that field of authority than we are. We trust our doctor, or lawyer, or the chef because we feel that in the area of decisions that we have given to them, they will be better judges, overall, than we are. In other situations, we might not consider the agent to be more expert or particularly better placed to make decisions than ourselves, but we realize that there needs to be a decision maker. Coordination and collective action problems arise because groups of people need information on what others are doing and might have different ideas about what should happen, even given common aims. Or they might have some conflicting aims that make collective action problematic. Giving authority to an agent to direct the group facilitates coordination and collective action. Thomas Hobbes justified an authoritarian state on the grounds that in anarchy, where there is no authority, each will fight all others. People, he suggests, are roughly equal, and each must fear the others. Each person could be killed by another, and nobody can expect others to abide by agreements made because they have incentives to cheat if they can. “Covenants, without the Sword,” he writes, “are but words, and are of no strength to secure a man at all.” In other words, without some authority to back up a contract, people might cheat. I pay you today to provide goods tomorrow, but tomorrow you can keep my money and your goods. All I can do is take to the sword to try to force you to keep your agreement. Knowing I might do this, you have an incentive to try to kill me before I take to the sword. But I can work out that you might do that, so I will not want to contract with you in the first place. And so on. Hence, Hobbes characterized life with no authority as “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” If all authority is given to the state, the state can ensure that each person will abide by the contracts they make. If any person should unjustly renege on a deal made, the injured party can appeal to the state, and the state with a monopoly of force can ensure compensation. Autonomy Knowing that the state has this power, each will abide by the contracts made. Of course, if we give all power to the state, then we cannot be assured that the state will not exploit us. We can see how a community might all agree that some central organs are required to keep all particular contracts as made. However, does the need for a central authority mean that we need one with absolute power? If Leviathan—Hobbes’s name for the central authority—is given absolute power, then why would it retain its role as arbiter of disputes? It might use that absolute power to exploit the citizens. In other words, the final authority of the state does not imply absolute power for the state. Two elements are normally thought to emerge from the lack of Hobbesian justification for absolute authority of the state. The first is the need for checks and balances. Rather than allow one agent to have absolute power, several agents are given powers in separate domains, allowing each agent to be able to check the power of the others. The powers are constrained by constitutional requirements that give each legitimate authority within its domain. Each is given certain powers by law and the powers they are given are justified by the need for solutions to collective action problems. The second is that before we can justify sets of state powers, we need reasons for accepting authority within those domains. Thus, we do not simply allow the state to impose laws for our safety or to protect our property but require justifications for specific laws. Similarly, when we give distributional powers to the state, we do not allow it to have complete authoritative allocation over property rights but, rather, demand justification for the specific rules that are adopted. Keith Dowding See also Consent; Hobbes, Thomas; Interests; Justice; Legitimation; Weber, Max Further Readings Green, L. (1984). The authority of the state. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Raz, J. (Ed.). (1973). Authority. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Weber, M. (1968). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. New York: Bedminster Press. 39 AUTONOMY The English word autonomy stems from two Greek words: autos, meaning “self,” and nomos, meaning “law,” or “rule.” To be autonomous, then, is to be self-ruled. This term was unproblematic in its early usage, when it was applied to self-governing, autonomous city-states. In contemporary philosophy, however, the term autonomy is usually applied to persons, with a person being held to be autonomous if the person rules himself or herself. This use of the term is an important one, for the concept of autonomy so understood is central to many debates within both applied and theoretical ethics and political philosophy. However, this extension of the term to persons has led to some confusion concerning how the term is to be used, which arises because the term autonomy plays a major role in two different philosophical traditions: the Kantian tradition and the personal autonomy tradition. There are also several different accounts of what it is for a person to be autonomous within the personal autonomy tradition alone: the hierarchical account of autonomy, the attitudinal-historicist account of autonomy, the coherentist account of autonomy, and substantive accounts of autonomy. The Importance of Autonomy Since the 1970s, the concept of autonomy has risen to prominence within both contemporary moral philosophy (especially applied ethics) and contemporary political philosophy. The question of whether a person is autonomous with respect to his or her actions has, for example, been taken to be closely related to the question of whether the person is morally responsible for those actions. Similarly, the question of whether a person is autonomous, or, alternatively, has the capacity for autonomy, has been taken to be closely related to the question of whether the person should be afforded participation within a liberal democracy, as well as the question of whether he or she is a full member of the moral community. Autonomy is also held to be of great value in many debates within applied ethics. In bioethics, for example, the value of autonomy is held to ground the importance of securing informed consent from 40 Autonomy patients. It is also often used to justify acceding to a patient’s request to be euthanized, or to be allowed to sell his or her body parts for transplantation to others. Similarly, in business ethics, the value of autonomy is used to ground discussions concerning the morality of attempting to persuade persons to buy products by advertising them, as well as the morality of employing people in sweatshops. The value of autonomy is also central to many other debates within ethics and political philosophy, ranging from those that concern the ethics of allowing plea bargaining within a criminal justice system, to the status of freedom of speech. Kantian Autonomy The first philosophical tradition in which autonomy plays a major role stems from the ethical work of Immanuel Kant. Kant believed a person is autonomous if he or she is selfdirected, where this self consists of those aspects of the person that are essential to him or her. Thus, people will not be acting autonomously if they are moved to act by their desires, for a person’s desires are only contingent aspects of his or her self, rather than necessary parts of it. A person might, for example, have had desires other than he or she did, and yet would still be the same person. Thus, a person will act autonomously, his or her actions will be directed by the person’s essential self, only when he or she acts rationally. Kant has already denied that people will act autonomously if they act to satisfy their own desires, so a person will not be acting autonomously if he or she acts in accord only with instrumental rationality. Rather, Kant believed people will act autonomously only when they act on those maxims of action that they can consistently will to be universal law, and so act because they recognize that the maxims on which they are acting could be so willed. Thus, for example, people would act autonomously when they told the truth if they did so because they believed that the maxim of their actions “tell the truth” could be consistently willed to be a universal law (i.e., one that everyone could follow without contradiction). A person who acts on maxims that could not be consistently willed to be universal law would fail to act autonomously and would fail to act morally, also. This is because, Kant believed, actions whose covering maxims could not be consistently willed to be universal law are immoral actions. Consider, for example, the maxim “lie when it is to your advantage.” This maxim could not be consistently willed to be a universal law. Were everyone to lie when it was to their advantage (i.e., were the maxim to be a universal law), no one would trust the word of another person because it would be known that everyone lies when it is to his or her advantage. As such, then, lying would become inefficacious, for no one would believe any claim that could be a lie uttered to secure the advantage of the person uttering it. Thus, autonomous action and moral action are linked. Personal Autonomy: The Early Hierarchical Account Partly as a reaction to the Kantian emphasis on autonomous action as rational, moral, action, an alternative philosophical tradition arose in the 1970s that focused on a person’s desires when assessing whether he or she was autonomous with respect to the actions that the person performed when he or she was motivated to act by them. The two primary proponents of this alternative understanding of autonomy as personal, rather than moral, autonomy were Harry Frankfurt and Gerald Dworkin, who independently developed hierarchical analyses of personal autonomy. Frankfurt believes a person is autonomous with respect to an effective first-order desire (i.e., that desire that actually moves the person to act, or to refrain from acting) if the person both wants to have it and wants it to move him or her to act. If both of these conditions are met, then the person in question will “volitionally endorse” that firstorder desire that moves the person to act, and thus will be autonomous with respect to it. Dworkin believes a person will be autonomous with respect to his or her actions if the person is moved to perform them by desires that are authentically the person’s, and with respect to which he or she enjoys both procedural and substantive independence. A person’s desires are authentically the person’s if they are desires Autonomy by which the person endorses being moved—in this way, Dworkin’s account of autonomy is similar to Frankfurt’s. A person enjoys procedural independence with respect to his or her desires if the person has not come to have them as a result of deception, manipulation, brainwashing, or other procedures that would undermine the person’s self-direction were he or she to be moved to act by them. A person enjoys substantive independence with respect to his or her desires if the person has them as a result of failing to renounce his or her independence of thought and action with respect to them. Objections to the Early Hierarchical Account of Autonomy The initial hierarchical account of autonomy was subject to three serious objections. Focusing on Frankfurt’s account of what it is for a person to be autonomous with respect to the person’s effective first-order desires, the critics of this account charged that it was subject to the problem of manipulation. Thus, all that is required for a person to be autonomous with respect to a first-order desire of his or hers is that it meets certain structural conditions; that he or she wants to have it and to be moved by it. But, argue Frankfurt’s critics, a person who is clearly non-autonomous with respect to an effective first-order desire could readily satisfy these conditions. For example, people who have implanted into them an effective first-order desire, and, at the same time, have implanted into them a desire for that first-order desire and a desire that it move them to act (i.e., a volitional endorsement of the desire in question) would, on Frankfurt’s account, be autonomous with respect to the first-order desire that was implanted into them. But this is implausible. The second objection to which Frankfurt’s early hierarchical account was subject was the regress problem. The proponents of this problem begin by asking what makes people autonomous with respect to their secondorder volitional endorsements of their effective first-order desires? If the answer is that these desires are themselves endorsed by a yet higher ranked desire, then a regress ensues, for why are the people in question autonomous with respect 41 to that higher-order desire? If, however, the answer is that the people in question are autonomous with respect to these higher-order endorsing desires for some other reason, then Frankfurt’s account of autonomy is incomplete until an account of what this “other way” is, is provided. Finally, Frankfurt’s hierarchical account of autonomy is subject to the problem of authority. This problem is simple: why is it that a person’s higher-order desires have authority over his or her lower-order desires in the way that Frankfurt envisages? After all, they too are simply desires. To see the force of this objection, consider the case of a woman who has been brought up in a sexist society, and all her life she has been taught that a woman’s place is in the home. Despite her upbringing, this woman still occasionally desires to leave her domestic prison and pursue a career. Because of her socialization, however, whenever she experiences these desires, she quashes them as being unworthy of her femininity. In this case, it seems that this woman would be more autonomous were she to act on her first-order desires to pursue a career, even though she repudiates, rather than endorses, these desires at the higher conative level. Alternative Accounts of Autonomy Proceduralist Accounts These three criticisms are widely taken to be serious objections to Frankfurt’s original hierarchical account of personal autonomy. Given this, several alternative accounts of what conditions must be met for a person to be autonomous with respect to his or her effective first-order desires have been developed. On a historical approach to analyzing autonomy, what matters in assessing whether a person is autonomous with respect to his or her effective first-order desires is not the attitude that the person now takes toward them, but their history. On an attitudinal–historical approach (such as that developed by John Christman), people will be autonomous with respect to their effective first-order desires if they would, under conditions when they were able to reflect on their desires rationally and without external interference, not repudiate their development. Alternatively, on a coherentist model of autonomy (such as that developed by Laura Waddell 42 Autonomy Ekstrom), people will be autonomous with respect to their effective first-order desires if those desires cohere in appropriate ways with their preexisting desires. This last approach to analyzing autonomy has an advantage over those that are based on an agent’s attitudes toward his or her desires, for it avoids all three of the problems that Frankfurt’s early account faced. It avoids the problem of manipulation because the coherence conditions can be specified in such a way that no implanted desires could fulfill them. It avoids the regress problem because people’s autonomy with respect to their effective firstorder desires does not rest on the attitude that they take toward those desires. Finally, it avoids the problem of authority because a person’s preexisting coherent set of desires has authority for him or her relative to any particular desire that would be in question when asking whether he or she was autonomous with respect to it. Substantive Accounts So far, all of the accounts of personal autonomy that have been outlined have been procedural accounts. That is, they have been accounts of autonomy on which a person is held to be autonomous with respect to his or her effective first-order desires if they meet certain procedural conditions, such as being endorsed by him or her, having the process by which they came about endorsed by the person, or cohering in certain ways with the person’s preexisting desires. On such accounts of autonomy, persons could be held to be autonomous with respect to any desires, irrespective of their content, provided that they met the specified procedural conditions. Such a procedural approach to analyzing autonomy has, however, been challenged by autonomy theorists who believe that persons could never be autonomous with respect to certain desires or, conversely, that persons must possess certain desires or values if they are to be autonomous. Many feminist autonomy theorists, for example, hold that persons cannot be autonomous with respect to desires or values that would lead to their possessors’ debasement. Similarly, many also hold that persons can only be autonomous if they value themselves as autonomous agents—a self-evaluation that would of necessity preclude any self-debasing desires or values. These substantive, or valueladen, accounts of autonomy vary in the degree to which they specify the values that persons must accept to be autonomous, and, as such, their proponents are faced with a dilemma. The more values that they require autonomous persons to accept, the narrower the range of persons that proponents consider to be autonomous will be—and the narrower this range is, the more implausible their theory looks. This is because such robustly substantive theories of autonomy would start to exclude persons who would normally be thought to be self-directing, autonomous persons, even though they do not endorse the values that the proponents of the more substantive accounts of autonomy require them to. However, the fewer particular values that the proponents of these substantive theories of autonomy require persons to have, the more these appear to be modifications of procedural accounts, rather than alternatives to them. This is because the proponents of many procedural accounts implicitly require persons to adopt some values, such as the value of critical reflection, to meet the procedural conditions to be autonomous with respect to their effective firstorder desires. Conclusion Although the value of autonomy is held to be of great importance in many debates within contemporary moral and political philosophy, there is a great deal of disagreement about precisely what conditions must be met for a person to be considered autonomous. Although the disagreement between the proponents of Kantian accounts of autonomy and the proponents of various accounts of personal autonomy concerning what the proper scope of this term is, given the significant dissimilarities between these two conceptions of this concept, easy to identify, the disagreements between the proponents of the various accounts of personal autonomy is often less obvious, for they are working within the same tradition as each other. As such, discussions that draw on this concept should begin by clarifying exactly what is meant by it, and then, if there is disagreement about this, it will be more focused and productive than were it to occur Autonomy of the State without an explicit recognition that disagreement is at hand. James Stacey Taylor Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, J. S. (2005). Personal autonomy: New essays. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. See also Agency; Determinism; Free Will Further Readings AUTONOMY Christman, J. (1989). The inner citadel: Essays on individual autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press. See Relative Autonomy of the State OF THE STATE 43 B BACHRACH, PETER, MORTON AND empirically. How can one study something that has not happened? But non decision making was not about processes that had not yet occurred. Rather, Bachrach and Baratz showed that examining the media to discover important issues was a flawed technique, potentially overlooking issues that elites either were not interested in or were attempting to ignore or remove from the agenda. In that sense, the idea is about agenda setting and how to surface important issues that elites and the mass media are not discussing. Bachrach and Baratz’s work was later criticized from the Left for ignoring the processes of interest formation. Writers such as Steven Lukes argued that non decision making was only concerned with actual struggle, albeit a struggle that is submerged. However, important power issues are involved in preference formation and the dominated agents may not realize that what they take to be in their own best interests are, in reality, the interests of the dominant. Bachrach and Baratz argued that, although preference formation was important, emphasis should still be placed on examining empirically the struggles in which agents wanted to engage. Their later work was less influential, and ironically, Bachrach’s later book Power and Empowerment (coauthored with Aryeh Botwinick) argued for participatory democracy through the workplace, in an account of democracy bearing striking similarities to that of Dahl from the latter’s doctoral thesis through to his later writings. BARATZ, Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz are neo-Marxists who made important contributions to the community power debate in the 1960s and 1970s. In a series of articles culminating in a short book, Power and Poverty: Theory and Practice, they introduced the concept of non decision making. Criticizing the pluralist accounts of power in communities, notably Robert Dahl’s in his Who Governs?, Bachrach and Baratz argued that pluralists only looked at the surface of conflict. Bachrach and Baratz suggest that there is a second face (or dimension) of power that concerns the way in which some issues are organized into politics and other issues are organized out. Thus, they argued, some issues do not come to the surface in democratic politics because elites ensure that these issues stay buried. One example of such a buried issue is race and poverty (in the late 1950s). In Who Governs?, a study of power in New Haven, Connecticut, Dahl and his researchers identified important political issues by examining what was being discussed in the local newspapers. They then explored who was influential in policy making for those issues. Neither race relations nor poverty were discussed in the local media and so were not studied by the New Haven pluralists. However, as Who Governs? was published, race riots tore across U.S. cities, including New Haven. Race was an important issue, but one that was simply not discussed by the media until the riots. Some writers, such as Raymond Wolfinger, have argued that non decision making cannot be studied Keith Dowding See also Community Power Debate; Dahl, Robert A.; Lukes, Steven; Pluralism; Second Face 45 46 Bakunin, Mikhail Further Readings Bachrach, P., & Baratz, M. S. (1970). Power and poverty: Theory and practice. New York: Oxford University Press. Dowding, K. (1991). Rational choice and political power. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar. BAKUNIN, MIKHAIL (1814–1876) Mikhail Bakunin understands power as an exercise of the will. His analysis is largely critical, and he conceptualizes power in relation to authority. In this context, power might be thought of as the will of those claiming a right of command or those who by virtue of their resources (wealth, talents, breeding, etc.) are in a position to dominate others. Where power is institutionalized, as it is in the state, it gives rise to certain habits, breeding paternalism and hubris in the elite and servility and diffidence in the masses. The idea—power corrupts the best—is similar to Lord Acton’s. In 1867 Bakunin argued, Nothing is more dangerous for man’s private morality than the habit of command. The best man, the most intelligent, disinterested, generous, pure, will infallibly and always be spoiled at this trade. Two sentiments inherent in power never fail to produce this demoralisation; they are: contempt for the masses and the overestimation of one’s own merits. (Power Corrupts The Best, retrieved from http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/ anarchist_archives/bakunin/bakuninpower.html) Bakunin neither celebrates this tendency nor regards it an inevitable feature of government. On the contrary, returning to the idea of will, he argues that elite power is open to challenge and that it is possible to neutralize its effects by abolishing the existing institutional frameworks. For as long as the downtrodden do not seek to use statist frameworks to overcome oppression, power can be exercised without the attendant corruption. This argument forms the crux of Bakunin’s disagreement with Karl Marx, which came to a head in 1871 after protracted arguments in the First International. Although he shares Marx’s view that the function of the state is to safeguard the interests of the economically dominant class, Bakunin also argues that it is too reductive and fails to consider the structures through which elites—economic, cultural, religious—exert their power. Marx’s solution, to capture political power in the state and use it to further the interests of the working class, would only result in the domination of a new proletarian elite, leaving other forms of oppression unchecked and the principle of command intact. Bakunin’s solution, to encourage workers and peasants to take direct control of the means of production, is designed to make state structures redundant and offer a new way of organizing in which elitism would be overcome. Bakunin sees no contradiction between his critique of elitism and his advocacy of conspiratorial organization. Though critics often accuse him of vanguardism, his position is that dedicated revolutionaries provide an important catalyst for social revolution, encouraging the oppressed to combat through rebellion the servility that centuries of elitism have engendered. In this, he was closer to François-Noël Babeuf than to Sergey Gennadiyevich Nechaev and Pyotr Nikitich Tkachev. Ruth Kinna See also Anarchism, Power in; Elite Theories; Revolutionary Cell Structure Further Readings Bakunin, M. A. (1867). Power corrupts the best. Retrieved September 26, 2007, from http://dwardmac .pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/bakunin/bakuninpower .html Bakunin, M. A. (1984). Marxism, freedom and the state (K. J. Kenafick, Ed.). Retrieved from http://www .marxists.org/reference/archive/bakunin/works/ mf-state/index.htm Lehning, A. (1974). Bakunin’s conceptions of revolutionary organisations and their role: A study of his “Secret Societies.” In C. Abramsky (Ed.), Essays in honour of E. H. Carr (pp. 57–8). London: Macmillan. BALANCE OF POWER The balance of power is a central concept in international relations that first came into widespread Balance of Power use in the 16th and 17th centuries. Though many different meanings have been associated with this concept, it refers generally to the principle that powerful states in an anarchic international environment will respond to one state’s increase in power by striving to increase their own levels of power. The result of this self-interested action by states is thought to be a general power equilibrium among the most powerful states in the system. Because of the interaction of states’ self-interested strategies, no one state is able to dominate the international system. This concept is thus held to explain why there has never been—nor is there likely to be—an overarching world government. Scholars of international relations have often remarked disparagingly on the ambiguity surrounding the meaning of the term balance of power. Richard Cobden once declared scathingly, “The theory of a balance of power is a mere chimera—a creation of the politician’s brain—a phantasm, without definite form or tangible existence.” In a noteworthy critique, Inis Claude identifies the contradictory manners in which scholars have referred to the concept: descriptively as a situation that inheres among states, prescriptively as a policy that statesmen should follow, and analytically as a system that regulates conduct among states and limits the range of possible international political outcomes. Within each category, there remains considerable variation in the way that the term is used. When referring to the balance of power as a situation, for instance, scholars sometimes use it to describe a situation of equilibrium, sometimes to describe its opposite, a situation of imbalance, and sometimes as a synonym for any distribution of power. Similarly, discussions of the balance of power as a policy sometimes refer to a policy of maintaining an equilibrium with other states and other times to a policy of maintaining a favorable balance of power—that is, a preponderance of power. Because of this confusion about the concept’s meaning, and because of many scholars’ tendency to slip between conflicting meanings of the concept with relatively little awareness, readers must take care to ascertain which meaning of the concept an author is employing at a particular time. Despite these sources of disagreement, scholars of the balance of power share many assumptions. These assumptions are also held in general by realist scholars of international relations, making the 47 balance of power a central realist concept. The state is viewed as the central unit of international politics in a system that is described as anarchical, a term that refers simply to the absence in the international context of an overarching world sovereign—anarchy in this context neither means nor implies chaos. Yet, because there is no international equivalent to Thomas Hobbes’s domestic Leviathan, states— which are assumed to desire, at a very minimum, survival—must jealously guard their own security. They must be ever circumspect, as the inherent uncertainty of the international system means that even states that seem benign today might become threatening tomorrow. In such a situation, states that see an emerging power on the horizon should attempt to counteract this new power. They have two primary means at their disposal as they attempt to balance against a rising potential threat: (1) they may increase their own military strength through such efforts as armament or (2) they may form alliances with other states against the potential threat. The first is known as internal balancing and the second as external balancing. Assessing the Balance of Power as System Of the various ways of viewing the balance of power discussed, the view of the balance of power as system is the one most relevant to analytical theories of international relations. The claim is that the balance of power imposes a degree of order on the international system that has some positive consequences. Two questions in particular are the subjects of debate in this realm: (1) the automatic or manual nature of the balance of power and (2) the specific outcomes the balance of power is expected to produce. Is the Balance of Power a Law? One claim made by some scholars of the balance of power draws on an analogy to laissez-faire economics and the “invisible hand” thought to bring about a positive collective outcome, the efficient operation of the market, from the self-interested action of individuals. Just as individual producers and consumers do not intend to produce the market but merely intend to achieve individual profit, individual states do not intend to produce equilibrium. Rather, each individual state aims to achieve 48 Balance of Power the preponderant power that will ensure its own security. Yet, as each state attempts to achieve this goal, the collective outcome is a rough balance of power, at least among the major states, because no state is able to achieve preponderance when other states simultaneously seek the same goal. Thus, the general security of the system, and the survival of the major state units, is ensured. To some scholars, then, the balance of power expresses a general law of how the international system operates regardless of the intentions of the individual states. No balance of power policy, in this view, is necessary to produce the outcome of equilibrium. In contrast, however, some scholars view the balance of power as semi-automatic or manual rather than fully automatic. In the semi-automatic view, a specific country able and willing to play the role of “holder of the balance” is needed for the balance of power system to operate. This country has sufficient strength that, by switching allegiance from one set of countries to another, it can alter the balance of power within a particular area. This state is usually in a unique position relative to the other states, possessing some distance from the other states but nevertheless being close enough to affect and be affected by these states. This state, unlike the others, also makes a conscious decision to undertake the role of balancer. The paradigmatic example of such a state is 19th-century Britain, the geographic position and military power of which made it an able holder of the balance. Finally, some scholars view the balance of power as being fully manual, able to function only by the careful and deliberate manipulation of skillful statespeople. In these latter two views, in contrast to the view of the balance of power as automatic, the balance of power can sometimes fail to operate effectively. The failure of states to balance appropriately can perhaps be partially explained by the concept of a collective action problem. Although it may be in the interest of a group of states to balance against the power of a rising threat, each individual state might prefer that the other states undertake the burden of doing so. Such behavior is known as buck passing, and the result might be that no state mobilizes against the rising power until it is too late. Such an explanation might explain why a coalition formed against Adolf Hitler only at such a late date. Similarly, states may possess options other than balancing in their attempt to maintain security. These options, which may be particularly tempting for weak states, include allying with the rising threat, or simply hiding. Awareness of the potential of the collective action problem to thwart effective balancing behavior led to Kenneth Waltz’s claim in his seminal Theory of International Politics that a bipolar distribution of power is more stable than is a multipolar distribution of power. When only two superpowers exist, according to Waltz, there is less uncertainty than in a multipolar world—each state knows who the potential enemy is and is able to respond via internal balancing rather than rely on external balancing, which is easily prone to miscalculation and war. Waltz thus provides a parsimonious account of one variable likely to affect how automatically—and effectively—the balance of power operates. What Are the Consequences of the Balance of Power System? A second important debate concerns precisely what desirable consequences the balance of power is expected to produce. Some theories view the balance of power system as one that helps bring about peace, but others dispute that this is a primary outcome of the balance of power. The balance of power is thought to contribute to relative—if not absolute—peace among major powers by ensuring that no state possesses sufficient power to conquer all other states. Thus, it is thought, the balance of power constitutes a disincentive to extreme aggression. However, as Claude perceptively notes, equilibrium is unlikely to be as much of a deterrent to aggressive behavior as would be a preponderance of power vested in a countervailing coalition. Abramo Fimo Kenneth Organski and the power transition school similarly cast doubt on the supposed relationship between balance and peace. They argue that, far from causing peace, relative stability or balance between two powers is a quite unstable and bellicose situation. A significant disparity of power between two states, they argue, is likely to result in peace because there is no doubt which state would prevail in a war. The weaker state is thus cognizant of its limitations and defers appropriately to the stronger power. War is most likely once the weaker state begins to approach Balance of Power parity with the stronger state because both the weaker and stronger parties then possess incentives to fight, the weaker to improve its power position and the stronger to prevent the emergence of the weaker as an equal contender. Balance of power partisans respond to these critiques in a number of ways. First, they assert that, though preponderance in a specific context might indeed be the best deterrent to aggression, this is not a generalizable rule for system-level international politics because one cannot determine a priori which states should possess a preponderance of power in the service of peace. The balance of power system is thus more appropriate in this regard. Furthermore, balance of power scholars take issue with Organski’s claim that disparity contributes to peace because disparity and the unequal treatment that occurs under it creates the motivation for war in Organski’s theory, even if war can only occur once relative parity is reached. Furthermore, such a war is more likely to be a major, systemic catastrophe, what Robert Gilpin calls a “hegemonic war,” than is a war that occurs between two relatively balanced states to rectify a slight imbalance perceived to exist between the two. Finally, balance of power theorists may assert that although the system does not succeed in completely eradicating war, it does achieve other arguably desirable outcomes. Indeed, some scholars have suggested that the balance of power system maintains the status quo. Yet, one notable feature of the balance of power system has been the occasional sacrifice of smaller powers in order to create a more desirable distribution of power among the major powers. Historically, the partitions of Poland provide an illuminating example of such a dynamic. Thus, it seems that the balance of power does not maintain the status quo in its entirety, though it may succeed most of the time in preserving the independence of the major units of the international system. At a very minimum, though, the balance of power system is thought to prevent any one state from achieving world domination, even if war may occasionally be a necessary means of achieving this end. How one assesses the outcomes produced by the balance of power system may depend partly on what one conceives of as the alternative systems of power management. One major ideological competitor to the balance of power system has been the 49 system of collective security. Collective security systems seek to provide a radical alternative to the self-help system that undergirds the balance of power. States that are members of the collective security community declare that a threat to any member state constitutes a threat to the whole. In theory, such a threat, once it emerges, is met with the united force of the community. Collective security thus aims to achieve a universal and automatic response to international aggression, something akin to the role of law enforcement in the domestic context. However, scholars have noted that many problems plague collective security even in theory, and it has yet to prove itself successful in practice. The failure of the League of Nations as a collective security organization is viewed as evidence of fatal flaws in collective security as a tool of power management, most notably because collective security theorists fail to detail how the collective action problem discussed earlier might be overcome. Thus, though the balance of power may not be ideal as a system of power management, it is often viewed as operating via a more consistent logic than is the collective security alternative. The Balance of Power and the Empirical Record The historical record of state behavior is relevant to assessing balance of power theory. Realist scholars often cite the “long century” from the end of the Napoleonic Wars to the outbreak of World War I as evidence of the relative peace and order that the balance of power provides, as well as of the general propensity of states to balance. However, the idea that balancing accurately describes state behavior in general has been challenged by recent scholarship. Historian Paul Schroeder has argued that states have historically engaged in a wide range of behaviors in response to threats, behaviors not at all limited to balancing. Likewise, some scholars have argued that the balance of power is a rather Eurocentric concept, and that the history of the world outside Europe provides numerous examples of hierarchical systems in which states did not effectively balance against overweening power. China during the Warring States period is a notable example of such a system. Post–cold war developments in international politics have also caused some to question basic 50 Balance of Power balance of power arguments. Immediately after the collapse of the Soviet Union, realist scholars such as Waltz and John Mearsheimer predicted that a rival to U.S. power would soon emerge because it was contra balance of power theory for such a superpower to remain long unchecked. However, a decade and a half later, a clear rival to the United States still had not emerged. Two amendments of balance of power theory have been used to explain this apparent anomaly. First, Stephen Walt argued that states do not simply balance against material power, but against threat. Thus, states should not balance against a powerful state viewed as having benign intentions. The explanation for the failure of other states to balance against the United States, then, lies in the U.S. ability to convince others that the United States does not pose an actual threat to other states’ security. U.S. democracy or its involvement in the post–World War II liberal international order might explain why the United States is able to convince others of its benign intentions. One should note that balance of threat theory represents a significant departure from the traditional realist skepticism of reliance on estimates of other states’ intentions to ensure one’s own security. Precisely because state intentions can so easily change, a conservative statesperson should balance against power, rather than against estimations of threat. Likewise, evaluating other states’ intentions is an extremely difficult task and one that, as standard histories of both world wars reveal, statespeople often do not do well. The second attempt to explain the purported failure of other states to balance argues that what constitutes balancing has changed in recent decades. States may not be engaging in traditional forms of balancing behavior, but they are, some argue, engaging in “soft balancing.” This refers to political, rather than military, efforts to restrain the actions of states possessing disproportionate power; the refusal of many European states to support the U.S. decision to invade Iraq in 2003, for example, might be viewed as “soft balancing.” Finally, some argue that changes occurred in the 20th century made it more difficult for the balance of power system to operate. Democracy has proliferated in many regions of the world, arguably making it difficult for states to make the rapid adjustments in foreign policy loyalties that the balance of power requires. Likewise, technological changes in warfare, particularly nuclear developments, may have changed the meaning of the distribution of power, making it more difficult to estimate, and may have likewise increased the costs of using war as a means of correcting power asymmetries. Alternative Views of the Balance of Power Though the balance of power is a traditionally realist concept, liberal and constructivist interpretations of the balance of power do exist. Hedley Bull and other scholars of the English School of international relations emphasize the way in which the balance of power, rooted in understandings about the possibility for mutual advantage among states, provides order and predictability to the international system. Others have called this the “associational” view of the balance of power, in contrast to the “adversarial” view that is traditionally realist. Departing even further from the realist position, constructivists highlight the contextual and social aspects of the ideas of balance and power. Richard Little, for instance, has argued that the prevalence of the metaphor of the balance of power in discussions of international politics contributed to a shift in mainstream views of power from hierarchical and agent-based to structural and relational. This constructivist critique relates to a broader critique of the balance of power—the difficulty of defining, and thus measuring, power. The typical realist response to such a critique is that although assessing the distribution of power, a necessary enterprise if the balance of power is to function, is by nature an art and not a science, statespeople are accustomed to making such estimations and are usually in broad agreement about which states constitute the most powerful states in the system at any given point in time. Brooke C. Greene See also Collective Action Problem; Power Transition Theory; Realism in International Relations Further Readings Claude, I. (1967). Power and international relations. New York: Random House. Jervis, R. (1997). System effects: Complexity in political and social life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Banks Little, R. (2007). The balance of power in international relations: Metaphors, myths, and models. New York: Cambridge University Press. Morgenthau, H. (1949). Politics among nations: The struggle for power and peace. New York: Knopf. Walt, S. (1987). The origins of alliances. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Waltz, K. (1979). Theory of international politics. New York: Random House. BANKS Banks, in their most basic function, act as financial intermediary institutions in an economy. They tend to act as conduits for capital and credit allocation between individuals, corporations, and the state. Banks also function as institutions of financial deepening—that is, they contribute to the monetization of the economy. Generically, banks are incorporated into the financial services industry. Despite the importance of banks in modern economic systems, the relationship between power and banks themselves has not been fully evaluated. A useful departing point from which to analyze the power of banks may be traced to Vladimir Lenin’s Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916). In this influential work, Lenin defined imperialism as “the monopoly stage of capitalism.” Lenin added that such a definition would include what is most important, for, on the one hand, finance capital is the bank capital of a few very big monopolist banks, merged with the capital of the monopolist associations of industrialists; and, on the other hand, the division of the world is the transition from a colonial policy which has extended without hindrance to territories unseized by any capitalist power, to a colonial policy of monopolist possession of the territory of the world, which has been completely divided up. In the Leninist critique of the power of banks, three of the critical ingredients of the last stage of capitalism (i.e., imperialism) include the merging of bank capital with industrial capital and the creation of finance capital, the increasing importance of the export of capital, and the fusion of the capitalist state with banks and industry. 51 Other recent analytical work has also tended to view the role of banks from a negative perspective, largely from the premise that they accelerate the growth of noxious corporate power. In this critical framework, the perception that banks hold growing power is based on the view that the income of many international banks is growing both absolutely and as a proportion of the world’s total gross domestic product (GDP). Viewed in absolute terms, as output from services becomes more central in emerging and transition economies, the potential economic power of banks is staggering. For instance, according to The Banker magazine’s annual index of the world’s largest banks, the top 10 banks—in total assets—include those shown in Table 1. By virtue of holding assets on behalf of individuals and corporations, the analysis of the power that banks may exert begins with an assessment of their aggregate assets, whereby it is imputed that banks with large asset holdings are likely to exert more power than do those with lesser asset holdings. However, empirical analyses of the relationship between a bank’s size and political power suggest that there is no apparent correlation between bank concentration and political power. The potential economic power exerted by banks Table 1 World’s top 10 banks by total assets, 2006 ($ million) Bank Total assets, 2006 ($ million) Barclays Bank 1,591,524 UBS 1,567,564 Mitsubishi UFJ Financial Group 1,508,541 HSBC Holdings 1,501,970 Citigroup 1,493,987 BNP Paribas 1,484,109 Crédit Agricole Groupe 1,380,617 Royal Bank of Scotland 1,337,512 Bank of America Corporation 1,291,795 Mizuho Financial Group 1,226,627 Source: The Banker (July 2006). 52 Banks could be considerable, if one equates revenues with GDP. For instance, in 2006, world GDP was $60.7 trillion, of which assets of the 10 largest banks, listed in Table 1, equaled about 14.3 trillion, about 23.5% of world GDP. Although the aggregate economic strength of the world’s largest banks is considerable, it would be simplistic to argue that aggregate assets themselves equal political power. First, total assets (or any other aggregate measure, such as sales or revenues) would not be comparable to GDP because it excludes liabilities. If one uses other widely used industry measures of bank strength, such as market capitalization or Tier 1 capital, the potential economic power is far more modest. Also, although some banks enhance their market share through merger, it would be erroneous to assume that banks act in unison for a defined political goal. Although many banks may prefer to operate in a deregulated environment, at times they prefer regulatory barriers to entry for their competitors. This suggests that the relationship between banks and political power is complex. In this sense, one also ought to consider that most banks worldwide are regulated, sometimes excessively so. Even in comparatively deregulated business environments, such as most advanced capitalist economies, banks are subject to regulatory controls by a central bank and by other related government regulators (such as the Securities and Exchange Commission in the United States, the Financial Services Authority in the United Kingdom, the China Banking Regulatory Commission in the People’s Republic of China, etc.). A contemporary analysis of the power exercised by banks would have to differentiate between the actual functions that banks perform in an economy and the likely magnitude of their effects. Perhaps a useful way to differentiate these functions and effects is by looking at banks through a threedimensional typology. Banks can be classified according to the following: 1. Business type classification 2. Ownership structure Most banks perform specific functions. Typically, as a result of performing these functions, banks are classified as being retail or commercial banks (i.e., institutions that hold consumer deposits and transact with these deposits in the form of loans) or investment banks (institutions that help corporations raise capital, in the form of both debt and equity). The first type of bank may exercise power over individual depositors and small businesses, whereas the latter may have larger macroeconomic effects on financial markets. In addition, many transition economies also have development banks, which act as instruments of the state for various developmental and planning purposes. In this latter form, a potential linkage between banks and politically well-connected enterprises, whereby capital is diverted to favored enterprises by the state, could be assessed. Over the centuries, the complexity of bank structures has grown. To determine the capacity of banks to exercise power, it is worthwhile to determine their ownership structure—specifically, whether a bank is wholly or majority owned by the private sector or by government entities. The power potentially exercised by banks will vary considerably based on ownership structure. Private sector banks are accountable solely to their shareholders, whereas state-owned banks are accountable to the state. In this sense, the power exercised by private sector banks will be to the benefit of their shareholders, whereas state-owned banks are instruments of state power. Finally, it is important to determine a bank’s degree of transnationality. Banks may conduct their operations exclusively within their country’s territorial boundaries. Alternatively, banks may have a transnational or international character, often determined by the proportion of banking assets held abroad as a proportion of the bank’s total assets or by the proportion of the banking staff working abroad as a percentage of the bank’s total employment. In this context, international banks may have a widespread presence worldwide, but their presence in any given individual country may be small compared with domestic competitors. 3. Degree of transnationality Lawrence Sáez The power potentially exercised by banks can be determined by their business type classification. See also Business and Power; Globalization; Neoliberalism Banzhaf Value Further Readings Anderson, S., & Cavanagh, J. (2000). Top 200: The rise of corporate global power. Washington, DC: Institute for Policy Studies. Retrieved November 6, 2006, from http://www.ips-dc.org/downloads/Top_200.pdf Glassman, C. (1981). The impact of banks’ statewide economic power on their political power: An empirical analysis. Atlantic Economic Journal, 9(2 July), 53–56. BANZHAF See Banzhaf Voting Power Measure BANZHAF VALUE The Banzhaf value is one of the most widely known solution concepts of cooperative game theory. It presents a reasonable expectation of the share-out of the global winnings among players and a fair division in normative contexts. It was initially introduced by Lionel Sharples Penrose in 1946 as a power index for voting games and later rediscovered by John Banzhaf in 1965 and James S. Coleman in 1971. Since then, the Banzhaf value has been extended to arbitrary (nonsimple) cooperative games (thus being converted from a power index to game value) by Guillermo Owen, Pradeep Dubey, Lloyd Stowell Shapley, and others. A definition of this value, in absolute and normalized versions, is given here, followed by an illustrative example. Let N5f1; 2; . . . ; ng be a set of players. A cooperative game v on N is expressed in characteristic function form if a function v (the characteristic function) is given that assigns a value v(S) to every coalition S N such that vðØÞ50 . For each coalition S of N and for each player i belonging to S the “marginal contribution” of such a player to S is the difference between the winning of S and the winning of S without player i—that is, v(S) v(S{i}). 0 The absolute Banzhaf value ðb ðvÞÞ assigns to each player i the average of the marginal contributions to all coalitions to which the player belongs: 1 0 bi ðvÞ5 2 n21 + ðvðSÞ 2 vðS/figÞÞ: SN ði2SÞ 53 In this definition, all coalitions are considered equally probable and each player is equally likely to enter any coalition. The absolute Banzhaf value does not satisfy the efficiency property—that is, the sum of the values assigned to all players 0 + bi ðvÞ is not generally equal to the total worth of i2N the grand coalition vðNÞ . The normalized Banzhaf value ðbðvÞÞ assigns to each player i a quota of the total win v(N) proportional to the sum of all h players’ marginal contributions to all coalitions: bi ðvÞ5K + ½vðSÞ 2 vðS/ figÞ; SN where K is the quotient between v(N) and the total of marginal contributions of all players; h is the index of players; the first summation in the denominator is over all players h in N K5 vðNÞ : + + ½vðSÞ 2 vðS/ f hgÞ h2N SN The restriction of the (absolute or normalized) Banzhaf value to simple games is known as the (absolute or normalized) Penrose, Banzhaf, or Penrose–Banzhaf–Coleman measure of voting power. An Example Consider the three-person game v({1}) v({2}) v({3}) 0, v({1, 2}) v({2, 3}) 1, v({1, 3}) 2, v({1, 2, 3}) 3. Let us compute the absolute Banzhaf value of player 1. There are four coalitions containing player 1: {1}, {1, 2}, {1, 3} and {1, 2, 3}. The marginal contributions of player 1 to these coalitions are v({1}) – v(Ø) 0, v({1, 2}) – v(2) 1, v({1, 3}) – v({3}) 2, v({1, 2, 3}) – v({2,3}) 2. 0111212 5 5 . 4 4 Let us compute the absolute Banzhaf value of player 2. There are four coalitions containing player 2: {2}, {1, 2}, {2, 3} and {1, 2, 3}. The marginal contributions of player 2 to these coalitions are 0, 1, 1, 1. 0111111 3 Thus b02 ðvÞ5 5 . Then for player 3: 4 4 0 Thus b1 ðvÞ5 b03 ðvÞ5 0121112 5 5 . 4 4 54 Banzhaf Voting Power Measure To calculate the normalized Banzhaf values, we divide the absolute Banzhaf values by the coef3 3 5 . This gives b1 ðvÞ515/13, ficient K5 51315 13 b2 ðvÞ59/13, b3 ðvÞ515/13 . Note that the sum of these values gives exactly vðf1; 2; 3gÞ53 . Gianfranco Gambarelli See also Coleman Index; Shapley Value; Value of a Game Further Readings Banzhaf, J. F. (1965). Weighted voting doesn’t work: A mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review, 19, 317–343. Coleman, J. S. (1971). Control of collectivities and the power of collectivity act. In B. Lieberman (Ed.), Social choice (pp. 269–300). New York: Gordon and Breach. Reprinted in J. S. Coleman (1986). Individual interest and collective action. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Dubey, P., & Shapley, L. S. (1979). Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Mathematics of Operations Research, 4, 99–131. Penrose, L. S. (1946). The elementary statistics of majority voting. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 109, 53–57. Van den Brink, R., & van der Laan, G. (1998). Axiomatizations of the normalized Banzhaf value and the Shapley value. Social Choice and Welfare, 15, 567–582. BANZHAF VOTING POWER MEASURE 0 The Banzhaf voting power measure (b ) is one of the best known and most widely applied measures of a priori voting power. Although introduced in 1946 by Lionel Sharples Penrose, it was unknowingly and more famously reinvented by John Banzhaf in 1965. Moreover, James S. Coleman reinvented it once again in 1971. Thus, it is known variously as the Banzhaf, Penrose, Penrose–Banzhaf, or Banzhaf–Coleman–Penrose measure (or index). It is also known as the absolute Banzhaf measure to distinguish it from the normalized Banzhaf index (b) introduced by subsequent authors. The definitions of the absolute and normalized versions of the Banzhaf measure will be presented, links with the previously mentioned indices will be illustrated, and some axiomatizations and algorithms will be noted. An example will be presented in conclusion. The essential element in the construction of both the absolute and the normalized Banzhaf measures is the concept of “swing.” Let N5f1; 2; . . . ; ng be the set of members of a collectivity. A swing for member i of N is a pair of coalitions ðS; S/figÞ such that S is a winning coalition and S/fig is not winning. The number of swings for each member i is called his Banzhaf score and is denoted by ci. For each voter i, the absolute Ban0 zhaf measure (b ) is the quotient between his Banzhaf score and the number of pairs of complementary coalitions (or bipartitions), that is, ci 0 n21 2 . Thus bi 5 n21 . 2 In 1979, Pradeep Dubey and Lloyd Stowell Shapley developed an axiomatization of the Banzhaf index using four axioms. Guillermo Owen and others have proposed successive axiomatizations. As noted at the outset, the absolute Banzhaf 0 measure b is essentially identical to the measure r previously proposed by Penrose. (Specifically, 0 b 52r .) Furthermore, the measures of the power to prevent action g and the power to initiate action g subsequently introduced by J. S. Coleman are both 0 0 rescalings of b (and r). In particular, b and both Coleman measures are equal if every coalition or its complement is winning (i.e., there are no blocking coalitions), otherwise b is the harmonic mean of g and g . The normalized Banzhaf index b is the rescaling 0 of b such that the power of all voters sums to 1. That is, for each voter i, this index is the ratio between his Banzhaf score and the sum of Banzhaf scores across all voters. Dan S. Felsenthal and Moshé Machover have classified b0 and b , as well as g and g , in the group of the I-power indices (power as influence). A key problem with the Banzhaf index regards 0 monotonicity. Both b and b are locally monotonic— that is, if a member has greater weight than another, the member’s index is not less. But only b0 is globally monotonic, that is, if the weight of the i-th member increases and the weights of all other members decrease or remain unchanged, then b0 of Bargaining the member i does not decrease, but this is not generally true for b . Numerous algorithms have been introduced to calculate Banzhaf values given a large number of voters. In 1962, Irwin Mann and L. S. Shapley proposed a method of calculating the Shapley–Shubik index that uses generating functions. This method was extended to the Banzhaf index by Steven J. Brams and Paul J. Affuso in 1976 and was subsequently implemented by Jesús Mario Bilbao, and others. Another algorithm, developed by Gianfranco Gambarelli in 1996, can be applied to weighted majority games and supplies a method for the direct calculation of the measure’s variations in response to variations of weight distribution among the players. An Example Assume that a parliament is composed of three parties (labeled 1, 2, 3). Let (2, 1, 1) be their respective seats. Suppose that a rule can be approved only if the votes in favor are equal to or greater than 3 (i.e., a simple majority). In this case, the winning coalitions are {1, 2}, {1, 3} and {1, 2, 3}. Party 1 has a swing for each of these three coalitions, because each of them, without it, becomes a losing coalition; parties 2 and 3 have swings only for {1, 2} and {1, 3} respectively. Thus c1 53, c2 51, n21 c3 51 , S cj 55, and 2 54 . The voting powers j2N measured by the non normalized Banzhaf index are b01 53/4 , b02 5b03 51/4 , whereas the powers measured by the normalized Banzhaf index are b1 53/5 , b2 5b3 51/5 . Cesarino Bertini and Izabella Stach See also Coleman Index; I-Power; Penrose Voting Power Measure; Voting Power Further Readings Banzhaf, J. F. (1965). Weighted voting doesn’t work: A mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review, 19, 317–343. Banzhaf, J. F. (1966). Multi-member electoral districts: Do they violate the “one man, one vote” principle? Yale Law Journal, 75, 1309–1338. Banzhaf, J. F. (1968). One man, 3.312 votes: A mathematical analysis of the Electoral College. Villanova Law Review, 13, 304–332. 55 Dubey, P., & Shapley, L. S. (1979). Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Mathematics of Operation Research, 4, 99–131. Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power: Theory and practice, problems and paradoxes. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. BARGAINING Bargaining is a process by which a voluntary agreement on the division of a good or the terms of a trade or exchange is reached. The object of the exchange can be a physical object (e.g., a commodity), a right, or a change of behavior. Bargaining is a ubiquitous feature of social interactions. Bargaining takes place, for example, among businesspeople on the price of commodities, among political parties on the formation of a government, among legislators on the contents of a law, among nations on the resolution of a conflict, among trade unions and employer associations on working conditions, or between an individual employer and employee on working hours and salary. The term negotiating is often used synonymously. We can distinguish between bargaining situations along several dimensions. Bargaining can be formal or informal, bilateral or multilateral, repeated or limited to one instance. Furthermore, it can take place in a more or less institutionalized context. Bargaining in a legislature, for example, is governed by an elaborate set of rules concerning the process in which proposals are put forward, amendments (counterproposals) are made, and a decision is reached. This is not the case with bargaining at a bazaar where the interaction is structured only (if at all) by custom. In settings where decisions are made by a formal vote, agreement can be reached by a simple majority, qualified majority, or unanimity. Bargaining on treaties is usually based on the consent of all bargaining partners: thus, the decision rule is unanimity. This gives all parties involved veto power. Bargaining in legislatures, on the other hand, often uses majority rule, with qualified majorities (e.g., two-thirds majority) for particularly important bills (e.g., constitutional amendments). Consequently, some 56 Bargaining members of the legislative body can be overruled by the majority. Furthermore, some members might enjoy procedural privileges such as agendasetting power. Finally, we can distinguish among bargaining situations based on the nature of the issue(s) at hand. Bargaining can be limited to one issue or involve several. The good may or may not be divisible. In the legislative context, policies can allocate funding ([re-]distributive) or set rules (regulatory). The outcome of a bargaining process can be evaluated for its efficiency and the distribution of benefits. Efficiency refers to the minimization of the costs of the bargaining process (transaction and opportunity costs) and the realization of maximum surplus. The latter includes the avoidance of non-agreement when a trade would have been mutually beneficial (bargaining failure). Distribution refers to the division of the surplus gained from cooperation or coordination (in contrast to unilateral action). The distributive consequences of an agreement are influenced by the bargaining power of the actors involved. The Negotiator’s Dilemma Bargaining is typically characterized as a mixedmotive situation. Bargaining partners can create value by changing the current situation in a mutually beneficial way, but have divergent interests regarding the exact terms of the agreement. For example, a potential buyer of a commodity might value an object more than its owner does. In other words, the reserve price of the seller (the minimum price at which the seller is willing to sell an object) is lower than the reserve price of the buyer (the maximum price he or she is willing to pay). The difference between the two is the potential joint surplus from a trade. If this value is positive, both have an interest in reaching agreement to realize this joint surplus. However, the buyer would like to keep the price as low as possible, whereas the opposite is true for the seller. In other words, buyer and seller have a common interest in the production of a surplus but diametrically opposed interests with regard to its distribution. The tension between the desire to find an agreement to create value and to maximize the individual share of its distribution is referred to as the negotiator’s dilemma. Tactics aimed at furthering the latter goal (e.g., misrepresentation of preferences, threats, etc.) might jeopardize the former. This also implies that bargaining tends to be inefficient in the sense that valuable time and resources are spent on a “dance of concessions” (in Raiffa’s phrase) rather than reaching agreement instantaneously. Bargaining success is also threatened if the involved parties cannot credibly commit to keeping their side of the deal. Recourse to third parties (e.g., a judicial system) can ameliorate this problem. In some instances, third parties can also facilitate reaching an agreement by mediating between the bargaining partners. The Bargaining Space Bargaining can only be successful if a common interest exists. Figure 1 illustrates the basic bargaining setting for two actors, A and B, whose consent is necessary for joint or coordinated action. The horizontal axis denotes the utility B would derive from an agreement and the vertical axis denotes A’s utility. Thus, any given point shows the utility A and B would derive from a particular agreement. A prefers agreements toward the top of the graph whereas B would like to see an agreement as far as possible to the right. The crosshatched area represents all feasible agreements. Some agreements might be highly desirable but are simply out of the reach of the actors. For example, the quantity of a good a firm can possibly produce and thus sell to an interested party is limited because the resources used in the production of the good are finite. Similarly, the price a buyer can pay is limited by the buyer’s budget and credit line. Another example would be logistical difficulties that limit the speed with which armies can be withdrawn from a territory as part of a ceasefire agreement. Note that the utility an actor associates with any given agreement can depend on a number of factors. For example, a buyer’s utility from a purchase depends on the price, quantity, and quality of a good. Similarly, the evaluation by a government of a disarmament treaty could depend among other things on the number and type of arms being reduced, the time frame, and the verification procedure. A widely shared assumption is that bargaining is effectively limited to agreements that make both bargaining Bargaining A’s utility 57 B’s reserve level Zone of possible agreement Nash bargaining solution Pareto frontier A’s reserve level Non-agreement B’s utility Feasible agreements Figure 1 A bilateral bargaining situation and the Nash bargaining solution partners better off relative to the Best Alternative To Non-Agreement (BATNA). This could simply be the continuation of the present situation (status quo). The broken lines represent the utility each actor would receive in the absence of an agreement, for example, from acting unilaterally (reserve level). The zone of possible agreement (or bargaining space) is the subset of feasible agreements that gives all the actors whose consent is necessary a higher utility than they could achieve in the absence of an agreement. This is the crosshatched area in Figure 1. A subset of the zone of possible agreements is the so-called Pareto frontier. This is the set of agreements that is Pareto-optimal. An agreement is Pareto-optimal if any change would make at least one of the involved actors worse off. Movements toward the Pareto frontier create value for both parties (although possibly to different degrees), whereas a movement along the Pareto frontier would only redistribute value. Models of Bargaining and Bargaining Power Several game-theoretic models of bargaining have been proposed to capture the strategic aspect of negotiations. The Nash bargaining solution (NBS) is based on cooperative game theory. The NBS derives a unique solution for a bilateral bargaining situation based on a set of axioms. These axioms imply that the actors strive to reach the Pareto frontier and disregard irrelevant alternatives (e.g., additions to the feasible set that are Pareto-inferior). It is also assumed that the utilities completely reflect the evaluation of various options by the actors (e.g., attitude toward risk). The NBS is the maximum of the product of the gains in utility (relative to the 58 Bargaining security level) for both actors, possibly weighted by the actor’s bargaining power. If both actors have equal bargaining power, they effectively split the difference of the surplus. This equal division of created surplus is represented in Figure 2 with the dotted diagonal starting at the point of no agreement. The 45-degree angle indicates that each move toward the Pareto frontier gives an equal share of the surplus to both parties. The point where this line crosses the Pareto frontier is the NBS. If A has more bargaining power than B, then the line would slope upward, and vice versa. Note that an equal split of the surplus relative to the point of no agreement does not necessarily imply equal utility in absolute terms. John Harsanyi has shown that the NBS is equivalent to the outcome of a bargaining model suggested by F. Zeuthen. In this model, both players make proposals until one of them accepts the proposal of the other. If neither makes a concession (i.e., moves his or her proposal toward the last proposal of the other player), bargaining breaks down, and conflict ensues. According to the Zeuthen–Harsanyi model, the player whose cost of accepting the opponent’s suggestion is lower (rather than insisting on his or her own suggestion) relative to the cost of conflict, makes a concession. Harsanyi offers a psychological interpretation of this bargaining behavior. A seminal bargaining model based on noncooperative game theory is Ariel Rubinstein’s alternating offer model. The bargaining partners alternate in making offers to each other. Actors are assumed to be impatient; the value of later agreements is discounted relative to earlier ones. If impatience is sufficiently small, the solution of this game approaches the NBS. David Baron and John Ferejohn have proposed an influential model of multilateral bargaining in which the probability that an actor is recognized to make a proposal differs. Several determinants of the distribution of the surplus have been derived from these and related game-theoretical models. In general, the share of the surplus one actor receives increases as his or her eagerness for striking a deal decreases. Thus, an actor who is patient can stick to maximal demands whereas an impatient actor is more willing to make concessions to reach agreement early. Similarly, a bargaining partner is stronger if he or she enjoys a valuable inside option. Inside options refer to the benefits an actor receives during the bargaining while the current situation prevails. The distributive properties of bargaining outcomes are not just affected by the valuation the actors attach to various agreements but also to events outside of the negotiations. For example, the less an actor is concerned about exogenous factors that would end the negotiations (bargaining breakdown), the stronger the actor’s bargaining position is. Also, new outside options might become available. For example, while a buyer and a seller are bargaining, a new customer may make an offer. The position of the bargaining partner is strengthened if the value of the outside option (i.e., the new offer) is higher than the previous best alternative to non-agreement (i.e., no deal). This is illustrated in Figure 2 where the new outside option increases the value of non-agreement (NA) for B. Subsequently, the outcome as determined by the NBS would change. Relative to the original solution B benefits whereas A loses. Similarly, an actor could gain a bargaining advantage by decreasing the reserve level of the other actor (e.g., by foreclosing its outside option). Thomas Schelling has highlighted the use of commitment strategies to influence the distribution of the potential bargaining surplus (“paradox of weakness”). If an actor can eliminate some possible agreements that are unfavorable to him or her as principally “unacceptable” or unfeasible, the actor can restrict the bargaining space in favor of his or her position. In international negotiations, for example, a government might credibly commit itself to certain demands relative to its domestic constituency to tie its hands and gain an advantage at the international stage. This is related to the notion of two-level games in international relations. Typically, bargaining partners do not know each other’s reserve level. This gives an incentive to misrepresent it to gain a bargaining advantage. Player B in Figure 2 might, for example, just pretend that there was an alternative offer from a third party that led to a shift in his or her reserve level. As previously discussed, this would probably increase B’s share of the surplus. So far, we have assumed that no deals are possible unless they represent utility gains relative to the point of no agreement for both bargaining partners. Side payments and issue linkage are two mechanisms to allow bargaining partners to increase their welfare even Bargaining A’s utility 59 B’s new reserve level B’s original reserve level Original NBS New NBS Pareto frontier NA New NA A’s reserve level B’s utility Figure 2 The distributive consequences of outside options when this is not the case. Consider the scenario in Figure 3 where only two agreements (x, y) are feasible. UCA denotes the change in A’s utility if y is adopted, UCB is the equivalent utility change for B. In this scenario, A would not support y because it would make A worse off than would non-agreement. However, B’s utility gain from adopting y exceeds A’s loss (|UCB||UCA|). Thus, B could get A’s approval by compensating A sufficiently via a side payment. The dotted diagonal represents the welfare boundary. Agreements on this line give the same utility to both bargaining partners jointly as non-agreement. For any agreement to the top and right of the welfare boundary, the joint utility exceeds the joint utility of non-agreement and an agreement could be struck with the help of side payments. Similarly, A and B could agree on both x and y (issue-linkage), which would result in the outcome of z for their utility. The utility gain of B from y would offset B’s utility loss from x. In the same manner, the utility gain of A from x would offset A’s utility loss from y. Logrolling (or vote trading) has the same effect. It is based on the idea that two bargaining partners might value two issues differently and hence are willing to make concessions on one issue in return for the other party’s concession on the other issue. Bargaining involving several bargaining partners (multilateral negotiations) encompasses the same issues. In contrast to bilateral bargaining, though, the bargaining space tends to be smaller and the transaction costs of bargaining tend to be higher. Furthermore, the formation of a bargaining coalition is thought of as a crucial step in multilateral negotiations, but is not relevant in bilateral bargaining. The literature on bargaining in the field of social psychology points out that humans are not perfectly rational decision makers who form the basis of game-theoretical models. Several cognitive biases have been identified that can influence bargaining behavior. For example, bargaining 60 Bargaining A’s utility B’s reserve level x z A’s reserve level Non-agreement UCA B’s utility UCB y Welfare boundary Figure 3 Side payments and issue linkage partners are biased by their own position and value self-serving information more highly than they objectively should (egocentrism). Furthermore, humans seem to behave differently toward risk depending on whether they perceive the bargaining object as entailing gains or losses (framing effect). In addition, negotiators tend to be unduly influenced by the early phases of bargaining (anchoring effect) and do not adjust their perception and behavior in a completely rational manner. Finally, negotiators can be too focused on the competitive dimension of bargaining (fixed-pie perception) and subsequently fail to realize mutually beneficial outcomes. Psychologists also argue that the relationship between bargaining partners and the social context influences the bargaining process. Other work addresses the medium of bargaining and cross-cultural differences. Andreas Warntjen See also Bargaining in International Relations Further Readings Bazerman, N., Curhan, J. D., Moore, D. A., & Valley, K. L. (2000). Negotiation. Annual Review of Psychology, 51, 279–314. Brams, S. (2003). Negotiation games. London: Routledge. Hopmann, P. T. (1998). The negotiation process and the resolution of international conflict. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. Muthoo, A. (1999). Bargaining theory with applications. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Raiffa, H. (2002). Negotiation analysis. Cambridge, MA: Belknap. Scharpf, F. (1997). Games real actors play: Actor-centered institutionalism in policy research. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Schelling, T. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Thomson, L., & Loewenstein, J. (2003). Mental models of negotiation. In M. A. Hogg & J. Cooper (Eds.), The Sage handbook of social psychology (pp. 494–511). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Young, H. P. (1991). Negotiation analysis. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Bargaining in International Relations BARGAINING RELATIONS IN INTERNATIONAL Bargaining—whether over arms control, the terms of a peace settlement, exchange rate coordination, alliances, or trade agreements—is a central feature of international relations. In the past decades, the literature on bargaining in international relations has seen much interesting research and has been at the forefront of formal work in international relations. Because bargaining is an activity in which the strategic interdependence of decision making is central, much of the literature is based on gametheoretic modeling. Bargaining is the negotiation over the terms of an agreement. Although often more than one agreement exists that two or more actors would prefer to no agreement, the actors disagree regarding their ranking of the mutually preferable agreement. Moreover, bargaining involves interdependent actions. In other words, the decisions made by one actor will depend largely on the actual or likely decisions made by another actor. In addition, bargaining often has “rules of the game.” For example, actors can make demands or offers simultaneously, one actor could make a demand or offer and the other accepts or rejects (a so-called take-it-orleave-it game), or the actors can make demands or offers sequentially. This brings us to another feature of bargaining: it is often dynamic. Finally, bargaining typically involves uncertainty about the other actor’s preferences. In sum, the process of bargaining in international relations is complex, and the literature on the topic spans the fields of history, economics, political science, and international relations. As we will see, conventional measures of power (physical strength or financial resources) are an important, but certainly not the only determinant of bargaining power. Issues such as credibility, multiple bargaining levels, enforcement possibilities, asymmetric information, indivisibility, commitment problems, political bias, and the social context all affect the bargaining outcome in important ways. Bargaining and Credibility Thomas Schelling’s 1960 book, The Strategy of Conflict, remains the classic work on bargaining in international relations. He argues that bargaining power 61 depends largely on the credibility of threats and promises. Greater physical power or more financial resources are by no means the only advantages in bargaining situations. On the contrary, Schelling argues that in some situations, restricting one’s options may be beneficial. Weakness may be strength because it can force others to make concessions. Schelling illustrates this concept through the example of a union bargaining with management. If the union insists on, say, $2 and expects the management to counter with $1.60, persuading the management to pay $2 is not the only option available to the union. Schelling argues that the union should lead the management to believe that it could not accept less than $2 even if it wished to. The union may, for example, argue that it no longer controls its members. By portraying its own weakness and confronting management with the threat of a strike the union itself cannot avert, the threat is made credible. The paradoxical result is that in bargaining, weakness is often strength. We also find this dynamic in international relations. In a seminal 1994 article, James D. Fearon illustrates how audience costs, the cost statespeople suffer among their constituency of backing down after escalating a conflict, can make actions such as troop mobilization and other forms of escalation credible signals. As we shall see later, states can often deliberately restrict their options in order to achieve better bargaining outcomes. Bargaining at Multiple Levels As the last example demonstrates, bargaining in international relations often occurs at more than one level. At the international level, a statesperson may bargain over an agreement with fellow statespeople, while bargaining with domestic constituents over the ratification of such an agreement. Thus, the statesperson must consider the interests of international actors, while considering pressures from different domestic actors, each pressuring the statesperson to adopt policies favorable to its interests. Robert Putnam labeled this the two-level game. The introduction of the domestic level of bargaining made an important contribution to the literature on bargaining in international relations. It also challenged the state-centered approach of realism and neorealism, which conceive states as unitary rational actors. Conceiving bargaining as a multilevel game enriches the level of strategic interaction, 62 Bargaining in International Relations which Putnam analyzed using win-sets, which are the sets of possible agreements at the international level that would find the necessary approval at the domestic level. In other words, larger win-sets make agreements more likely because they leave more room for agreement. Conversely, if the winsets of two negotiators do not overlap, no agreement will be reached. The less “powerful” a negotiator is, the more bargaining power he or she may have. That is, being under severe domestic constraints, and therefore having a small domestic win-set, can be a bargaining advantage to a statesperson because it limits what he or she can promise at the international level. Similarly, just as domestic constraints can improve statespeople’s international bargaining power, international constraints can enhance the bargaining power of the statespeople at home. Indeed, international negotiations sometimes enable government leaders to do what they privately wish to do, but would otherwise be powerless to do domestically. Finally, negotiators have a strong interest in the domestic support of their bargaining counterpart. If the domestic support of bargaining partners increases, so does the size of their win-set, thereby increasing the likelihood of reaching an agreement, and the relative bargaining leverage of the other state. Negotiators in international relations are therefore to be expected to try to reinforce one another’s standing with their respective constituents. Bargaining and International Cooperation Bargaining over an agreement is often only a first step. States need to look at the future monitoring and enforcement of any agreement reached. An agreement reached in principle is not worth the paper it is written on if it cannot be enforced in practice. This second stage of bargaining is addressed by cooperation theory. Compliance with agreements, according to cooperation theory, is akin to the prisoner’s dilemma. States may have an incentive to keep their end of the bargain, but only if the other side is likely to do so as well. Cooperation under the security dilemma can be sustained if states interact over a long span of time. States can deter defection from a bargain through conditional retaliation such as tit-for-tat. A key condition for such mechanisms to work is that states should care sufficiently about future payoffs. This is often described as “the shadow of the future.” If the utility of future cooperation is greater than the utility of immediate defection and subsequent punishment, cooperation can be sustained. In an important 1998 article, Fearon explains how the shadow of the future can affect international bargaining. First, in cases where effective monitoring of an agreement is not possible, statespeople know that no bargaining agreement will be enforceable. Consequently, it is possible to observe nonserious bargaining in which states will only commit to vague agreements for various political purposes, or there will be no bargaining at all. Second, and more interestingly, although better monitoring and a long shadow of the future may make enforcing an international agreement easier, it also gives states an incentive to bargain harder, delaying agreement in hopes of getting a better deal. That is, the more the future is valued, the greater are the incentives for states to bargain hard for favorable terms. It is therefore possible to observe costly, noncooperative standoffs in precisely those situations where cooperation theorists predict cooperation—that is, in situations where the shadow of the future is long and there are potential mutual gains from an agreement. Bargaining and War A great deal of work on international relations bargaining has dealt with war. This topic is also at the forefront of game-theoretic modeling in international relations. In a seminal 1995 article, Fearon illustrates the central puzzle about war. When a war is costly to its parties, each side would have been better off if they could have achieved the same outcome without suffering the costs. Consequently, war should be considered as a bargaining breakdown. Figure 1 illustrates. States A and B compete over a piece of territory that covers 0 to 1. Initially, state A (B) owns part 0 to x (x to 1). If country A fights, it wins the whole territory (0 to 1) with probability p. However, fighting results in a cost equal to cA (cB) to state A (B). Accordingly, the payoff for fighting for country A (B) is given by 0 to p – cA (p cB to 1). The central puzzle about war is this ex post inefficiency because any settlement between p – cA and p cB is preferred by both parties over fighting. Why then does war, as a bargaining breakdown, occur? Fearon suggests 63 Bargaining in International Relations that there can be only three rationalist explanations for war: asymmetric information, indivisibility, and commitment problems. Asymmetric Information Asymmetric information occurs when one state knows more about its capabilities than does the other. According to Fearon, asymmetric information can lead to war. Indeed, if both sides knew who was going to win a war, they would not bother fighting it. But to know which side would win the war, there must be symmetric information between potential belligerents. For example, suppose state A makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer, which B can accept or reject by fighting. If the states have complete information, then A will make the largest demand that B will accept (p cB). B will accept because it can’t do better by fighting. However, if A is unsure about B’s cost of fighting (cB), A no longer knows what to ask without provoking war. There is now a trade-off for state A between obtaining better terms and a higher probability that war will occur. Conversely, in misperceiving the capabilities of its opponent, B may mistakenly opt for war. Most tragically, information asymmetries are difficult to overcome because states have incentives to misrepresent their capabilities to achieve better bargaining outcomes. Thus, although states may want to avoid war, they often choose not to be completely transparent. finer graded divisions or compromise—then there may not be any feasible outcome that both states prefer to fighting. If the issue allows only a finite number of resolutions, it might be that none falls within the bargaining range (p – cA and p cB). However, although this is a potential reason why rational states may go to war, Fearon does not find this explanation compelling. The issues over which states bargain typically are multidimensional. Side payments or linkages with other issues typically are possible. Also, states could alternate or randomize among a fixed number of possible solutions to a dispute. Empirically, therefore, all issues can be divided. Commitment Problems Finally, war may occur if states cannot credibly commit themselves to follow through on a negotiated agreement. That is, mutually preferable bargains may be unattainable because one or more states has an incentive to renege on the terms. The prisoner’s dilemma is the classic example of this problem. Although both actors prefer the cooperative outcome to mutual defection, both have an incentive to renege. Commitment problems are usually illustrated in a dynamic bargaining setting. If state B is expected to decline in military power (p2 p1), and if state A cannot commit itself not to exploit the greater bargaining leverage it will have starting in the second period, a preventive attack may be rational for state B. Indivisibility Political Bias The indivisibility of issues can also lead to war. If states A and B bargain over an issue that is indivisible—some issues maybe do not admit Recently, Matthew O. Jackson and Massimo Morelli argued that political bias may also lead to war. It is possible that a pivotal decision 0 x A’s status quo payoff A’s payoff from fighting Figure 1 The bargaining range Source: Adapted from Fearon (1995). p cA p p cB 1 B’s status quo payoff B’s payoff from fighting 64 Barry, Brian maker—whether an executive, a monarch, the median member of an oligarchy, or the median voter—might have relative benefits or costs of war that are different from the state at large. In an authoritarian regime, for example, a leader might keep a disproportionate share of the gains of war. Jackson and Morelli show that, given sufficient bias by one or both countries, war cannot be prevented by any transfer payment. Interestingly, they also show that a country may choose a biased leader because it will lead to a stronger bargaining position. Social Context and Bargaining Most of the literature on bargaining in international relations takes relations among states as a function of the material capabilities and interests of nations. However, interstate relations are often embedded in socially constructed norms. This social context can play a role in shaping international bargaining outcomes. In an important article, Leonard Schoppa introduces the social context in the field of international bargaining and argues how issues such as identity, trust, and norms influence bargaining. The amount of trust among bargaining parties, for example, can dramatically affect the likelihood of achieving cooperative agreements. In addition, in the context of bargaining, threats that are perceived as “fair” (e.g., in accord with procedural rules stipulated under an international regime) are more likely to be effective in extracting concessions. These examples illustrate how the social context might have an effect on bargaining in international relations, independent of the power and interests of the players. Conclusion Bargaining in international relations is at the forefront of (formal) research in international relations. Bargaining can take place in different policy dimensions, with two or more players, at more than two levels, with single or repeated interactions, with perfect or asymmetric information, social context, and so on. Great insights have been generated by the literature on bargaining in international relations. These insights have also paved the way for future potential empirical work. Peter van der Windt See also Bargaining; Cooperation; Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power; Nash Equilibrium; Neorealism; Prisoner’s Dilemma; Realism in International Relations Further Readings Fearon, J. D. (1994). Domestic political audiences and the escalation of international disputes. American Political Science Review, 88(3), 577–592. Fearon, J. D. (1995). Rationalist explanations for war. International Organization, 49(3), 379–414. Fearon, J. D. (1998). Bargaining, enforcement, and international cooperation. International Organization, 52(2), 269–305. Jackson, M. O., & Morelli. M. (2007). Political bias and war. American Economic Review, 97(4), 1353–1373. Putnam, R. D. (1988). Diplomacy and domestic politics: The logic of two-level games. International Organization, 42(3), 427–460. Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. BARRY, BRIAN (1936–2009) Brian Barry is one of the most influential political scientists of the last 50 years and in 2001 was made the seventh recipient of the Johan Skytte Prize in political science. In addition to his work on justice, rational choice theory, and multiculturalism, Barry wrote several essays on political power—a number of which have been reprinted in Democracy, Power and Justice: Essays in Political Theory (1989). Barry’s first contribution to the study of power was a methodological one. In the 1970s, he was one of the first political scientists to apply to the study of political power some of the analytical tools used by economists to study markets and exchange. In “Power: An Economic Analysis” (1975), he poses a series of questions about the nature of power and the relationship between having and exercising power. He says that it is his intention to “dissolve the puzzlement that such questions reflect” not through the “orthodox” linguistic approach of grappling with the nuances of meaning but through the construction of a “model designed to give insight into the processes involved.” This model, which makes use of such concepts as ordinal and cardinal utility and equilibrium, is presented for the reader through a series of 15 Barry, Brian diagrams. Looked at today, the essay appears unexceptional because a number of rational choice theorists apply the methods of economics to the study of power. Barry was, however, one of the first to appreciate both the possibilities and limitations of this economic approach. Barry’s other principal contribution revolves around the distinction between power and luck. People are successful to the extent that they get the outcomes that correspond to their preferences. People are lucky to the extent that they are successful without having to do anything. The difference between people’s success and their luck is their decisiveness (luck decisiveness success). When it is expressed in this way, decisiveness appears to be a property of individuals. Yet, Barry is also clear that there may be situations in which a group collectively brings about an outcome though no one person is decisive. If a bloc of voters always agree with each other and together constitute substantially more than a majority, then as long as each of them votes, no one member of the bloc will make any difference to the overall result even though each member of the group will always be successful. What of political power? Power is related to but is not the same as decisiveness. The difference between the two is that although decisiveness is a probability, power is a capacity. An actor’s power is his or her ability to overcome resistance—not the actor’s probability of encountering and overcoming resistance. To see what is at stake here, consider the position of an omnipotent dictator. We would want to say that the dictator is powerful. But imagine a situation in which the dictator happens to live in a society in which everyone else already wants what it is that the dictator also happens to want. In such a situation, the dictator would be very lucky but completely indecisive because his or her luck would be entirely responsible for the dictator’s success. If we were to equate power with decisiveness, we would then be forced to conclude that the dictator is powerless. What is missing here is the relevant counterfactual. The dictator is powerful because, even if every other person in the society had the opposite set of preferences, the dictator could still bring about the outcome he or she wanted. The important lesson to be drawn is that power is an “inherently counterfactual notion.” Is it better to be powerful or lucky? Given any amount of luck, it is always better to be more 65 powerful than less because the more powerful you are, the better your chances are of being decisive and so being successful. But unless the possession of power is to be valued as an end in itself rather than as a means to an end, is there any necessary reason why it is better to be powerful than lucky? The answer is that it is better to be powerful than lucky if you are unsure whether your preferences will continue to be the same as those of the people on whom you currently rely. Someone who is successful today because he or she is lucky may well be unlucky and unsuccessful tomorrow. People who are successful today because they are powerful need not depend on their luck holding. In a more recent essay, Barry (2002) argues that capitalists are powerful rather than lucky. The definition of power Barry employs here is similar to that used in the earlier article. Power is “the ability to bring about desired states of the world . . . by acting in such a way as to overcome the resistance of others.” When power is defined in this way, it is plausible to argue that the option of voting for another party gives voters power over a democratically elected government and that the option of buying a product from another firm (or not buying it at all) gives consumers power over firms. This is pretty much standard liberal fare. The interesting argument is that for much the same reasons capitalists are not simply lucky in wanting what it is that governments want but that they also have power over governments. If it makes sense to argue that consumers are powerful even if they do not formally have to write to a firm to say that they are going withdraw their custom unless the firm lowers its price or raises its quality, it also makes sense to argue that capitalists are powerful even if they do not have to threaten to withhold their investments unless offered some policy concessions. Furthermore, if it makes sense to argue that voters are powerful even if no single person’s vote can make any difference to an election result, it also makes sense to say that capitalists are collectively powerful even if no single firm acting alone can change the course of government policy. Andrew Hindmoor See also Banzhof Value; Distributive Justice; Dowding, Keith; Luck; Systematic Luck 66 Bases of Power Further Readings Barry, B. (1989). Democracy, power and justice: Essays in political theory. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. Barry, B. (2002). Capitalists rule OK? Some puzzles about power. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 1, 155–184. BASES OF POWER The ability to get others to do one’s will is known as social power. Social power consists of the available tools one person has to exert influence over another. It is the potential resources (which may or may not be used) that one has at one’s command that can lead to an actual change (or deliberate maintenance) in the beliefs, attitudes, behavior, emotions, and so on in another person. Much of human interaction involves attempts to change or maintain beliefs, attitudes, and behaviors in another, so this topic has long been of interest to social psychologists. Because of this, there have been a number of investigations using different definitions of social power, and investigations using different ways of measuring power. However, the approach most commonly used in the social psychological and industrial/organizational literature was proposed by John R. P. French Jr. and Bertram H. Raven in the 1950s. French and Raven identified specific social resources that people might possess that they could use to influence others; French and Raven called these resources the bases of power: informational, reward, coercion, legitimacy, expertise, and referent. Based on an early paper, some researchers omit informational, which was later listed as a base of power. With additional research, there has been continual development of the bases of power. Now the bases of power include the original six resources as a broad framework, but some of these resources have been further differentiated. Origins of the Bases of Power The bases of power concept was developed at the Research Center for Group Dynamics at the University of Michigan in the early 1950s. Raven was a graduate student there working closely with Leon Festinger, who was Raven’s PhD dissertation advisor at the time. During this period, Festinger wrote an article concerning some of the reasons people agree to do things. In the article, he observed that when offered a reward or threatened with punishment, people will often change their behavior, but only when those trying to influence them can observe them—when not being observed, the requested behavior stops. However, Festinger also found that sometimes the new behavior continued whether or not someone was being observed. In this case, it appeared that personal beliefs as well as behavior had changed. Raven’s dissertation (completed with French as his advisor when Festinger left for the University of Minnesota) was, in part, based on factors that distinguished behavior change requiring continued observation from change that did not. After Festinger left Michigan, Raven and French began to look at additional factors that affected changes in personal beliefs from those that only affected observable behavior. With the leadership of Dorwin Cartwright, at this point most of the members of the Research Center for Group Dynamics began to study social power. As members of the group, French and Raven continued their investigations into social power. Because of French’s extensive background in industrial and organizational psychology, they concentrated on the relationship between supervisors and subordinates in a work environment. Using the work environment as a guide while examining both the experimental literature and their own experiences, they developed the bases of power model. Bases of Power Defined and Explained In the power literature, the person who is the source of influence is commonly known as the influencing agent, and the object of the attempted or successful influence is commonly known the target (of influence). Thus, influencing agents have social power, which are the means they may use to influence targets. As discussed, six bases of power were included in French and Raven’s original statement. Additional research led to continued development of the typology, and these original bases were further differentiated. Socially Independent and Socially Dependent Change The base (or bases) of power chosen for an influence attempt can have a number of effects on Bases of Power the target in addition to the intended effect to persuade. One such effect that French and Raven described is in the difference between socially independent and socially dependent change. A successful socially independent influence attempt leads to a change in the beliefs of the target, and as such, the change that occurs in the target does not require the target to refer, remember, or necessarily think about the agent of change. By contrast, socially dependent change does require the target to connect the change to the influencing agent in some way. To illustrate: some people wear motorcycle helmets because at some point in the past, they were convinced that wearing a helmet is a good thing to do. Because these people believe that helmets make riding safer, they wear them because they want to. Thus, their change is socially independent; they do not need continued outside influence to compel them to wear a helmet. But other motorcyclists do not believe helmets make riding safer, and they may believe that helmets are dangerous. Yet in states where a police officer has the legitimate authority to require motorcyclists to wear a helmet, they will do so. As long as the police have that authority, these motorcyclists will wear their helmets while riding. Take the authority of the police to require helmets away (as in states that do not require helmets), and the helmet comes off. In this case, the change (wearing a helmet) is connected to the police (and the authority they have), thus it is socially dependent. Power That Leads to Socially Independent Change Informational Power Informational power has the property of being a socially independent source of influence. Informational power, or persuasion, is based on the information or logical argument that the agent can present to the target. Information can be presented directly by the agent, indirectly through a third party, or by the agent suggesting that he or she overheard someone else giving such an argument. Evidence indicates that in certain cases, information presented indirectly as an overheard conversation may be more effective than is information presented directly. In the latter case, the target may show reactance (which is resisting influence because the influence attempt may 67 threaten the target’s sense of independence). Presenting information indirectly avoids the possibility of reactance. No matter how it is presented, however, if successful, informational power has advantages because it leads to more a permanent cognitive change, a personal acceptance of the changed behavior by the target. Power That Leads to Socially Dependent Change With Surveillance Necessary Coercive Power The threat of punishment is the basis of coercive power. The influencing agent brings about a change in the target by threatening the target with some sort of negative or undesirable consequences for not doing what the influencing agent wants. Though it can be very effective, coercive power carries with it certain problems and dangers. It depends on the target expecting that his or her compliance will be monitored or observed by the agent. If the threat of being observed is removed, the behavior itself may also cease. Another negative effect of coercion is that the target will generally resent and dislike such threats and the agent who might use them. Reward Power Reward power stems from the agent’s ability to grant some reward to the target, such as a promise of promotion or offering of certain privileges for complying with a request. Reward power also requires surveillance of the target, but surveillance is usually less difficult than with coercion. Here, the target will generally attempt to let the agent know that compliance has occurred and the reward is due. Reward power also may lead to more positive feelings toward the agent. In French and Raven’s original statement, both reward and coercive power were defined in terms of tangible physical rewards and real physical threats such as being fired or fined, monetary rewards, and job bonuses or promotion. Later, it became clear that both reward and coercion may have more personal forms, and these personal forms could also serve as powerful tools for influence. Thus, potential approval and liking can be seen as very rewarding; disapproval and personal rejection can be very punishing. So both reward power and coercive power were later distinguished 68 Bases of Power along the lines of impersonal coercion and impersonal reward, which concern tangible physical matters, and personal coercion and personal reward, which involve intangible personal concerns such as liking. Considering personal as well as impersonal rewards and punishments helped researchers better understand certain forms of influence where surveillance was important, but that had previously been confused with referent power (referent power is discussed below). Power That Leads to Socially Dependent Change With Surveillance Unnecessary As discussed, coercive power and reward power are distinguished in that their effectiveness requires that the target feel that the degree of his or her compliance with the influencing agent’s request will be discernible to the agent. Thus, surveillance or observability of the target becomes critical. For the bases of power to be discussed (expert, legitimate, and referent), surveillance by the influencing agent is not important. However, even though surveillance is not necessary for expert and referent and legitimate power, it is still important that the target relate the changed behavior to the agent in some way. Using expert power as an example: if your uncle asks you to drive your new car gently until it is broken in, and if you trust your uncle (and you care about your car), you will comply with his request. However, if you later hear differently from someone you trust more (such as your longtime mechanic), you will probably just drive your new car normally. In the preceding example, surveillance is not necessary because, with respect to the influencing agent, there is no reward or punishment involved. However, the success of the influence attempt (by the uncle or mechanic) is socially dependent because it depends on qualities that the influencing agent is perceived to possess (in this case trustworthiness, credibility, and perceived automotive expertise). Expert Power This form of power (as it was used in the earlier example) shares some of the positive qualities of informational power in that it can result in a transformation of a person’s beliefs, with the resulting personal acceptance of the change. However, it differs from informational power in that the target does not need to be convinced by argument or rationale for the change per se. Indeed, with effective use of expert power, no argument or rational is necessary. Instead, the target accepts on faith the accuracy and propriety of the suggestions or advice, trusting in the superior knowledge or ability and truthfulness of the influencing agent: it is if targets are saying to themselves, “He or she knows best, even if I don’t entirely understand why, but because they are the experts I’ll do what they say.” Referent Power Referent power is based on the target of influence positively identifying with the influencing agent. If the influencing agent possesses referent power, this leads the target to have a sense of “oneness” and mutuality, or a desire for such a relationship. So if the influencing agent is someone that the target likes, admires, or feels very positive about, this gives the influencing agent referent power with respect to that target. The target wants to do what the influencing agent wants, because of its feelings of oneness, mutuality, or a desire to feel a sense of oneness or mutuality. For example, it is not uncommon for movie, music, sports, and political stars to be able to influence their fans simply because their fans admire these people. Because of this admiration, fans may do what the star requests (or what they think the star might request), even if it would be impossible for the star to know what the fan did (thus no possibility of reward or punishment from the influencing agent). Overview of Legitimate Power Legitimate power is based on social norms, such that the target feels an obligation to comply with the requests by the agent. Legitimate power depends on the target’s acceptance of the right of the influencing agent to require the changed behavior, and the target’s sense of obligation to comply. Essentially, the influencing agent says, “I have a right to ask you to do this and you have an obligation to comply.” Terms such as obliged to, should, ought to, and required to generally imply legitimate power. There are four delineations of legitimate power within the bases of power typology: position, reciprocity, equity, and responsibility. Bases of Power Legitimate Position Power Legitimate position power is perhaps the most obvious form of legitimate power. Position power is tied to a certain position in an organization, society, or group, and the power that comes with that position. This form of power often (but not always) depends on a formal hierarchy in an organization, or cultural norms relating power to a hierarchy in society. So, in organizations such as the military, this is the power that a superior officer has over a subordinate officer or enlisted person; in companies, it is the power that a supervisor has over a subordinate worker; and in hospitals, it is the power that a doctor has over a nurse. Other examples that reflect specific cultural norms might be the right of elders to make tribal decisions, royalty to influence commoners, parents to influence children, professors to influence students, and traffic cops to direct traffic. The specific context in which position power is exercised often matters, so, for example, although professors have legitimate position power in their classrooms, they do not have it at a ballgame with friends. However, other less-obvious social norms dictate such obligatory compliance. Legitimate Power of Reciprocity Legitimate power of reciprocity is the type of influence that essentially says, “I did this good thing for you and so, in return, you should be ready to grant my request.” For example, if, while waiting for the bus, one accepts a ride home, one would feel obligated to help the person who gave you the ride in the future. Reciprocity is a basic social norm, so basic that many respond automatically without thinking when the legitimate power of reciprocity is invoked. Thus, many will automatically repay small debts unwillingly incurred to others and find it hard to resist the repayment of even large debts. Some will resist by avoiding the receipt of “free” gifts so as not to incur the psychological debt associated with reciprocity. Legitimate Power of Equity The legitimate power of equity is based on the social norm that people should get what they deserve. So if the agent has worked hard, and suffered for a target, the social norm is that the target 69 should make things more equitable by doing what the influencing agent requests. Some might refer to this as the compensatory norm because the agent might legitimately say, “What you have done in the past has been harmful or painful for me, so now you should make up (compensate me) for it by doing as I ask.” To invoke the legitimate power of equity, the agent must have done something for the target that affected the agent in a negative way, or the target must have done something that has had a negative effect on the agent. This gives the agent the social power to ask the target to compensate the agent to make things right. Legitimate Power of Responsibility This last named form of legitimacy has also been called the power of dependence, or the legitimate power of the powerless. This is based on the social norm of the responsibility, which is that society expects individuals to help those who cannot help themselves. Examples might include children asking for help with tasks they cannot do themselves (such as tying their shoes), a stranger asking for directions, or a homeless person asking for a handout. Note that these last two forms of legitimate power (equity and responsibility) seem to rely heavily on the target’s feelings of guilt, either for what he or she has done or not done in the past, or the anticipation of guilt in the future for not having complied. The Power/Interaction Model of Interpersonal Influence Recent developments concerning the bases of power have put the bases of power discussed earlier into a larger context through the development of the power/interaction model of interpersonal influence. As in the original statement by French and Raven, the power/interaction model first considers the obvious fact that people often change their behaviors, their beliefs, attitudes, or emotions. Often such changes occur without the involvement of others—they are responses to the changes in the environmental conditions, to new insights from personal observation, and so forth. In the model, social influence is defined as (a) a change in the belief, attitude, or behavior of a target of influence 70 Bases of Power that has its origin in an influencing agent, or (b) stability or lack of change that is similarly attributable to an influencing agent. The latter point recognizes that sometimes people may be ready to change in response to the environment or because of new intellectual insights, but such change may be mitigated through the influence of others. Social power is defined as potential influence. The influencing agent has various bases of power, which are resources he or she may draw on to bring about such change. These bases of power, in turn, have important implications for the effectiveness of influence, whether the influence depends on the agent socially, whether surveillance by the influencing agent is important for the change to be maintained, and on the future interpersonal relationship between agent and target. The power/ interaction model assumes that when making an influence attempt, rational influencing agents will tend to choose the base or bases of power they use because of their projected efficacy and anticipated side effects. However, other considerations also enter into the choice: considerations of time and energy involved, views of third parties, moral or ethical considerations, personal preference for influence style, and so on. To avoid negative side effects during an influence attempt, an influencing agent may adopt any number of tactics known as ameliorative strategies. In addition, the power/ interaction model examines preparatory or stagesetting devices that an agent must often use to strengthen the bases of power that he or she may plan to use. Choice of Power Strategy Motivations may play an important role as the agent determines what bases of power and influence strategies he or she might use. There may be considerations other than making sure that the influence attempt is successful. The rational agent would examine each available influence strategy relative to the target and the situation. Which influence strategy would effectively bring about the desired change? At what cost and how much effort? How much time would it take to implement the change with that strategy? Would the influence strategy be consistent with the agent’s norms and values? Would the strategy lead to long-term change? Would continued surveillance be necessary? The effects of motivation in influencing the choice of influence strategy becomes more clear when we consider that sometimes the agent could influence the target very readily through the use of informational power (logical persuasion), but other motivations would make such a choice less likely. For example, in certain instances, influencing agents might want to emphasize their superior position in a hierarchy when influencing a target. In this case, they could rely on coercion or reward to emphasize to the target that the influencing agent is in a position to punish or reward the target, thus reminding the target that the agent is more powerful than the target. In other cases, the influencing agent might not feel that he or she alone has sufficient power resources to produce an effect in the target. Here, the agent might invoke what is called the power of third parties—for example, a mother telling children that if they do not behave, wait till their father gets home, or a minister invoking the power of God. Preparing for Influence In planning an influence strategy, an agent will often decide that a particular strategy might be best, but that some preparation is needed. Research has described the various preparatory strategies used by a former president of the United States, Harry Truman, and the former chancellor of Nazi Germany, Adolf Hitler. For example, attempting to establish his expert power with five star general Douglas MacArthur, Truman spoke of his inside intelligence information concerning China, about military preparedness, and the likelihood of diplomatic losses for the United States. In preparing for the use of referent power Truman emphasized to MacArthur their mutual military background, and that they essentially had the same goals. To prepare for coercive power, Hitler sometimes behaved like a madman who would not be restrained by the usual protocol in dealing with Austria. He also showed that he had excellent information about what was going on in Austria, thus demonstrating the power of his intelligence services. By the use of these preparatory strategies, when it came time for the actual use of power, the effectiveness of the tactic(s) was enhanced. Bicameral Legislature Assessing the Effects and Reassessing Strategies Once influence has been attempted, the agent then reviews the success of the attempt, as well as positive and negative side effects. He or she then might also reexamine the motivation for influence, reexamine the choice of influence strategies, and renew the influence process. If an influence attempt is effective in obtaining the desirable effect, the influencing agent need only examine what costs were involved, whether the target might resent the influence and the agent, and how to remedy these side effects. If the influence attempt is unsuccessful, or only partially successful, the agent must then carefully assess why it might not have succeeded, monitor any changes in the relationship positive or negative, and then determine whether the influence attempt should be abandoned or a change in strategy is called for. Clever influencing agents will monitor the effects of their influencing strategies on the target, and reconsider and change tactics as needed. Sometimes they will use personal observation, but often it is necessary to use third parties or other means. For example, during World War II, British Prime Minister Winston Churchill relied heavily on the British Ambassador Lord Lothian to keep him informed about the effects of Churchill’s attempts to influence the United States to enter the war. Lothian reported changes in the attitudes and beliefs of President Franklin D. Roosevelt, Congress, and other important figures on the U.S. scene, thus enabling Churchill to better calibrate his influence strategies. Power/Interaction From the Target’s Perspective Finally, within the power/interaction model, social influence is a dynamic interactive process. Thus, although the focus to this point has been on the behavior of the influencing agent, it is also worthwhile to examine the process from the target’s perspective. The target also has extrinsic and intrinsic motivations to comply with or resist influence. There will be cases when the target will not be particularly opposed to the requested change, or when the change, when properly described, will even be desirable. In other cases, the change would be particularly undesirable for the target, whose resistance to change will be all the greater. The target’s perspective will depend on his or her attitudes toward the agent, concern about internal 71 constructs of self-image, and how compliance or noncompliance would affect how other persons would view the target. As noted previously, resistance to change, and even change in a direction opposite to that desired by the agent, will sometimes result from what has been called “reactance,” concern that one’s independence or freedom of choice may be threatened by compliance. In anticipation of influence, the target may also develop a series of counterstrategies and would then review the effects of such compliance or noncompliance on subsequent relationships with the influencing agent. Gregg J. Gold See also French, John R. P., Jr.; Influence; Raven, Bertram; Social Power Further Readings French, J. R. P., Jr., & Raven, B. H. (1959). The bases of social power. In D. Cartwright (Ed.), Studies in social power (pp. 150–167). Ann Arbor, MI: Institute for Social Research. Mintzberg, H. (1983). Power in and around organizations. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Raven, B. H. (1992). A power/interaction model of interpersonal influence: French and Raven thirty years later. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 7, 217–244. Raven, B. H. (2001). Power/interaction and interpersonal influence: Experimental investigations and case studies. In A. Y. Lee-Chai & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The use and abuse of power (pp. 217–240). Ann Arbor, MI: Sheridan Books. BICAMERAL LEGISLATURE Bicameral legislatures are law-making institutions of a country with two chambers or houses—a lower house representing the democratic interests of the common people and an upper house to represent specific classes, regions, or people of experience. The term bicameral was coined by Jeremy Bentham in 1832, and bicameralism gained popularity in the 18th century, even though the concept was adopted in Britain much earlier, in the 14th century. Bicameral legislatures provide an institutionalized veto power that aims to prevent tyranny of the majority 72 Biopower as described by Alexander Hamilton and others, as well as tyranny of the minority. In most bicameral legislatures, members of the lower house are directly elected, whereas those in upper house are indirectly or directly elected, or appointed based on criteria such as regional representation, heredity, and expertise in a particular field. In many countries, members of directly elected local, provincial, or state governments elect the members of upper house. About two thirds of democratic national legislatures are bicameral, with one third of these located in federal polities. Examples of upper and lower houses include the Senate and the House of Representatives in the United States and the House of Lords and House of Commons in the United Kingdom. Different political parties can dominate in lower and upper houses, so bicameralism can lead to power struggles to influence legislation and policy making. The upper house can delay, oppose, or in some cases even veto a legislation, thus acting as a check on the powers of the lower house. However, in most polities, the lower house has the ultimate power to legislate and can overrule the objections of the upper house. Arend Lijphart categorizes bicameral legislatures by congruence of the political composition and symmetry of power of the two houses. Thus, bicameral legislatures can be strong (incongruent and symmetric), weak (congruent and symmetric, or incongruent and asymmetric), and insignificant (congruent and asymmetric). Under symmetric bicameralism, both chambers have equal power—for example, in polities with federal units or presidential systems, such as the United States— whereas in asymmetric bicameralism, the lower house has more power, as in parliamentary democracies and unitary systems such as Britain. An upper house that has veto power increases the number of veto players and can thus result in higher policy stability. For example, in the United States, the Senate as a veto-player can shift the legislative status quo. However, this can also lead to unnecessary deadlocks, delays, and hindrance to policy making. Powers and practices of the upper house have come under review in many countries. Britain, for example, partially abolished hereditary peerage in the House of Lords in 1999 with a view to making it more democratic. Rekha Diwakar See also Bargaining; Legislative Power; Unicameral Legislature; Veto Players Further Readings Riker, W. (1992). The justification of bicameralism. International Political Science Review, 12(1), 101–116. Tsebelis, G., & Money, J. (1997). Bicameralism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. BIOPOWER Michel Foucault coined the term biopower to refer to the administration of human life both collectively and individually. Biopower involves the production and reproduction of life and is evident in such things as public health, welfare policy, regulation of fertility and heredity, population control and eugenics, racial ordering, the regulation of sexuality, and modern biotechnologies. Biopower emerged in the 18th century, but had its ascendancy in the latter 20th and early 21st centuries. Foucault and Biopower Foucault introduced the notion of biopower, and a related term, bio-politics, in the first volume of The History of Sexuality. Here, the concept biopower builds on his earlier reconceptualization of power as omnipresent capillaries and as productive. In Discipline and Punish, Foucault contrasts the productive nature of the power of discipline with the restrictive nature of sovereign power. Foucault later explains that the disciplinary power that emerged in the 17th century operates on the body, reflecting an “anatomo-politics,” whereas biopower emerged in the following century and involves the regulation of the population, or species body. At the beginning of his lecture series, Security, Territory, Population, Foucault describes biopower as those mechanisms through which human biological features became the target of political strategies. Foucault examines the emergence of this governmental interest in the population through liberalism, the technologies of statistics, and the social sciences, such as political economy, demography and sociology. Although the emphasis of biopower is on Blackmail enhancing the productive aspects of the population, and contrasts with the sovereign power’s right to take, biopower also involves the capacity to take, or withhold, life. Other Authors In Homo Sacer, Giorgio Agamben has used Foucault’s notion of biopower as part of his argument that sovereign power is not eclipsed by biopower. Rather, Agamben argues that sovereign power and biopower come together in the formation of “The Camp,” a zone in which the state of exception is permanent, and “in which power confronts nothing but pure life.” In Empire, Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri use the concept of biopower in their neo-Marxist account of contemporary globalized power, denoted as “Empire.” They argue that biopolitical production has become the centerpiece of contemporary power. Indeed, “Empire presents the paradigmatic form of biopower.” More recently, Nikolas Rose examined the role of biopower in the operation of contemporary biotechnologies. He argues that emerging biotechnologies link biopower increasing to the liberal formation of selves, with their associated questions of ethics, risk, and responsibility. Paul Henman See also Discipline; Foucault, Michel; Governmentality; Postmodern View of Power in International Relations; Sovereignty Further Readings Foucault, M. (2008). The birth of biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 1978–1979. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Rose, N. (2007). The politics of life itself: Biomedicine, power and subjectivity in the twenty-first century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. BLACKMAIL Blackmail occurs when one person threatens another that unless the latter carries out some act, such as paying money or providing some favor for 73 the blackmailer, the blackmailer will reveal information to other people such as family members, friends, or the general public. This information need not concern any criminal act by the person being blackmailed, but will usually be of an embarrassing or socially damaging nature. To succeed, the blackmailer will need information that is substantially true about the blackmailed person and some evidence that the blackmailer can reveal to others, such as tapes, letters, photographs, or video. The wrongness of blackmail and its criminal nature are normally thought to rest on the demand for payment in order not to reveal the information. Criminal prosecutions might themselves end up revealing the information, if not publicly then to the close family or associates of the person blackmailed, and this gives blackmailers advantages insofar as their victims might prefer to pay to keep the blackmailer quiet. In many ways, formally speaking, blackmail looks like many other contracts. One party asks for payment from another for services rendered—in this case to keep information that one has to oneself. There is nothing necessarily wrong with revealing the information itself unless it is considered that revealing the information is done merely to spite or hurt others. And there certainly may be nothing criminally wrong in revealing the information to others. What is paradoxical about blackmail is that it concerns two acts, neither of which is illegal, that combine to make a wrong. Revealing damaging information about a person is not necessarily wrong. Asking payment for services rendered is not necessarily wrong. Why then is the combination of the two wrong? The moral wrongness seems to stem from at least two sources. First, if the person has no reason to reveal the information, then promising not to do so for payment seems to be a form of exploitation. Second, if the person does have a reason to reveal the information—say an individual or the public ought to know this fact—then demanding payment to keep quiet seems wrong. Where the information about the blackmailed person concerns some criminal activity, then blackmail becomes a form of extortion. Here, the blackmailer is also committing a criminal offence in not bringing the information to the authorities and being paid not to do so increases the crime. One form of blackmail is emotional blackmail. This occurs when the blackmailer understands the 74 Blocking Coalition vulnerabilities of the victim and plays on these to get what the blackmailer wants. Emotional blackmail might occur unconsciously on both sides; might involve close family members, lovers, or friends; and often involves withholding love or affection, or threatening to do so if the victim does not act as the emotional blackmailer desires. Emotional blackmail is a form of manipulation, and it is often argued that people with weak personalities or psychological problems are most likely to suffer emotional blackmail and therefore require greater recourse to the law. votes. By looking at the relative frequency of possible blocking coalitions, one can estimate a priori how likely indecision is for any given combination of these two factors. The possibility of a blocking coalition might be the result of procedural rules other than the voting rule. For example, in the United States, Senate decisions are made by simple majority. However, the rule that allows filibusters means that a higher voting threshold may be required to bring a bill to a vote in the first place. Andreas Warntjen Keith Dowding See also Simple Games See also Exploitation; Manipulation Further Readings Further Readings Forward, S., & Frazier, D. (1998). Emotional blackmail: When the people in your life use fear, obligation, and guilt to manipulate you. New York: HarperCollins. Lindgren, J. (1984). Unraveling the paradox of blackmail. Columbia Law Review, 84(3), 670–717. BLOCKING COALITION A blocking coalition comprises a group of voters that collectively can prevent the passage of a proposal. Thus, a blocking coalition exerts negative power. The term is often used in a narrower sense to denote a coalition that can prevent a measure from being passed but cannot muster sufficient votes to pass a proposal. Whether blocking coalitions exist depends on the voting rule. Simple voting games without blocking coalitions are called strong. Under simple majority rule with an odd number of voters, a coalition is either winning or losing but cannot be blocking. In contrast, blocking coalitions can occur if a tie is possible or if a qualified majority is required. For example, the Council of the European Union decides on legislation using a qualified majority or unanimity. In the case of unanimity, any single member state can form a blocking coalition consisting just of itself. Under qualified majority, the number of possible blocking coalitions depends on the voting threshold and the distribution of Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. Ordeshook, P. C. (1986). Game theory and political theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. BOURDIEU, PIERRE (1930–2002) Power, particularly in the form of domination, stands at the core of the work of one of the most important sociologists of the late 20th century, Pierre Bourdieu. Widely recognized for his original contributions to the ethnology of Algeria; to the sociology of education, literature and art, taste, class, language, science, politics, and religion; and to social theory, Bourdieu authored more than 25 books and more than another 30 edited collections of his more than 400 articles, many of which have been translated into more than two dozen languages. He established a network of highly productive scholars around his Center for European Sociology; founded and directed an innovative journal, Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales; and was elected to the chair of sociology at the scholarly prestigious Collège de France in 1981. An International Sociological Association survey ranked Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste (1984) as the sixth most important social scientific work of the 20th century. Bourdieu is arguably the most influential and Bourdieu, Pierre original French sociologist since Émile Durkheim, and at the time of his death, Bourdieu was a leading European public intellectual. For Bourdieu, the analysis of and debunking of power relations should be the central goals of sociology. Bourdieu analyzes power in three overlapping but analytically distinct ways: (1) power in valued resources (capitals), (2) power in specific spheres of struggle (fields), and (3) power in legitimation (symbolic violence). Bourdieu conceptualizes valued resources as capital when they function as social relations of power by becoming objects of struggle. Capitals can be created, accumulated, exchanged, and consumed. His concept of cultural capital is most widely known—particularly in the sociology of education and culture—but his work includes a wide array of capitals, such as social capital, economic capital, academic capital, and statist capital. His view of capital extends the analysis of power to more subtle expressions beyond that of material advantage and physical coercion. Capitals as forms of power exist not in isolation but relationally in what Bourdieu calls fields. Fields denote arenas of production, circulation, and appropriation of goods, services, knowledge, or status, and the competitive positions held by actors in their struggle to accumulate and monopolize different kinds of capital. Field struggle, for Bourdieu, has two distinct dimensions: struggle over the distribution of capitals (i.e., struggle to accumulate the more valued forms of capital or to convert one form into another more valued form) and struggle over the very definition of the most legitimate form of capital for a particular field. One particular power arena Bourdieu emphasizes in his sociology of modern societies is the field of power, which is that arena of struggle among the different power fields (particularly the economic field and the cultural field) for the right to dominate throughout the social order. Bourdieu identifies different subfields within the field of power, such as the artistic field, the administrative field, the university field, the political field, and the economic field. Leaders of particular subfields compete to impose their particular type of capital as the most legitimate claim to authority. For example, artists, writers, and professors compete in the field of power against business leaders to impose their respective capitals 75 (cultural capital vs. economic capital) as the most legitimate. Central to but not synonymous with the field of power is the state, which assumes the key role of regulating the struggle within the field of power. Bourdieu believed the state consists of bureaucratic agencies, authorities, ritual, and ceremony but also official classifications that regulate group relations. The state regulates the classification struggle among social groups by giving some classifications and categories official legitimation and rejecting others. In this regulatory function, the state institutionalizes its own specific form of capital, statist capital, a kind of meta-capital that consecrates and renders official the most legitimate forms of powers. Bourdieu uses the conceptual language of symbolic power, violence, and capital to talk about a third kind of power, a power that legitimates the stratified social order. Following the thought of Max Weber, Bourdieu argues that neither brute force nor material possession is sufficient for the effective exercise of power. Power requires legitimation. The language of symbolic power and violence stresses that legitimate understandings of the social world are imposed by dominant groups and deeply internalized by subordinate groups in the form of practical taken-for-granted understandings. Symbolic power finds expression in everyday classifications, labels, meanings, and categorizations that subtly implement a social as well as symbolic logic of inclusion and exclusion. Symbolic power also finds expression through body language, comportment, self-presentation, bodily care, and adornment. Symbolic violence takes the forms of embodied dispositions—what Bourdieu calls the habitus—that generate a “practical sense” for organizing perceptions of and actions in the social world. The dispositions of habitus incorporate a sense of place in the social order, an understanding of inclusion and exclusion in the various social hierarchies. And symbolic capital designates the social authority that individuals and groups can accumulate through public recognition of their capital holdings and positions occupied in social hierarchies. Two key properties of symbolic power are its naturalization and misrecognition. Bourdieu’s symbolic power does not suggest “consent” but “practical adaptation” to existing hierarchies. The “practical adaptation” occurs pre-reflectively, as if it were the “thing to do,” the “natural” response in existing 76 Bribe Index circumstances. The dominated misperceive the real origins and interests of symbolic power when they adopt the dominant view of the dominant and of themselves. They therefore accept definitions of social reality that do not correspond to their best interests. Those “misrecognized” definitions go unchallenged as appearing natural and justified. These properties of symbolic power help explain how inegalitarian social systems are able to perpetuate without powerful resistance and transformation. Bourdieu’s sociology of symbolic power sensitizes us to the more subtle and influential forms of power that operate through cultural resources and symbolic classifications that interweave everyday life with prevailing institutional arrangements. He identifies a wide variety of valued resources (capitals) beyond sheer economic interests that function as power resources. And his concept of field offers a conceptual language that encourages examination of interrelationships across levels of analysis and analytical units that usually are isolated for specialized focus in empirical research. David L. Swartz See also Agency–Structure Problem; Habitus; Structural Power; Symbolic Power and Violence Further Readings Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A social critique of the judgement of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1979) Bourdieu, P. (1986). The forms of capital. In J. G. Richardson (Ed.), Handbook of theory and research for the sociology of education (pp. 241–258). New York: Greenwood Press. Bourdieu, P. (1996). The state nobility: Elite schools in the field of power. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press. (Original work published 1989) Swartz, D. (1997). Culture and power: The sociology of Pierre Bourdieu. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. BRIBE INDEX A bribe index is an idea introduced by Peter Morriss, following a remark made by Brian Barry that the powerful people in a society must include those whom the U.S. Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) would want to bribe. The intuitive idea is that the extent of their power can be gauged by the amount that they can demand as a bribe. Morriss applied this idea to the development of power indices measuring the power of votes. This discussion abstracts from any consideration the morality or immorality of taking or accepting bribes; all it considers is how much one could charge for one’s vote if votes were for sale. The same idea has been applied to considering what the market value would be of shares in a company, if shares were bought and sold only for purposes of altering the policies of that company. Consider, then, voters who each have different numbers of votes—such as parties in a parliament, states in the U.S. Electoral College, or shareholders at an annual general meeting who each have one vote per share. They are about to make a decision on some matter of public policy. You do not have a vote, but stand to gain $100 if policy X is chosen over the voters’ own preferred outcome. If you know that voter A by himself or herself could deliver policy X, then you would be willing to pay voter A as much as $100 to vote for it. If voter B could increase the probability of policy X being chosen from nothing to 50%, then you would be willing to pay B as much as $50. That shows that A’s votes have twice the value to you that B’s have, which is an indication of A’s greater voting power. Morriss showed how some of the standard power indices can be understood as bribe indices. The Banzhaf index is produced under the constraint that you can bribe any, but only one, voter. But that is only part of the story: for, if you had bribed B first, then you would still want to raise your 50% to 100% by buying up the votes of some others. When you can bribe as many voters as you wish, until your preferred outcome is guaranteed, we get the Shapley–Shubik index. So the Shapley–Shubik index measures the relative worth of votes, and hence their relative power. This has subsequently been shown mathematically by Dan Felsenthal and Moshé Machover. They define P-power as the proportion of a fixed purse (the spoils of victory) each voter could obtain for himself or herself. This is the same as what the voter could deliver to an outside briber and is represented by the Shapley–Shubik index. Peter Morriss Bull, Hedley See also Banzhaf Value; Barry, Brian; Morriss, Peter; P-Power; Shapley–Shubik Index; Voting Power Further Readings Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power: Theory and practice, problems and paradoxes. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. Morriss, P. (2002). Power: A philosophical analysis (2nd ed.). Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. BUDGET-MAXIMIZING BUREAUCRATS Budget maximization is put forward as an aim and practice of bureaucrats operating in a nonmarket context who are often able to exert informational or agenda-setting power. Sometimes these practices result in oversupply or other undesirable outcomes. Whereas Gordon Tullock and Anthony Downs had previously discussed aspects of budget maximization, it was most comprehensively developed by William Niskanen in 1971. In Niskanen’s model, a bilateral monopoly exists between a sponsor and a bureau. He famously claims, Among the several variables that may enter the bureaucrat’s utility function are the following: salary, prerequisites of the office, public reputation, power, patronage, output of the bureau, ease of making changes and ease of managing the bureau. All of these variables except the last two, I contend, are a positive monotonic function of the total budget of the bureau during the bureaucrat’s tenure in office. (Niskanen, 1971, p. 38) However, Niskanen also states that officials are able to push up budgets only through the production of more output for the sponsor, making the model one of budget/output maximization rather than just budget maximization. In the context of the bureau being able to offer take-it-or-leave-it outcomes for the sponsor, the budget tends to be expanded beyond the point where marginal public benefits equal marginal costs to a point where all the consumer surplus gains are balanced by the 77 excess of marginal cost over marginal benefits. This “oversupply” result has been an influential critique of bureaucratic supply of services, especially in the late 1970s given concerns about the growth of the public sector. Keith Dowding, however, has noted the difficulty of comparing outputs from markets and political processes, using a common framework that potentially limits the force of the critique. The concept of budget-maximizing has been extended and altered in many ways, and there have been many empirical tests of this family of models. Taking some examples: the take-it-or-leave-it agenda-setting power of the bureau has been replaced with a unit price or price schedule. Alternative behavioral assumptions have been posited, notably budget-slack maximization rather than budget/output maximization. A trade-off between benefits from spending time managing a budget and undertaking alternative, and desirable, policy work activity has been suggested—resulting in bureau-shaping as well as budget-maximizing activity. Overall, the literature suggests that the agenda-setting power of bureaucrats can facilitate budget maximization and that sponsors are often able to use better monitoring and competitive pressures to limit its extent. Oliver James See also Bureaucratic Power; Public Goods Further Readings Dowding, K. M. (1995). The civil service. London: Routledge. Dunleavy, P. (1991). Democracy, bureaucracy and public choice. Hemel Hempstead, UK: Harvester Wheatsheaf. James, O. (2003). The executive agency revolution in Whitehall: Public interest versus bureau-shaping strategies. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Niskanen, W. A. (1971). Bureaucracy and representative government. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton. BULL, HEDLEY (1932–1985) Hedley Bull was one of most acute and originalminded of the Australian scholars who have 78 Bull, Hedley worked in the field of international theory and strategic analysis. He came from a reasonably comfortable Sydney family, and his high intellectual capacity was recognized early in his life. He was admitted as a student to the University of Sydney at the age of 16 in 1949. While there, he concentrated on philosophy and history and was strongly influenced by the most controversial of his professors at the time, John Anderson. Bull remained an “Andersonian” all his life. He was also influenced by one of his history professors, Ernest Bramstead, whose vision of world history was largely focused on Europe. Hedley Bull graduated with first-class honors in philosophy and second-class honors in history in 1952, and was accorded a scholarship to Oxford University. There, he continued to pursue those subjects, eventually to a master of philosophy degree. Quite unexpectedly, because he had taken no courses in the subject, he was offered an assistant lectureship at London School of Economics and Political Science (LSE) in international relations. The professor at the time, Charles Manning, looked for original minds in his young appointees, and Hedley Bull certainly offered that. At LSE, Bull found the second great intellectual influence of his life in Martin Wight, then reader in the International Relations department. Wight was an immensely charismatic teacher, remarkable for the depth of his learning and the elegance of his analysis. Moreover, London in the mid-1950s offered an immense stimulus to someone of Bull’s originality of mind. Policy makers, even at the level of prime minister, were beginning to understand the immensity of the dangers that the acquisition of nuclear weapons by several powers represented for the whole world. So the old interest in disarmament reappeared, and Hedley Bull was invited to assist one of its stalwarts from the 1930s, Philip Noel-Baker, to produce a new book on the subject. During his research on that project, however, Bull found himself convinced the earlier approach to the subject was mistaken and unproductive, and in due course, he produced a book of his own, The Control of the Arms Race, which suggested a new approach to the overall objective of keeping the peace. The English authorities in the field, such as Michael Howard, had recently founded a new institute, the Institute for Strategic Studies (ISS) and were instantly impressed when the book was produced for its 1960 conference at Oxford University. So when Harold Wilson became prime minister in 1964 and was looking for a new mind to head the Arms Control and Disarmament Research Unit at the Foreign Office, Bull was appointed. He stayed in that appointment until 1967, then accepted a chair in international relations at Australian National University (ANU). By that time, Bull’s main intellectual interests had focused on the general theory of international politics. In Canberra, he wrote his best-known and most influential book, The Anarchical Society. In that book, he continued his English School realist analysis of international relations, likening the international scene to a Hobbesian state of nature where anarchy prevails, kept in check by alliances and reciprocal agreements. States form a system when they interact in this manner to form a society with some common organizations where they see common interests. One can see in that notable work the influence of two associations, the ISS, and a much smaller group, the British Association for International Theory. In the years at ANU, Hedley’s interests also expanded further, to be concerned particularly with the relationship between the old established powers of the West and the rising powers of Asia, especially China and India. That subject was central to his last two works, The Expansion of International Society, and Intervention in World Politics. In 1977, he was appointed to a chair in International Relations at Oxford and would have continued to pursue that line of analysis, had he lived longer. But he died early, at 52, much mourned by friends and colleagues. Coral Bell See also Anarchism, Power in; Hobbes, Thomas; Realism in International Relations; Wight, Martin Further Readings Bull, H. (1977). The anarchical society. London: Macmillan. Miller, J. D. B., & Vincent, R. J. (Eds.). (1990). Order and violence: Hedley Bull and international relations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Business and Power BUREAUCRACY See Bureaucratic Power BUREAUCRATIC POWER Bureaucracy, defined as “rule by the bureau,” entails the power of career officials in large organizations and can be considered a form of government. Max Weber defined the bureaucratic organizational form as allocation of competencies within a hierarchical body, continuity of office, impersonality of treatment, working according to rules, and expertise entailing selection by merit and training. Bureaucratic power comes from authority vested in particular positions and technical expertise acquired through training and official sources of information available only through administrative channels. A further form of ideational power arises from the domination of a bureaucratic mind-set, an “iron cage” of reason, permeating from the bureaucracy across society. Bureaucratic power limits political elites’ capacity for control, and limits individuals’ freedom in society. Weber saw multiple sources of power in society, oversight by Parliament, and effective political leadership as ways of curbing bureaucratic power, and his work contains a critique of socialism as empowering bureaucracy both by creating more of it and removing countervailing forces. In contrast, Marxists see bureaucratic power emanating primarily from class power. In contemporary research on public organizations within the liberal democratic state, most attention focuses on power relations between the bureaucracy and elected politicians, citizens, interest groups, and others, and on the blurred boundaries between “politics” and “administration.” Bureaucrats exercise discretion in implementing laws, make secondary laws in areas delegated to them, and exert influence through advice—particularly to politicians. Multiple stakeholders are variously seen as constraining bureaucracies’ autonomy or enabling bureaucrats to use conflicting demands to exercise greater autonomy. Policy development often involves complex learning in networks across public and private boundaries, 79 with bureaucrats sharing power with other actors. Research has examined political control and delegation to bureaucracies, including the role legislatures play in this activity and bureaucratic “regulatory” oversight of other parts of the bureaucracy. Sources of power from personal and professional positions, as well as from formal bureaucratic posts, have been noted, especially the discretion of street-level bureaucrats in public services involving direct contact with citizens. Challenges to bureaucratic power from the use of competitive quasi-markets, private sector contractors, and target regimes have been a focus of recent research. Oliver James See also Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrats; Public Goods Further Readings Beetham, D. (1987). Bureaucracy. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press. Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society (Vols. 1 & 2; G. Roth & C. Wittich, Eds.) Berkeley: University of California Press. BUSINESS AND POWER When people think about the power of business or “big business,” they often think of the way in which business in the form of major companies, corporations, and major firms dominate the lives of their employees, the communities in which they are located, and government. Business power in this sense comes in several different, though often subtly related, forms. We consider each in turn. Obviously business affects the lives of employees and their families. The livelihood of the workforce and their families depends on their employers. This immediately makes for a complex relationship between employees and the business that employs them. On the one hand, the managers of the firm, following the interests of the owners or shareholders, want to get as much from each employee as possible for as little as possible to maximize profits. This does not necessarily mean paying as low a wage as possible for the job to be done; managers 80 Business and Power can realize that giving incentives to workers in the form of better pay and working conditions can maximize output and revenue. Nevertheless, the workers have an interest in higher wages and less control, whereas their managers have an interest in reducing the overall wage bill and getting as much output at possible. On the other hand, the workers also should have an interest in the business being profitable. Otherwise, it might go out of business, leaving them unemployed; so workers do share interests with stockholders. It is not enough merely for a firm to keep in profit. Listed companies can be subject to hostile takeover bids where other businesses believe that their profits are not being maximized. Hostile takeovers often lead to reductions in the workforce, the closure of some factories or offices, harsher terms of employment, and so forth, in the attempt to get more profit from the capital stock than the current company manages. At this level, the interests of stockholders and workers diverge, or at least the interests of some of the workers and stockholders diverge. In some communities, interest in the firm staying in business goes beyond the workforce and workers’ immediate families. In some “company towns” the entire economy is dominated by the local business. Here, the livelihood of everyone is at stake if the firm goes out of business. Other local companies’ business depends on the company’s contracts, and the entire local economy of shops, service agencies, and so on, depends on the company’s employees spending their money locally. And the local government depends on the business for taxes both directly and through any local income tax or sales tax that is generated by that business. This gives the company enormous influence over the lives of everyone. This local power comes in various forms. First, local power comes about directly. Because the firm is vital to the welfare of everyone, if its managers state that certain local policies are important to its continued existence—whether they claim competitive pressures or pressures from some corporate headquarters elsewhere, even in another country—then local politicians are likely to acquiesce. Thus, if a company wants some land rezoned to allow it to build a factory extension, the local community is likely to facilitate this. Or if company owners are concerned with local environmental laws affecting the company’s profit line, the company might be able to have the laws changed. In a classic book from the 1970s, The Unpolitics of Air Pollution, Matthew Crenson was able to demonstrate that towns dominated by a single business had lower environmental controls than did similar towns less dominated by one company. It is not simply that firms can force their interests on recalcitrant local communities; rather, the power relationship is more subtle. The local community also sees these policies in their interests in the sense that the company sustains the local economy. If it is true that the company “must leave” without the rezoning or relaxing of environmental controls, then it is true that those policies are in the community’s interests too, even if, in some sense, the community wants clean air, does not want the land rezoned, and so on. Such issues sometimes take the form of collective action problems. The power of local business can stand as a metaphor for the power of business more broadly both at the national level and in the international arena. Here the power of business can take at least five forms: to define the agenda; to gain disproportionate benefits from the political process; for elected and civil officials to pander to the interests of business; the superior ability of business to mobilize political resources; and finally, underlying the first four types, the overarching system of capitalism that privileges business interests above others. Business can define the agenda of government. With free-flowing international capital, governments are severely constrained in how they can regulate business over tax policy and even over social or welfare legislation. Politicians fear the effects of their announced policies on share prices; they fear businesses relocating to countries with more favorable regulatory and tax policies. With corporate business deciding what is best for the politicians, corporations define the very agenda by which national governments operate. Business can gain disproportionate benefits from the democratic process. Beyond their privileged or systematically lucky situation, big businesses can threaten governments. Politicians fear disinvestment and design policy accordingly, but businesspeople can also ask for tax breaks, for relaxation of regulatory controls, or directly or Business and Power indirectly threaten that some proposed laws would make them reconsider their investment in a given location. In doing so, businesses can gain much more from the democratic legislative process than the votes they command. Business can also capture regulatory bodies. Often health and safety legislation comes from business itself, rather than from consumer or health groups’ demands. Stricter legislation can make current products obsolete, forcing consumers to buy the latest products, while making it more difficult for new entrants to the market. In an important article, Jacob Hacker and Paul Pierson demonstrated that the structural power or systematic luck of business is not a constant. Although companies’ influence depends on the fear of disinvestment, that fear can be reduced at certain times. Hacker and Pierson show that the Great Depression of the 1930s enabled government to bring in welfare reform as the power of business momentarily waned. The global financial crisis 81 that began in late 2008 demonstrated the power of the financial sector as governments rushed to bail out major investment banks deemed too big to fail, and it provided a window of opportunity for governments to introduce stricter regulation of financial institutions. Keith Dowding See also Capture Theory of Regulation; Free Market; Globalization; Growth Coalitions; Neoliberalism; Relative Autonomy of the State; Structural Power; Systematic Luck; Systemic Power Further Readings Hacker, J. S., & Pierson, P. (2002). Business and social policy: Employers and the formation of the American welfare state. Policy and Politics, 30, 277–325. Vogel, D. (1989). Fluctuating fortunes: The political power of business in America. New York: Basic Books. C they are remembered. They were united only because they all signed the Treaty of Dover of 1670 and its renewal in 1672 (a pact to support French policy to subjugate the Netherlands in return for a subsidy that helped free Charles from financial dependence on parliament); only Clifford and Arlington knew of the Secret Treaty of Dover (concerned with converting England to Roman Catholicism). Parliament did not like these secret advisors and eventually pressed for the whole Privy Council to meet, which did not happen until the end of the 1670s. CABAL A cabal is a private meeting of a group of people, usually to conspire against someone or something, and normally carrying a sinister interpretation. Thus, intrigues against the monarch or the state are termed cabals. Sometimes the leaders of parties will denounce some faction or group as a cabal secretly conspiring against the leadership. The term carries far more negative connotations than do faction, coalition, or party. The word cabal derives originally from cabbala or kabbalah, a Hebrew word denoting a centuriesold esoteric tradition of Jewish biblical interpretation associated with “secret” learning or mystical interpretations of Hebrew scripture. Thus, the term cabal carries anti-Semitic overtones of a “Jewish conspiracy” against the state or against current orthodox (Christian or moral) doctrines. The term cabal also came to prominence politically because of the so-called CABAL ministry of Charles II of England, deriving from the names of five privy councilors: Sir Thomas Clifford, Lord Arlington, the Duke of Buckingham, Lord AshleyCooper, and Lord Lauderdale. Charles II was known to pursue his own ends while appearing to defer to parliament, and only a few trusted members of the Privy Council—the body of parliament that advised the king—might be aware of these inner machinations. The five members of the CABAL were the most famous of this inner circle of ministers, though the fact that their initial letters could be arranged to spell cabal is probably why Keith Dowding See also Coalition Theory Further Readings Macintosh, J. P. (1977). The British cabinet (3rd ed.). London: Stevens and Sons. CAPABILITY Capability is the core concept of the capability approach, which is a broad normative framework for the evaluation of individual well-being and social arrangements, and the development of policies and social change. The central claim of the capability approach is that these evaluations and proposals should rely on an analysis of the (expected) changes in the capabilities of individuals 83 84 Capital, Marxist or groups. Although the precise terminology has changed a little over time, the most widely used description of capability is the real opportunity or freedom to be the person one wants to be and do the things one wants to do. These beings and doings are called functionings. The expansion of people’s capabilities is the central normative goal of the human development approach, which is best known from the human development reports that are published annually by the United Nations Development Programme. The concept of power is relevant for the capability approach in two ways. The first is at the ontological level: the concept of capability refers to human power. In ordinary language, capability refers to an undeveloped or unused faculty of a human being, without reference to his or her environment. In this sense, capability is a human power. However, this is not how “capability” is conceptualized in the capability approach. Martha Nussbaum explains that the philosophical–technical “capability” has three components: (1) the innate capabilities such as the capability for speech and language, (2) the internal capabilities that are the developed states of the person himself or herself, and (3) the external conditions that are needed for the exercise of the functioning. If all three components are present, a person is said to have a capability. Having a capability thus implies having the necessary internal powers, but goes beyond them by stressing the external conditions too. If we rephrase this in terms of the concepts of ability and ableness, then the notion of capability corresponds to the notion of ableness because it is not just about our abilities to do what we can do and be the person we can be, but also about the right external conditions that enable us to fulfill our abilities should we wish to do so. Power plays a second, and rather different, role in the capability approach. Structures and relations of power in society, organizations, and human interactions influence the capability sets of individuals. Yet, some argue that by shifting the focus of analysis from the determinants of people’s quality of life to a discussion of what precisely entails that quality of life, a capability analysis is insufficiently able to analyze these power structures. Stated differently, critics assert that the capability approach would focus too much on conceptualizing, evaluating, and measuring people’s well-being, thereby losing sight of the political and economic analysis of the causal factors that determine wellbeing, including structures of power. Ingrid Robeyns See also Ability; Ableness; Distributive Justice; Freedom; Opportunity Further Readings Nussbaum, M. (2000). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Knopf. CAPITAL, MARXIST Generally speaking, capital is any asset that can potentially be used as a source of income. In academic literature, it has been categorized far more extensively, especially in Karl Marx’s economic writings. Marx does not see capital as a thing, that is, as an inanimate object, but rather as a series of socioeconomic relations that appear thing-like. Along with capitalism’s key features of the private ownership of the means of production, wagelabor, and a market economy, Marx insists that capitalism, as a finite mode of production, is characterized chiefly by the production and exchange of commodities. Central to his class-based inquiry into political economy is an analysis of the valueextending process, the role of constant and variable capital, an account of concrete and abstract labor, the crucial distinction between socially necessary labor and surplus labor, and the circulation of capital. For Marx, value is a social relation that assumes a particular material form. Capitalist social relations exhibit value relations in the form of commodities. Commodities are intended to be exchanged, so they have an exchangeability feature that he argues is its value. In quantitative terms, use values of various kinds are exchanged for each other. Commodities therefore are bearers of use and exchange values. As each particular product can be differentiated from others, the use Capital, Marxist values of commodities are qualitatively distinct. Yet the values of commodities are equal in qualitative terms; they vary in the magnitude of value they embody. So in one key respect they must possess an identical magnitude. The homogeneous property that commodities share is that they are all produced by labor. On this analysis, value is the objectification of labor, and this value appears as the exchange value of commodities. That is, value is expressed as exchange value. So for Marx, the magnitude of exchange value is not determined quantitatively by use value. He held that the time workers spend creating value, measured by hours in the working day, has two parts: necessary labor, time at work in which workers produce an equivalent in the wages needed to meet personal consumption; and surplus labor, where the remaining hours are worked for the benefit of the capitalist. The measure of value is accounted for by establishing the amount of labor, calculated through hours of the day, that is required to produce a given commodity. To summarize, the substance of value is objectified (abstract) labor, and the measure of value is socially necessary labor. Marx draws a distinction between constant and variable capital. The former is the value of the means of production embodied in the product during the process of production; it is termed constant because it does not engender any quantitative alteration of value in the process of production. The latter is capital used to hire labor power, it is termed variable because it alone holds the capacity to create value; its quantity changes during the productive process—from the value of labor power to the value it produces, and the difference between the two is surplus value. Commodities have use value as well as exchange value, so the labor that produces them must also have a twofold character. The labor with a “definite aim” (Capital, vol. 1, ch. 1) is concrete labor, which is of a particular kind and produces a use value. The labor analyzed without its particular attributes, as simply the expenditure of labor power in general, is termed abstract labor—this labor is the source of the value of commodities. With these points in mind, it can now be appreciated how Marx tries to capture the flow of capital by contrasting two sequences of market transactions. First, at the most immediate level, exchange is commodity circulation, C (commodities)—M 85 (money)—C (commodities) (Capital, vol. 1, ch. 3, sec. 2a): commodities exchanged for money that is used to buy other commodities. Second, where commodities are brought to be sold, M—C—M¹ (general formula of capital, Capital, vol. 1, ch. 4), the intention being that M¹ is a greater amount than M. Marx argues that because value is not actually created in the sphere of exchange, there must be a factor of production that has a use value capable of adding extra value to its initial expenditure. This particular commodity is labor power. Labor power is not just labor, but the capacity to labor. The labor increases the value of commodities. Labor power does, therefore, have a use value—its unique capability to create new value when consumed in the productive process. Marx believes the distinction he made between labor and labor power is vital to the understanding of capitalist political economy. Capitalism, he infers, is based on the unstated yet omnipresent reality that labor power produces more, in value terms, than the cost of reproducing labor power. To elaborate, labor power is exchanged for a wage, and the commodities it produces are then sold for a value that exceeds the overall value of inputs. These total inputs are the value of labor power combined with the value of the materials consumed in the process of production. The series of transactions in C—M—C captures the selling of labor power for a paid wage, by which the necessary commodities are brought to reproduce workers. The series of relations in M—C—M¹ constitutes the capitalists’ inputs that are transformed into outputs of greater value. As M¹ is money plus surplus value, the full formula of capital is M[C & LP & MP] . . . P . . . C¹—M¹ M and M¹ are money capital; C is productive capital, in the form of labor power (LP) and the means of production (MP); C¹ represents commodity capital; and P is the actual process of production in which the inputs (LP & MP) are transformed into outputs, which by now have a greater value (C¹). Marx distinguishes between the productive sphere, in which surplus value is created, and the financial sphere within which commodities are exchanged. These two spheres of activity represent the circulation of capital, within which the value of capital is subject to a series of transformations 86 Capital, Neoclassical through which it expands, assuming different forms at various stages. As the sphere of circulation creates no value, an analysis of value expansion in production, capital’s essence, must precede a consideration of the circulation of value, capital’s appearance. Crucially, the assets that expand capital stem from propertied relations in which only a minority own the accumulated wealth embodied in productive resources; therefore, this class holds real power. As non-owners of the means of production, the workers cannot make use of labor power’s value, they possess no such power; only by selling their labor power can workers gain access to the means of production. Here, in the sphere of production, capital exploits labor through the extraction of surplus value. The rate of surplus value/exploitation is the amount of surplus produced over the variable capital laid out. So for Marx, workers create a relation that exploits them, they create the capital that fundamentally shapes the labor process and reproduces the capital/labor relation. In sum, capital for Marx is value in motion, a social relation attached to things such as money and commodities. Marx’s critical analysis of capital has been the subject of prolonged critical appraisals. Most notably, it has been suggested that value as embodied labor has an insufficient treatment of demand. Further, if value is not labor exclusively, the labor theory of value cannot adequately explain empirical prices. Further still, as even Marxist sympathizers such as John Elster have acknowledged, if only some labor is irreducibly heterogeneous, then the labor theory of value is seriously impaired. In response, although labor may not be the only variable, it remains analytically unique because it alone is required for all systems of production. As such, no account of value can ignore labor. Also, wherever there is an unequal ownership of productive assets, labor values remain a powerful tool in considerations of exploitation. In either of these cases, all the time capital as inherent self-expanding tendency exists; Marx’s economic writings will continue to provide, for both critics and proponents, a focal reference point. Chris Wyatt See also Exploitation; False Consciousness; Ideology; Marx, Karl; Marxist Accounts of Power; Substructure and Superstructure Further Readings Eldred, M., & Roth, M. (1978). Guide to Marx’s Capital. London: CSE Books. Elster, J. (1985). Making sense of Marx. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Fine, B. (1975). Marx’s Capital. London: Macmillan. Howard, M., & King, J. (1975). The political economy of Marx. London: Longman. Marx, K. (1967). Capital (3 vols.). New York: International Publishers. CAPITAL, NEOCLASSICAL In the neoclassical tradition of economics, capital simply means any human-made means of production. Capital goods are products that are made to be used in the productive process. The term includes natural assets but their worth or value is given in terms of the use that might be made of them in a productive process. Thus, the capital value of a piece of land might increase as the potential for its use changes (through new techniques or legal arrangements, for example). Most firms will monitor capital consumption (i.e., the amount of capital that is used up in the productive process) and capital investment (investment in new means of production that might increase output and profits). An important difference between capital as ordinarily understood and human capital and social capital is that the latter two cannot be bought and sold in the same way. Human capital is the value of a person within production. The amount of capital that resides in a person is usually thought to depend on the amount of education and training the person has received. The more experienced a person and the more transferable his or her skills, the higher the person’s capital value and the greater the rewards he or she should be able to command in the employment market. However, wages and salaries often depend on noncapital assets such as gender, ethnicity, or contacts. Social capital has several meanings, but in this context, it usually means the amount of value inherent in a person given his or her contacts. If one has a set of friends or relatives who can help secure employment, then one’s social capital is higher than that of others lacking such contacts. Capture Theory of Regulation Sometimes being a member of a particular ethnic group might bring contacts within a specific industry where that group is heavily represented. Again, education might increase an individual’s capital through the networks he or she has made. Here, it might not be the precise level of education that is important but the school or university one has attended. This might create a set of networks both through contemporaries at the school and through alumni. The more capital a person has the more powerful the person might be; he or she is able to bargain for or buy more. Similarly, we might expect the greater the capital holdings of a firm relative to its debts and commitments, the more powerful it might be in relation to other firms and organizations. However, in neoclassical economics, the term power is rarely used. In contexts where power might be used, it is replaced by the resources of the agent. In other words, power is reduced to the agent’s capital in the three forms mentioned here. In that sense, within economics, capital is a measure of an agent’s (a person, a firm, or other collective entity) power (or power to). Or at least, capital is the measure of what an agent can bring to any contractual or bargaining situation. A second important meaning of the term capital is in terms of financial stocks. The stocks can provide an income through interest payments. In this sense, the capital of a firm is the initial amount of money with which it started plus the profits it has retained subsequently. This capital can be spent on future capital goods, held as balances, or used for credit. The capital market is the system through which firms gain capital in this financial sense. Firms sell shares to investors who may be paid dividends, perhaps annually, or can sell those shares for profit as the reputation of the firm increases their value. This capital appreciation is simply the increase in the value of the firm’s capital. Keith Dowding See also Capital, Marxist; Small Worlds, Power in; Social Capital Further Readings Becker, G. (1975). Human capital. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 87 Colman, J. S. (1988). Social capital in the creation of human capital. American Journal of Sociology: Supplementary Volume, 94, S95–S120. CAPTURE THEORY REGULATION OF The capture theory of regulation was first developed by the economist and 1982 Nobel laureate George Stigler. Regulation of industry is generally thought to be a government function designed to protect consumers by setting safety standards and ensuring good practice in production processes and sometimes through price regulation. Stigler and the public choice school suggest that regulators are often “captured” by the firms and industry they regulate and produce regulatory practices that are in the interests of the industry rather than the consumer. Although consumers want safe products and low cost, firms also have an interest in regulation, first to keep out competitors and second to build obsolescence into their products. If firms within an industry are protected from competition from new entrants, then they can charge higher prices. Firms have an incentive to lobby regulators to write regulations that will discourage new entrants into the industry, thus allowing established firms to act as a cartel. One way of discouraging new entrants is to have complex regulations. Furthermore, if the safety standards of products, such as gas boilers or cars, are continually being upgraded then the industry builds obsolescence into its products, ensuring a continual demand for new versions. Sam Peltzman’s model for capture theory reflects the competition between firms and consumers for the attention of politicians and state regulators. Consumers have voting power, and can demand the type of regulations they desire through the ballot box. Firms within an industry have a concentrated and high financial stake. Thus, they are prepared to spend large amounts of money lobbying regulators and politicians. Firms are also a source of expertise for the bureaucrats. Politicians will support consumer demands to the extent of their vote power, but financial contributions from industry to politicians can also buy vote power. Furthermore, consumer interests are diffuse—they 88 Carr, E. H. make many demands on politicians—whereas the industry interests are concentrated. Thus, consumers face a greater collective action problem than do producers. This can lead to industry capture. Examples of capture found in the literature include the commercial airline industry in the United States. The Civil Aeronautics Board controlled price competition but allowed airlines to compete on non-price frills such as in-flight entertainment. After deregulation in the 1970s, the Federal Aviation Administration was also accused of aiding airlines rather than consumers. The U.S. Food and Drug Administration has been accused of acting in the interests of pharmaceutical, agricultural, and health industries at the expense of consumers. The European Union is also accused of acting in the interests of industry rather than consumers. There has been a great deal of headline deregulation, which seems to undermine capture theory. However, bureaucracies do continue to regulate in quiet and unspectacular ways. It is difficult to judge how far these regulations really work in the interests of consumers and how far in those of the industries regulated. However, given the greater bargaining power of industry, the suspicion will always be that regulations exist for industry rather than consumers. Keith Dowding See also Business and Power; Collective Action Problem Further Readings Peltzman. S. (1976). Towards a more general theory of regulation. Journal of Law and Economics, 19, 211–240. Stigler, G. R. (1971). The theory of economic regulation. Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 2, 137–146. CARR, E. H. (1892–1992) Edward Hallett (E. H.) Carr was one of the most brilliant British international relations scholars of the 20th century, and his strident views caused much controversy. He began his career as a diplomat in 1916, resigning in 1936 to become Woodrow Wilson Professor of International Relations at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. Carr became interested in the Soviet Union as a diplomat, having been assigned in 1917 to the Northern desk that included dealings with Russia. He became convinced in 1919 that the Bolsheviks would win the Russian civil war and believed that for reasons of realpolitik Britain should not support anti-Bolshevik forces. At this time, he had little sympathy with Marxism or the Bolsheviks. One of his early books, Karl Marx: A Study in Fanaticism (1931), was, as its title suggests, so far from being an apologia for Marxism as to cause him some later embarrassment; though from the depths of the 1930s Depression he thought it difficult to completely dismiss Marx’s view that capitalism contained the seeds of its own destruction. Also during the early 1930s, Carr started to sympathize with the Soviet Union, largely because he admired Soviet efforts to industrialize and become a modern civilization. Carr started writing about Soviet and other international affairs in the 1930s, reviewing books and contributing articles to various journals. He argued that the Nazi regime was caused by the Treaty of Versailles and the intractable attitude of France and the other Western powers. His book The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939 (1939) defended appeasement as the only realistic policy. He attacked utopians who believed the League of Nations could provide a new international order. For these views, Carr became known as a realist thinker, though he also recognized that realism lacks goals and grounds for action. In Carr’s work, we can discern three important differences between realism and utopianism. First, utopians want a world of peace but do not consider the constraints on action properly. The realists understand that the world we live in is the product of a long chain of causation. Second, utopians derive their conclusions about what should be done from theory; realists from practice. For the realists, theory is derived from reality. Third, utopians tend to be intellectuals with book learning; realists tend to be diplomats and those who actually operate in the world of international relations. Finally, the utopian believes that ethics should guide policy, the realist that ethics is derived from power relations as they currently stand. Cartwright, Dorwin Making these distinctions, one can see how Marxism came to appeal to Carr, given his views on realism. Carr argued that the troubled times of the mid20th century were caused by structural political– economic problems and should not be blamed on individual people who lacked morals. He believed that differences between nations were best traced to the “haves” and “have-nots,” those with power in international affairs and those without, and not to democracies and nondemocracies. During World War II, Carr’s ideological views shifted to the left and his interest in the Soviet Union became admiration, reflected in leader columns he wrote for The Times. Immediately after the war, he argued that Western civilization was a sham and that totalitarian societies were more likely to succeed. Communist totalitarianism was the most successful and had the most progressive social and economic policies. His interest in communism and the Soviet Union led him to start his monumental 14-volume history of the Soviet Union, the first volume of which appeared in 1950 and the last in 1978. It still stands as an important work in Sovietology, though many commentators argue that Carr takes at face value far too many claims from Soviet sources that do not bear closer empirical scrutiny. These days Carr is best remembered for his short book derived from a series of Cambridge lectures entitled What Is History? that has become a key text in historiography. It is relativist in that it argues both that our morality has changed over time and that history is understood in terms of our own morality. Carr also argues against the idea of contingency in historical understanding, arguing instead for a strong form of determinism. Keith Dowding See also Agency; Agency–Structure Problem; Appeasement; League of Nations; Marx, Karl; Marxist Accounts of Power; Realism in International Relations Further Readings Cox, M. (Ed.). (2000). E. H. Carr: A critical appraisal. London: Palgrave. Jones, C. (1998). E. H. Carr and international relations: A duty to lie. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 89 CARTWRIGHT, DORWIN (1915–2008) Dorwin Cartwright, in his presidential address to the Society for the Psychological Study of Social Issues, noted that social power, long the prerogative of political scientists and philosophers, was a sadly neglected variable in social psychology. As director of the Research Center for Group Dynamics, he encouraged and coordinated his colleagues and other social psychologists in clarifying and exploring the dynamics of social power. On completing his doctoral studies at Harvard University in 1940, Cartwright accepted a postdoctoral fellowship at Iowa State University with Kurt Lewin, who was well known for his work in field theory. When the United States became an active participant in World War II, Cartwright accepted an appointment from Rensis Likert to move to Washington, D.C., to join Likert’s research program in evaluating opinions, attitudes, and behavior related to the war effort. Cartwright’s first major assignment was to conduct a series of national surveys evaluating the effectiveness of war bond drives. Related studies of group discussion and group decision indicated that, beyond informational appeals, the power of the group could play an important role in changing food habits, such as encouraging housewives to serve nutritious but less popular cuts of meat to help alleviate the wartime meat shortage. Later research indicated that in similar fashion, work group productivity could also be increased. After Lewin’s untimely death in 1947, Cartwright assumed directorship of the Research Center for Group Dynamics, which Lewin had established at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and coordinated its relocation to the University of Michigan. There, Cartwright edited Field Theory in Social Science, a collection of important articles by Kurt Lewin. Cartwright also edited Studies in Social Power, which opened with his presidential address to the Society for the Psychological Study of Social Issues and included a series of theoretical works and experiments. His concluding chapter proposed a field theoretical conception of social power. Though the term social power was indeed neglected by social psychologists, many relevant 90 Caste System (India) variables had been investigated. This became more clear once social power was defined as the ability or potential of an influencing agent (O) to influence a change in a target (P). A substantial body of research on social influence on attitudes, beliefs, emotions, and behavior could now be examined in terms of the potential for such influence—social power. The studies of group norms and group decisions, as in the studies of food habits, or group decisions affecting level of worker productivity (John R. P. French and Lester Coch), represented the power of the group. Leadership could then be considered in terms of social power—the manner in which a leader might use his or her available resources to affect the beliefs and behavior of followers. Kurt Lewin, Ronald Lippitt, and Ralph White illustrated this conception of power in experiments on effectiveness of democratic, autocratic, and laissez-faire leadership. Field studies of the way behavior patterns spread among boys in a camp setting (Ronald Lippitt, Norman Polanski, and Sidney Rosen) could be also be understood in terms of social power relationships. John R. P. French and Bertram Raven, as part of the Research Center for Group Dynamics program coordinated by Cartwright, developed their widely cited analysis of the bases of social power. Though Cartwright’s research and theory on social power were important in their own right, he is even better known for his significant role as an integrating force for social psychologists and others working in disparate areas, encouraging rigor in research and theory with applications to important social problems and issues. Bertram H. Raven See also Bases of Power; French, John R. P., Jr.; Lewin, Kurt, and Power; Raven, Bertram Further Readings Cartwright, D. (1959). A field theoretical conception of power. In D. Cartwright (Ed.), Studies in social power (pp. 183–220). Ann Arbor, MI: Institute for Social Research. Cartwright, D. (1959). Power: A neglected variable in social psychology. In D. Cartwright (Ed.), Studies in social power (pp. 1–14). Ann Arbor, MI: Institute for Social Research. CASTE SYSTEM (INDIA) The traditional view of caste system in India is largely associated with the rituals and practices of Hindus, wherein social stratification is explained and justified in terms of purity and pollution. The concepts of purity and pollution are complex, but in general are interpreted in terms of deeds, occupation, language, dress patterns, and food habits. One can also distinguish between timed pollution—at birth and death—and internal and external pollution, which originates from either a polluting action or an object, and thus, there is a connection between ritual purity and matters of hygiene and sanitation. The caste system is an ancient institution with its origin in religious ideology; the social, economic, and political organization of the village; and rituals and traditions that evolved over centuries. The system is usually used to describe the whole varna-jati system where varna is a design to organize society, and jati refers to communities and subcommunities often identified with their respective job functions. There are four varnas—Brahman, Kshatriya, Vaishya, and Shudra—which represent the functional hierarchy among Hindus within the caste system. D. L. Sheth cites a 16th-century empirical work of Portuguese writer and trader Duarte Barbosa who identified caste in India as a hierarchy with the ritually purest Brahmans at the top and Shudras (untouchables) at the bottom; untouchability as linked to the idea of pollution; separation of castes by endogamy, occupation, and commensality; application of sanctions by castes to maintain customs and rules; and relationship of caste with the political organization. Although the traditional varna hierarchy has diminished over the years, and untouchability was abolished after India’s independence in 1947, a large number of jatis, despite having undergone changes over time, continue to have an important place and identity in the social structure of India. During British colonial rule in India, caste was seen in terms of local hierarchies that were embedded in the religious and cultural context of a region. By the end of British rule, the caste system had undergone many changes in the horizontal organization of castes occupying a similar location in different local hierarchies, and development of a Caste System (India) collective identity among lower castes that led them to question the traditional caste hierarchy through the modern ideas of justice and equality. During the first two decades after India’s independence, the Congress Party evolved a stable electoral base across castes by expressing political issues in terms of common priorities of economic development and national integration. A key factor in the success of the Congress Party was its strategy of forming a vertical link between the upper-caste national elite and the numerically strong but traditionally lower-caste landowning peasants who were typically located in the rural areas. Since the mid-1970s, the lower castes of peasants, artisans, and the ex-untouchables began to challenge the political domination of the Congress Party, which found it increasingly difficult to manage the aspirations and demand of these castes. This development was helped by the affirmative action policy of the state that provided quotas for government jobs and education seats for selected lower castes—scheduled castes (SCs)— and tribal communities—schedule tribes (STs)—as well as by the escalation of appeals made by many non-Congress parties that mobilized their support primarily on the basis of caste. Caste became highly politicized at the beginning of the 1980s with the extension of the benefits of affirmative action policy to other backward classes (OBCs). OBCs comprised a large number of backward castes that could organize themselves outside the Congress influence because of their numerical strength. In this changed scenario, Congress and other Indian national parties had to negotiate with the OBCs, SCs (and STs), or with the parties constituted by them for electoral alliances and support. This trend strengthened in the 1990s with the fragmentation of the Indian party system and the emergence of coalition politics that increased the political importance of caste and caste-based parties. Some scholars have described the rise of caste politics during this period as the second democratic upsurge that brought political leaders from lower and backward castes to the forefront of Indian politics. Increasingly, politicians in India tend to calculate along caste lines, and caste is an important criterion in choosing electoral candidates. The growth and modernization of the Indian economy in the 1990s has further weakened the traditional caste hierarchy that has been 91 superimposed by the power system created by closely fought elections, a growing middle class, and the policies of affirmative action of the state. The net result of all these changes is that the ritually determined vertical social hierarchy has been overlaid by horizontally competing power blocs comprising heterogeneous castes that occupy different status across traditional hierarchies. An important feature of the current lower-caste agenda is the belief that the real improvement in their lives can come only through pursuit of political power. Thus, although the caste system in India was traditionally a graded hierarchy based on a purity– pollution scale, it has undergone many changes over the years. After India’s independence, there has been a de-ritualization of caste, and it has moved toward being a community based on affinity or kinship rather than representing a fixed hierarchy. The association of each caste with a distinct occupation has weakened considerably, and intercaste marriages across different ritual strata, even crossing the varna boundaries, are not uncommon. According to Depankar Gupta, the task of defining caste is not an easy one because many fundamental features of the caste system such as a uniform hierarchical ideology, occupational specialization, and the concepts of purity and pollution have greatly diminished in the contemporary Indian situation. Accordingly, his view is that caste should be described as discrete categories that incorporate multiple hierarchies that overlap and share many commonalities. In the current phase of coalition governments in India, the pursuit of social and political power dominates the caste agenda, and therefore, traditionally opposed caste groups find it possible to engage in opportunistic alliances and power-sharing arrangements in a volatile political situation. Rekha Diwakar See also Hierarchy; Ideology; Religious Power Further Readings Dumont, L. (1980). Homo hierarchicus: The caste system and its implications. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1966) Gupta, D. (2000). Interrogating caste. New Delhi, India: Penguin. 92 Castells, Manuel Sheth, D. L. (1999). Secularisation of caste and making of new middle class. Economic and Political Weekly, 34 (34/35, August 21–September 3), 2502–2510. CASTELLS, MANUEL (1942– ) Manuel Castells is a Spanish sociologist who has worked in Spain, France, and the United States. His early work was a form of Marxist urban sociology that concentrated on the conception of collective consumption, and how that defines the needs of the urban masses and displaces conflict in society from its original Marxist productive site to the site of consumption. He pioneered the idea that social struggle concerned these welfare needs via state intervention in consumption. Castells saw that social movements within broad networks were the key to understanding the potential power of the underclass. His interest in networks led him in his later work to concentrate on information. Castells has a straightforward understanding of power: the ability of a social actor to impose his or her will over other social actors. Social actors are not individual human beings; their abilities are structural: that is, they lie in relational forces between actors. In Castell’s later work, these forces reside in new information technologies that have restructured the economy and society. He sees three sociological dimensions as important to understanding the structure of society: power, production, and experience. These create the organization of the economy and of society, which in turn define the ways in which people create their own identities through their work and through their consumption. Castells has always seen a struggle between individual identity and that of the collective—the manner in which individuals identify themselves with collective processes. In his later work, he sees this dichotomy as between the biological individual human being and the “Net,” the set of organizations that have transcended the traditional hierarchies of the state. In a radically changing cultural environment, people find it more difficult to affirm their individual identities in relation to a social identity. The media provide the social space where power is formulated. The development of interactive and horizontal forms of communication, notably through the Internet, has created a form of mass individual communication as opposed to mass communication through institutional actors such as newspapers or TV channels. Castells sees this as a way in which social movements are able to gain power against the traditional forms of capitalist and state forces. He claims that the mass media and horizontal communication are converging, creating a historically new space of communication that can transform society. Castells’s work is bound up with traditional notions of power through interests and identity, through the importance of collective action through networks of social movements (which themselves bring individual identity), and by the possibilities of transforming society through those social movements. He has been an extremely influential sociologist in both the urban and communication literatures. Keith Dowding See also Globalization; Governmentality; Marxist Accounts of Power; Relational Power Further Readings Castells, M. (1977). The urban question: A Marxist approach. London: Edward Arnold. Stalder, F. (2006). Manuel Castells and the theory of the network society. Oxford, UK: Polity Press. CAUSAL THEORIES OF POWER There are key similarities between what is ordinarily considered an ascription of social power and that which is considered under the more general rubric of a “cause.” At one end of the historical scale, Thomas Hobbes asserted, “Power and Cause are the same thing.” At the other end, Herbert Simon asserted that we can substitute the locution “i has power over j” with “i’s behavior causes j’s behavior,” and William Riker argued that power and causality are really two sides of the same coin, so that we can delete the concept of power from the vocabulary of social science and political philosophy. These claims are not surprising because in social contexts we generally use the terms power and Causal Theories of Power cause to refer to circumstances related to the potential or actual “inducement of change” or of “making things happen” by some agent or group of agents against a set of known background conditions and regularities. That is, we are concerned with an asymmetric relation between two distinct events in the same time series, in which one ancestral event, an action on the part of some agent (or group of agents) has the efficacy to produce, or be part of the production, of another, the effect (which may or may not be the response of another agent or group of agents). If a chairperson of a committee has a casting vote and breaks a tie that leads to the acceptance of a new policy, we can say that the chair “induced a change” or “made things happen” and thus “exercised his or her power” or “was a causal factor” for the outcome. If there are good reasons to believe that the committee vote will be tied, we say that the chairperson has the power to force the outcome in which the policy is approved. Similarly, if j alters his or her course of action of getting into his or her car by instead handing the keys to i who is pointing a gun at j’s head, we say that i had power over j because the latter did something he or she would not have otherwise done. We say i had power over j if he or she caused j to act in a particular manner; we can rewrite this as i “induced a change” (of j’s behavior) or could be said to have “made things happen” (the change of j’s behavior or j’s performance or nonperformance of some specific action). The Equivalence Thesis In very broad terms, then, when we say that an agent was causal for some state-of-affair x or an agent has, had, or exercised his power with respect to x, we are suggesting some form of dependence between the agent’s behavior and x. Causal theories of power are those theories that take the dependency relations of “power’” to be equivalent to, or a subset of, “causal” relations. It is straightforward to show that the equivalence thesis is untenable. First, we need to be clear about the general nature of the causal relation that a causal theory of power refers to. When we say that c is a cause of e, we mean one of two things. We may be referring to a regularity that exemplifies a “covering law” and takes the form of “drinking a gallon of wine causes drunkenness.” 93 This says that whenever a specific quantity of wine is consumed, drunkenness will follow, given a set of background conditions. Alternatively, by a cause, we may be referring to a particular or singular event, such as “Mack’s drinking a gallon of wine was a cause of his drunkenness.” Here, no “covering law” is implied, but rather, the term cause is used to refer to a particular contingency, the occurrence of which is a departure from the normal or expected course of events. A causal theory of power refers to this second sense of cause. Not every piece of behavior that can be said to be a cause of some event can be said to be an exercise of power. If I accidentally slipped on the ice and knocked you over with the result that you are injured, we would say that I caused the injury, but not that I exercised my power to bring about your injury or that I exercised my power over you. A defender of the equivalence thesis could reply here that although this is true, equivalence could be restored for a subclass of events that captures the way in which we ordinarily use the term power. Slipping on the ice lacks a defining feature of power: “getting what you want.” The natural move here is to constrain power to potential or actual causal relations that exhibit some further behavioral characteristic. One route is to take Bertrand Russell’s famous dictum that power is the “production of intended effects”—which is loosely the idea of “getting what you want”—and say that power and cause are equivalents if the agent had intended the state of affairs and was a causal factor for it. Contingent Dependency: The “But For” Test But this move will also run into difficulties for reasons related to the precise nature of the causal relation for singular events, never mind the problems of intentionality. To see this, we need to add some precision to the dependency relation that is used to define singular causation. For the sake of argument, let us adopt a very general theory of theory of singular causation that is used in law, known as the NESS test (it has the advantage of getting around the quandaries of overdetermination). This test is a form of “contingent dependency” and says that c is a cause or causal factor of e if c is at least a necessary element of a sufficient set of conditions for e. It is a nested version 94 Causal Theories of Power of the more standard “but for test” for singular causation, which says that c is a cause or causal factor of e if, “but for” the occurrence of c, e would not have occurred. That is, the NESS test says that but for the presence of c, the particular set of conditions containing c would not be sufficient for e. To reject the equivalence thesis for intended effects we need to find a simple and intuitive example where an agent’s behavior can be said to be a causal factor by the NESS test but we would not say that the agent exercised any power in bringing about the outcome. Consider the following scenario. Victim is held up in his or her car by Assassin1, who ties Victim up and locks Victim in his or her car. Together with Assassin2, Assassin1 pushes the car over the cliff, killing Victim. Assassin1 is sufficient for holding up Victim and pushing the car over the cliff. Assassin2 cannot prevent Assassin1 killing Victim. To make matters more concrete, suppose that it requires at least 2 units of force to push Victim’s car over the cliff. Suppose further that Assassin1 has the physical strength to push with 0, 1, 2, or 3 units of force, while Assassin2 can only push with 0 or 1 unit of force. Finally, suppose Assassin1 and Assassin2 push the car over the cliff with 3 units and 1 unit of force, respectively. Now, supposing that the force of Assassin1 can be disaggregated into 0, 1, 2, and 3 units, then there exists a set of events such that Assassin2’s actual action of pushing with 1 unit of force is a NESS condition, namely, the combination with Assassin1’s 1 unit of force. For this argument, we can say that Assassin2 made a causal contribution to Victim’s death, which Assassin2 intended, but it would be inappropriate to say that Assassin2 exercised any power, either with respect to Victim’s death or over Victim. Power clearly requires more: Assassin1 would seem to be powerful because he or she can force Victim’s death and can prevent it. In contrast, Assassin2 can neither force Victim’s death nor prevent it. Power appears to require that the agent has an action that can contribute to x and to not-x. Power and Causation The question, then, is what is the appropriate causal relation for describing social power in a generic sense (power to x or power over x) that picks up the idea of being able to “get what you want” as well as “forcing” (x and not-x). Some writers have suggested that with respect to x, power requires that an agent have an action that is necessary condition for x, that is, the agent can force not-x but not x itself; others suggest that the agent have an action that is a sufficient condition, that is, the agent can force x but not necessarily not-x; and others postulate necessity and sufficiency, that is, the agent can force x and not-x. Each of these is too strong. Necessity fails because it means that two assassins, each of whom could kill their common victim, have no power over the victim or the power to realize his or her death because the other assassin could do it; the same holds true for necessity and sufficiency. Sufficiency fails because it says that a committee member with a veto has no power even though he or she can block x, that is, force not-x. The solution would seem to lie with a subset of NESS conditions. Max Weber’s definition of power gives the hint. In his now canonical definition, “power is the chance of a man or number of men to realize their own will in a communal action even against the resistance of others who are participating in the action.” Consider a three-member simple-majority committee and suppose that for some proposal x all three members vote in favor. The NESS test attributes a causal contribution for x to all three members on the grounds that the set of three “yes” votes can be decomposed into sets of two “yes” votes in which each “yes” is necessary for the set of votes to be sufficient for x. But there is also an additional property, given the actions of voting “yes” and “no”—any two-member coalition could force either x or not-x. In other words, the voters have power and have exercised this power because they have the chance to force their desired outcome in a communal action with others—a coalition—against the resistance of others participating in the action (in this case, committee voting). Note that to have power in this Weberian sense means that the agent must have an action that is necessary for the coalition to be able to force an outcome; the agent does not have to be in a position to contribute to forcing all outcomes. The difference from the assassin example should be clear. In the committee case, each voter is a necessary member of a coalition that can force an outcome; in that sense, they have an action that is Causal Theories of Power a necessary causal condition for a coalition of agents to be able to force an outcome. This is why we would say they have power, even if it is contingent. In the assassin case, Assassin2 has no such ability: Assassin2 can only perform an action that is necessary for a set of conditions to be causally efficacious but does not have an action or set of actions that would make him or her an indispensable member of a coalition that can force a particular outcome. Only Assassin1 has this. If an agent is an indispensable member of a coalition that has power, that agent has either made a causal impact on the state of affairs or has the potential to do so. But as the assassin example shows, having a causal impact does not imply power. So a causal theory of power must build on a subset of causal relations. A theory of power that matches this structure is Alvin Goldman’s. Although he expressed the view that causal terminology is likely to obscure the crucial questions of power, he presented a framework that is implicitly based on the NESS test. Goldman distinguishes between three categories of power: individual, collective, and social. In rough outline, an individual i has individual power with respect to x if and only if i has an action (or sequence of actions) such that the performance of this action (or sequence of actions) under the stated or implied conditions would result in x but would not so result if i had not performed this action (or sequence of actions). This definition states that individual power is equivalent to the case of an agent performing an action that is a sufficient condition for x. A collection of individuals T (a coalition) has collective power with respect to x if the members of T each have an action (or sequence of actions) such that if the performance of these actions (or sequence of actions) under the stated or implied conditions would result in x, but would not if any member of T did not perform this action (or sequence of actions). An individual i has social power with respect to x if i is a member of T that has social power with respect to x. In the NESS structure, i has individual power with respect to x if i has an action that is a NESS condition on its own (and is a one-member coalition that can force x), and i has social power with respect to x if i has an action such that i is an indispensable member of a coalition that can force x, which means that i is a NESS condition for x. 95 Causal theories of power not only come in terms of dependency relations. They can also be framed probabilistically. Robert Dahl’s theory of power is the prime example. Starting from the intuitive idea that “i has power over j to the extent that he can get j to do something that j would not otherwise do,” he then fleshes this out in probabilistic terms: i’s power is the difference in the probability of an event, given certain actions by i, and its probability given no such action by i. That is, i has power with respect to x to the extent that i can perform an action that raises the probability of x. This is Patrick Suppe’s well-known definition of a cause as a probability-raising event. Despite the intuitive appeal of this approach to causation, it suffers a fundamental weakness: not all probability-raising events should count as causes because it is possible to raise the probability of an event via an unactualized event. Consider two terrorists A and B fighting for the same cause who each plant an indeterministic bomb (a and b) on two different airplanes. Bomb a goes off, but bomb b does not. As a result, a government that is affected by the disaster changes its policy. Even though bomb b raised the probability of the policy change, it certainly did not cause the policy change. Can it be said that terrorist B exercised power with respect to the policy change? If yes, then we break the link between power and actual causation; if no, then we break the link to potential causal effects. It is probably not far off the mark to say that any theory of power entails a theory of causation in some form. To name a few: classical voting power indices such as the Banzhaf Index or the Shapley– Shubik Index can be defined in terms of NESS conditions or in terms of probability raising. This is not surprising: we use the concepts of power and cause to capture the generic phenomena of differencemaking in social interactions. Here a cautionary remark is in order: although power clearly requires a form of difference making, not all difference making that falls under the rubric of causality is power. Causes as difference makers can also be functional relationships between two variables as in the sense of causation as a regularity expressing a covering law. In these cases, if some social variable x, is very sensitive to movements in some other variable y, this does not by itself express the power of y to move x or the power of y over x in a social sense. This is a “marginality” conception of causation and 96 Causation has been implicitly used recently by some formal theorists of power, but it is not clear that “power” is what is expressed in the models if by power we mean some idea of “getting what you want” in the face of a “clash of wills.” Matthew Braham See also Causation; Dahl, Robert A. Strict necessity C is necessary for the occurrence of x whenever x occurs. Strong necessity C was necessary for x on the particular occasion. Weak necessity C was a necessary element of some set of existing conditions that was sufficient for the occurrence of x. For sufficiency: Further Readings Braham, M. (2007). Social power and social causation: Towards a formal synthesis. In M. Braham & F. Steffen (Eds.), Power: Conceptual, formal, and applied dimensions. Heidelberg, Germany: Springer. Braham, M., & van Hees, M. (2009). Degrees of causation. Erkenntnis, 73, 323–343. Dahl, R. A. (1957). The concept of power. Behavioral Science, 2, 201–215. Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. CAUSATION Causation is a concept that is at the heart of the subject of social power, of social relations more generally, and of questions of legal and moral responsibility and prediction in the social and natural sciences. In very general terms, to ask for the cause of some particular event is to ask what brought it about. That is, a cause is a relation between events, processes, or entities in the same time series, in which one event, process, or entity, C, has the efficacy to produce or be part of the production of another, the effect (or outcome) x. C is causal for x if C somehow makes a difference to the occurrence of x. In social contexts, C is an action performed by a person. Arguments among philosophers about what actually constitutes this efficacy—or “making a difference”—are often concerned with whether the efficacy is a necessity requirement (if x occurred, then C preceded it) or sufficiency requirement (if C occurs, then x will follow) or both. There are three senses for each of these. In descending order of stringency, for necessity we have Strict sufficiency occurrence of x. C is sufficient by itself for the Strong sufficiency C was a necessary element of some set of existing conditions that was sufficient for the occurrence of x. Weak sufficiency C was an element of some set of existing conditions that was sufficient for the occurrence of x. There are three remarks to be made here. First, we can instantly dispense with the concept of weak sufficiency for the simple reason that it is trivially satisfied by any condition C by simply adding C to an already existing set of conditions that is sufficient for x, although C is irrelevant as regards x. That is, weak sufficiency can fail to satisfy the simple counterfactual test of efficacy known as the “but for” test in a very unacceptable way. According to this test, C was a cause of some result x only if but for the occurrence of C, then x would not have occurred. Second, if C is strictly necessary for x, then C should be ascribed causal status for x, and if C is strongly necessary for x, then C should also be ascribed causal status for x. In both cases, C satisfies the “but for” test. Yet strict necessity is inadequate to cover causal relations in general because it will often not be fulfilled. It would mean that evidence of an electrical short-circuit that combined with other conditions and resulted in a house burning down would not qualify for causal status given that it is not true that for all instances of a house burning down there must have been an electrical short-circuit. Strict sufficiency is also inadequate because it too may fail to exist: it is rare that a single condition C is sufficient for x. Strict sufficiency also rules out ascribing the electrical short-circuit causal status for the house Causation burning down given that it alone cannot lead to the fire; the presence of flammable material, and so forth, is also called for. Moreover, that C may be strictly sufficient for x and was present on the occasion of x’s occurrence does not imply that C actually caused x; x may have brought about by another strictly sufficient condition that was also present on the occasion. Third, although strong necessity is ostensibly an attractive candidate for ascribing causality, it too can easily crumble in cases of causal overdetermination. These are those circumstances in which the causes of an event are cumulatively more than sufficient to generate the effect. That is, there exist situations in which a strongly necessary condition will fail to exist. Causal overdetermination comes in two broad types: duplicative and preemptive causation. A case of duplicative causation is one in which two similar and independent causal processes C1 and C2, each of which is sufficient for the same effect x, may culminate in x at the same time. It will be best to turn quickly to some examples of human action. Assassin case 1. Assassin1 and Assassin2 independently and simultaneously aim and shoot at Victim such that each shot is sufficient to kill Victim at exactly the same moment. Thus, neither assassin was strongly necessary for Victim’s death because, other things being equal, if either had not fired his shot, Victim would have died anyway from the shot fired by the other assassin. Although one could argue that this example is intuitively resolved by saying that a cause is either strictly sufficient, strictly necessary, or strongly necessary, this will not work for the following case. 97 of Victim’s car by any assassin alone is neither strictly necessary nor strictly sufficient nor strongly necessary for Victim’s death. The absence of strict sufficiency and necessity is obvious: no assassin pushing alone can kill Victim, and no particular assassin must push together with another assassin to have Victim’s car shoved over the cliff. To determine strong necessity, we again apply the but for test by holding the pushing by the other assassins constant and ask whether the car would have gone over the cliff killing Victim had the third assassin not been pushing. The answer is affirmative because it takes the pushing of at least two assassins for this to happen, and because under the circumstance this is true, then the car would have gone over the cliff and killed Victim. Thus, the pushing by the third assassin cannot be attributed as having causal status for Victim’s death. The same holds true for the pushing by the other two assassins. We can now turn to preemptive causation. This is the case in which an effect x is brought about by some actual sufficient condition(s) C1 such that had C1 not occurred, then x would have been brought about by some alternative sufficient condition(s) C2. There are two subcases of preemptive causation: (1) The alternative set of conditions C2 emerged after C1 brought about x. (2) The alternative set of conditions C2 did not emerge because C1 emerged and brought about x. The canonical example of type (i) preemptive causation is Assassin case 3. Assassin1 shoots and kills Victim who is embarking on a trek across the desert just as Victim was about to take a swig from his water bottle, which was poisoned by Assassin2. Assassin case 2. Victim is held up in Victim’s car by Assassin1, Assassin2, and Assassin3, who together tie Victim up and lock Victim in his or her car and then push the car over a cliff, killing Victim. It is sufficient for Victim’s death that only two assassins hold up Victim and push the car over the cliff. Here strong necessity is not correct given the failure of the but for test to allocate causal status to either assassin: Assassin1 cannot be said to have caused Victim’s death on the occasion in question because had Assassin1 not shot and killed Victim, Assassin2’s poisoning would have, given that Victim was just about to take a swig from his water bottle, and Assassin2 cannot be said to have caused Victim’s death because it was in fact Assassin1’s shot that did it and not Assassin2’s poisoning of Victim’s water. A type (2) case is To simplify matters, we need only focus on the pushing of Victim’s car over the cliff. The pushing Assassin case 4. Assassin1 shoots and kills Victim, and Assassin2 decides not to poison Victim’s 98 Causation water bottle (but would have had Assassin1 not shot Victim). Here strong necessity is not required because Assassin1 cannot be considered as having caused Victim’s death on the occasion in question because had Assassin1 not shot and killed Victim, then Assassin2 would have poisoned Victim’s water; yet Assassin2 cannot be attributed as causal for Victim’s death because Assassin2 did not in fact poison the water; he or she only would have done if Assassin1 had not shot Victim. From the six criteria, we have still to deal with the equivalent criteria of weak necessity and strong sufficiency. These were introduced by H. L. A. Hart, A. M. Honoré, John Mackie, and Richard Wright in various different forms to deal with causal ascriptions when an outcome is a result of a complex of conditions. The idea behind the weak necessity/strong sufficiency requirement is that to be ascribed causal status for an event x, a prior event C need not be the cause as in the sense of it being the single sufficient condition present on the occasion or a cause in the senses of strict or strong necessity, but merely shown to be a “causally relevant condition” of x. That is, weak necessity/strong sufficiency drops what can actually be considered a deeply rooted presupposition that to be ascribed causal status for x C must be directly related to x in that any state of affairs is brought about by some singularly identifiable prior event. In its place comes a conception of causality that allows for an indirect relation between a prior event C and its consequence x; but the indirect relation still requires a necessity requirement. This is obtained by combining a sufficiency and a necessity requirement in a set-based framework. That is, weak necessity/strong sufficiency means it need not be the case that a single condition is sufficient for x but that a set of conditions be sufficient (strict sufficiency is then the special case of a singleton set) on this occasion and combines this with a necessity requirement in that the members of this set are necessary for the set to be sufficient—that is, the set of conditions is minimally sufficient (MSS). Mackie denoted a test of weak necessity/strong sufficiency by the acronym INUS: “an insufficient but necessary part of a condition which is itself unnecessary but sufficient for the result.” In Wright’s simpler mnemonic: “a necessary element of a sufficient set” or NESS. The attractive feature of weak necessity/strong sufficiency is that it is general enough to cover strict and strong necessity and strict sufficiency: (a) if C is a member of every MSS for any instance of x, then C is strictly necessary for x; (b) if C was a member of every MSS for a given instance of x then C is strongly necessary for x; and (c) if C is sufficient for one MSS, then C is strictly sufficient for x. To see how NESS works in cases of duplicative causation the idea is to resolve the excess sufficient set into its component MSSs. Consider again Assassin case 1. Each assassin’s act of shooting is a necessary element of some minimally sufficient set and therefore the behavior of each marksperson can be attributed causal status for Victim’s death because the behavior of each marksperson was necessary to complete a set of conditions sufficient for Victim to die, and each of these conditions was present on the occasion in question. In Assassin case 2, we see that given that it is true that the pushing of the car by each of the three assassins belongs to at least one MSS consisting of pushing by two assassins and each of these MSSs was present on the occasion, then the pushing by each assassin qualifies for causal status for Victim’s death. It is similarly easy to disentangle the cases of preemptive causation. Here, the idea is to check if a particular act is an element of an MSS that forms a preempting cause. In Assassin case 3, Assassin1’s act of shooting is a necessary element of some MSS and therefore a cause, although Assassin2’s poisoning of the water is not because although poisoned water would be sufficient for killing Victim, in the circumstances it cannot be an actual sufficient condition because Victim has already been killed by Assassin1’s shot. In Assassin case 4, Assassin1’s act of shooting is a cause of Victim’s death, but Assassin2’s intention to poison Victim’s water is not. What the NESS condition does in cases of preemptive causation is to evaluate the claim that C1 could not be a causal factor of x because of the existence of an alternative cause C2 that either emerged or could have emerged subsequent to the occurrence of C1. According to the NESS test, this fact does not vitiate the causal status of C1. Note that the NESS test only passes a judgment about the causal status of an agent’s action and not its moral status. Central Intelligence Agency Finally, we should consider the important question of how a power ascription is related to causation. Here, there is a fair amount of debate but little is settled. One strand of thought, going back to Thomas Hobbes, considers an ascription of power and cause as being one and the same; a second strand of thought considers a power ascription to be a subset of causal ascriptions; and a third strand considers power and causal ascriptions to be merely overlapping categories. Probably the most accurate position is the second one. This can be seen with another example: Assassin case 5. Victim is held up in Victim’s car by Assassin1 who ties and locks Victim up in his or her car. Together with Assassin2, Assassin1 pushes the car over the cliff killing Victim. Assassin1 is sufficient for holding up Victim and pushing the car over the cliff. Assassin2 cannot prevent Assassin1 from killing Victim. To make this case more concrete, suppose that it requires at least 2 units of force to push Victim’s car over the cliff. Suppose further that Assassin1 has the physical strength to push with 0, 1, 2, or 3 units of force, whereas Assassin2 can only push with 0 or 1 unit of force. Finally, suppose both assassins each apply 1 unit of force. In this circumstance, each assassin can be said to have made a causal contribution to Victim’s death because each contributed an action to an MSS and therefore each action satisfies the NESS test. However, Assassin1 clearly possesses a characteristic that Assassin2 does not: Assassin1 possesses an action that satisfies the Weberian definition of power in that Assassin1 can force the outcome that Victim lives or dies despite any resistance that Assassin2 may put up. Hence, the difference between an ascription of power and one of causal contribution lies in that power demands reference to the potential of overcoming resistance, but a causal ascription does not. Thus, we can say that if a person exercised power then the person was a causal condition for an outcome but the converse is not true. Game-theoretically, the difference between an ascription of causal contribution and power lies in the objects of analysis. To say that an agent made a causal contribution to some outcome is to say that an agent performed an action that was a necessary element of an event, the action profile, that 99 was sufficient for the outcome; whereas to say that an agent had power with respect to some outcome is to say that the agent was a necessary member of a coalition that is sufficient for the outcome. The set-inclusion proposition goes through because if a coalition is sufficient for an outcome it means that the members of the coalition have an action profile that is sufficient for the outcome: however, the fact that an agent contributes an action to a minimally sufficient action profile does not imply that this agent is necessary for some subset of agents that can form an action profile to bring about the outcome. Matthew Braham See also Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power; Weber, Max Further Readings Braham, M. (2007). Social power and social causation: Towards a formal synthesis. In M. Braham & F. Steffen (Eds.), Power: Conceptual, formal, and applied dimensions. Heidelberg, Germany: Springer. Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, A. M. (1959). Causation in the law. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Mackie, J. L. (1974). The cement of the universe. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Wright, R. (1985). Causation in tort law. California Law Review, 73, 1735–1828. CENTRAL INTELLIGENCE AGENCY The U.S. Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) was established under the 1947 National Security Act in response to the Japanese surprise attack at Pearl Harbor in 1941. Its statutory functions were to advise the National Security Council (NSC) on intelligence matters, to “correlate and evaluate” intelligence information from across the U.S. government, and to perform unspecified other tasks that the NSC judged could be “more effectively accomplished centrally.” Before the 2004 Intelligence Reform and Terrorism Prevention Act, the CIA was headed by the director of Central Intelligence (DCI), who was also responsible for coordinating the intelligence community (IC), that is, all of the various departmental intelligence agencies. 100 Chicken Games Under the 2004 Act, which was prompted by the failure of the intelligence community to detect the impending 9/11 terrorist attacks, the “community” role was delegated to a new director of National Intelligence (DNI) and the CIA is now headed by a director, appointed by the president. The CIA, and its short-lived predecessor, the 1946 Central Intelligence Group (CIG), were originally intended to be administrative and analytical staff organizations. Covert operational capability developed as something of an afterthought when CIG took on the residual elements of the wartime Office of Strategic Services because of a lack of viable alternatives. In 1952, the CIA’s covert capability was consolidated as the Directorate of Plans (DP), redesignated the Directorate of Operations (DO) in 1972 and the National Clandestine Service (NCS) in 2005. The analytical components became the Directorate of Intelligence in 1952 and have remained that since. Despite the DO’s improvised origins, the 1976 Church inquiry noted that between 1962 and 1970, the DO alone accounted for 52% of the CIA’s budget and 55% of its personnel. Most of this was, however, human intelligence rather than special activities, although public and press attention over the years has typically focused on the latter. After the failed Bay of Pigs invasion of Cuba in 1961, the CIA placed steadily less emphasis on large covert actions and, as documentary releases clearly show (albeit contrary to conventional wisdom), had no role in the coup that toppled the regime of Salvador Allende in Chile in 1972. During the 1970s, the DO lost about one third of its staff with the end of the Vietnam conflict and an increased emphasis on analysis and technical collection methods, although numbers were partially restored during Ronald Reagan’s presidency. After the cold war, the CIA experienced another sharp reduction of approximately 25% in overall funds and humanpower. Contrary to popular perceptions, the CIA does not produce national intelligence estimates such as that on Iraqi nonconventional weapons in October 2002. These are generated by an interagency body involving all 14 agencies of the U.S. intelligence community called the National Intelligence Council. Philip H. J. Davies See also Espionage; Intelligence Further Readings Andrew, C. (1995). For the president’s eyes only: Secret intelligence and the American presidency from Washington to Bush. London: HarperCollins. Darling, A. B. (1990). The Central Intelligence Agency: An instrument of government, to 1950. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Richelson, J. T. (2008). The U.S. intelligence community (5th ed.). Boulder, CO: Westview Press. CHICKEN GAMES The game of chicken refers to (a) a stylized conflict situation, (b) a 2 2 game matrix that provides a simplified representation of this conflict situation, and (c) a class of real-world conflict situations for which both (a) and (b) provide oversimplified but perhaps enlightening models. In the stylized conflict situation, two juvenile delinquents position their cars at opposite ends of a deserted stretch of road. With their respective gang members and girlfriends looking on, they drive toward each other at high speed, each straddling the center line. The first driver to lose his nerve and swerve into his own lane to avoid a crash is revealed to be “chicken” and loses the game, and the driver with stronger nerves is victorious. If both swerve, the outcome is a draw. If both drive straight, the outcome is mutual disaster. The game matrix for this specific stylized conflict is shown on the left in Figure 1. Many real-world conflict situations in which each side has a general choice between “standing firm” or “giving in”—for example, international crises, hostage-holding negotiations, industrial conflicts, and bargaining situations generally— have characteristics of the game of chicken, as shown in the more generic matrix on the right in Figure 1, in which P ([Mutual] Punishment) > L (Lose) C (Compromise) W (Win). Chicken, probably the most famous 2 2 game other than prisoner’s dilemma, has the following properties. Neither player has a dominant strategy; for each player, the best choice is to do the opposite of what the other player does, and each asymmetric pair of choices is a (Nash) equilibrium. But each equilibrium is a victory for one player over the other, with the victory going to the more reckless 101 Civil War (a) (b) Player 2 Player 1 Swerve Straight Figure 1 Swerve Straight 2 Player 1 2 0 Give In 2 0 2 10 Player 2 10 Stand Firm Give In Stand Firm C2 C1 W2 L1 P2 L2 W1 P1 Game matrix for chicken: (a) specific; (b) generic player. Finally, although compromise is the symmetric outcome best for both players, it is not an equilibrium, and the apparent willingness of one player to compromise encourages the other to stand firm. In short, chicken is a particularly nasty game. Various signals, tactics, and strategic moves can enhance the bargaining power of a player and his or her probability of victory. If one player can make an absolutely credible commitment to stand firm, the other is compelled to give in. Likewise, if one player can convey the impression that he or she is crazy, reckless, stumble-down drunk, and so on (perhaps by actually being so), the other may likewise be compelled to give in. Conversely, if one player publicly attributes rationality, caution, or cowardice to the other, or if the former claims that he or she believes that his or her car is crash-proof (or that martyrdom is a ticket to heaven), that player thereby conveys to the other player that the first player believes he or she can safely stand firm. More perversely, if a player takes some visible action that actually increases the player’s cost of giving in, he or she thereby makes it more likely that the other player must give in. For example, hostage holders can kill one or a few hostages, so that they must expect a worse penalty if they give in and are captured. Real-world conflicts play out through a chronological sequence of moves not represented in the 2 2 chicken matrix. In such a sequence, each player can try to displace onto the other the “last clear chance” to avoid mutual disaster, forcing the other player either to give in or “start the shooting,” anticipating that the other player will be unwilling to do the latter and will therefore give in. Finally, a player can explicitly stake his or her future reputation on standing firm in the present conflict. Thus, although the repeated play of a prisoner’s dilemma can induce mutual cooperation, the expectation of repeated play of the game of chicken increases the incentive for each player to stand firm to gain a reputation that will intimidate later opponents. Nicholas R. Miller See also Bargaining; Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power; Prisoner’s Dilemma Further Readings Kahn, H. (1965). On escalation: Metaphors and scenarios. New York: Praeger. Schelling, T. C. (1966). Arms and influence. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Snyder, G. H. (1971). “Prisoner’s dilemma” and “chicken” models in international politics. International Studies Quarterly, 4, 66–103. CIVIL WAR Civil wars occur between different groups within a nation-state so that one group can take control of the apparatus of the state. Sometimes groups that want to secede part of the country from the nation-state also fight conflicts described as civil war. To distinguish civil wars from other disputes, conflicts, or terrorism within a state, most academics recognize that at least 1,000 casualties are required for a conflict to be termed a civil war. The number of conflicts deemed civil wars in the 20th century is much higher than in the preceding century, almost certainly because of the increase in the number of nation-states and because of the end of colonial empires in Africa and Asia. The cold war has also been a factor. Academics studying civil wars have examined factors that are correlated with their onset and 102 Civil War duration. These factors include aspects of the society in which civil war occurs and factors external to the country. Generally, we might see these factors as incentives to fight or not: the greater the costs of war, the lower the likelihood they will occur; the greater the benefits, both to participants and to outsiders, the more likely they are. Internal factors include levels of education, per capita income, and economic growth. The first two factors are related to the potential costs of civil war to participants. Better-off people have more to lose in conflict than do poorer people. Education, especially higher secondary school enrolment for boys, has been shown to be significantly related to civil war. Most soldiers are young men: those with higher levels of education have greater economic prospects and are less likely to be prepared to fight. Higher economic growth also increases future expectations, thus lowering the probability of conflict. Lower per capita income and lower growth might also be signs of grievance leading to higher probabilities of conflict. However, measures of economic inequality do not correlate with the probability of civil war, which suggests grievance over inequalities is not a straightforward cause. Another cause of grievance is ethnic conflict, especially if one ethnic group feels it is being exploited by another. Again, economic growth might alleviate this tension, but not necessarily. The findings here are complex. Ethnic heterogeneity is not itself correlated with the probability of civil war; ethnic dominance, however, is. If one ethnic group comprises more than 50% of the population and there are large ethnic minorities, then civil war is more likely. There have to be two sides in a civil war, and forming coalitions of smaller groups against a dominant one can be problematic, as the dominant group can make side payments to keep some groups on its side. Furthermore, it is not always the largest ethnic group that is the dominant group controlling the state, which increases the risk of civil war further. The size of the population also increases the risk of civil war, though the smaller the population is, the less the likelihood of any conflict reaching the 1,000-casualty threshold. There is also a heritage effect, in that the longer since the last civil war, the lower the probability is of another one. Past grievance, especially from the losers, increases the probability of armed conflict occurring again. Outside factors include large numbers of one ethnic group living outside the country. Such a diaspora can fuel discontent and form both a source of money and organization to fund armies. Sometimes disaffected peoples live in a country and plot destabilization from bases outside it. It has also been found that a high proportion of primary commodities in national exports increase the risk of civil war. The likely explanation is that it is easier to take control of primary industries than of manufacturing industry, and war creates less disruption of production. Furthermore, sourcing primary commodities means that outside interests, both countries and, at times, business interests, can fund and support one side or another in a civil conflict. The cold war also exacerbated civil wars, particularly because it coincided with countries gaining self-rule from colonial empires. In civil conflicts, both sides gained support from either the West or the Soviet bloc and received funding, arms, and training. This encouraged the onset of civil wars and increased the wars’ duration. The average number of civil wars per year increased dramatically from 1945 to the late 1990s from 2 or 3 to more than 40, though the number has fallen since the end of the cold war to around 30 per year in the new century. However, the average duration of civil wars has continued to rise from about a year to about 16 years by the beginning of the 21st century. In addition to outside forces backing the two sides, their abilities to self-fund through trade is important, so again each side being able to control mineral or agricultural (often illicit drugs) commodities is important to a civil conflict’s duration. In contrast, in the 19th century, the major European powers tended to quell civil conflict (in Europe at least) by all backing one side, almost always the government in power at the time. Nineteenth-century civil wars lasted longer in Latin America (though they did not always result in the 1,000 deaths needed to enter the statistics). Keith Dowding See also Coalition Theory; Military in Government Further Readings Collier, P., & Sambukas, N. (Eds.). (2005). Understanding civil war. Washington, DC: World Bank. Clegg, Stewart Fearon, J. D. (2004). Why do some civil wars last longer than others? Journal of Peace Research, 41, 275–301. CLAUSEWITZ, CARL (1780–1831) VON Prussian general and military thinker, whose posthumous book On War has become the most respected military classic, Carl von Clausewitz’s ideas were shaped by the coming together of two revolutions that dominated his life and times: the French Revolution and the Romantic reaction against the ideas of the Enlightenment. Joining the Prussian army at the age of 12, he took part in the invasion of France in 1793 and participated in Prussia’s disastrous defeat before Napoleon at Jena-Auerstädt (1806). Then, in an effort to rescue Prussia from the verge of extinction, he became one of the young members of the Prussian reform movement, headed in the army by his mentor, war minister Gerhard von Scharnhorst. The reformers traced the roots of French military power to the political and social revolution that had given the French state the legitimacy and means to harness the whole nation—fired with civic and patriotic energies—to the cause of war. In the teeth of oligarchic opposition, they worked for a social and political reform of Prussia as the only means for reviving its great-power status in the age of mass social participation. A fervent German nationalist and Prussian patriot, Clausewitz shared Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s admiration for Niccolò Machiavelli’s elevation of the patriotic cause above all else, the concept of power as the paramount political factor, and rejection of moral considerations in the anarchic international arena. Resigning the Prussian service for a while to join the Russian army to fight Napoleon in 1812, Clausewitz and his fellow-reformers saw their aspirations fulfilled with Napoleon’s downfall (1813– 1815). However, once the danger had gone, their program faced even greater resistance than before, as reaction set in. Clausewitz’s main efforts were now channeled to the writing of a great work on war. Deeply impressed by Napoleon’s crushing strategy that completely overwhelmed the armies of the ancien régime, Clausewitz rejected the limited 103 warfare of the 18th century. He believed that the “nature,” “essence,” “concept,” or “spirit” of war required mobilization of all available forces to be thrown against the enemy’s main army with the aim of destroying it in a major battle in pursuit of ambitious political aims. These notions, cultivated by the reformers during the heroic struggle against Napoleon, were systematized in On War. However, after drafting the first six books (of eight) that make up On War, Clausewitz realized, contrary to his lifelong views, that limited war was as legitimate as all-out war because “war is nothing but the continuation of state policy by the admixture of other means.” He developed these fundamental new insights in writing Books 7 and 8 of On War, and in revising Chapter 1 of Book 1, but he died before completing the revision of the rest of the work. The posthumous work thus conserves two different, and conflicting, layers of Clausewitz’s thought—the cause of much confusion among later readers. Clausewitz became a man for all seasons: the people of the 19th century canonized his work for its emphasis on the decisive clash of forces, whereas in the nuclear age he has been celebrated for postulating the supremacy of the political aim and for his concept of limited war. Azar Gat See also Anarchy in International Relations; Realism in International Relations; War Further Readings Gat, A. (1989). The origins of military thought from the Enlightenment to Clausewitz. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Incorporated in Gat, A. (2001). A history of military thought: From the Enlightenment to the cold war. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. CLEGG, STEWART (1947– ) The Anglo-Australian Stewart Clegg has established himself as one of the important figures in contemporary social theory as a result of his contribution to the study of social power and organization. Although his theory is well informed by 104 Clegg, Stewart modern theories, Clegg’s recent focus has taken a postmodern turn. As noted in his 2005 Vita Contemplativa, a clear theoretical thread runs through his work: 1. Power is a “relation of flows,” rather than an obdurate reality out there that avails itself to positivistic analysis. 2. Power is always countered; hence, a theory of power that disregards the “dialectics of control” between authority and resistance is deeply flawed. 3. Resources and surveillance are important, but a social theory that undermines the role of other factors in the understanding of power and organizational dynamics is wanting. 4. The study of power needs to be premised on the idea that there is no one grand rationality but disparate rationalities that are embedded in social history. Born in Bradford, United Kingdom, Clegg got his bachelor’s degree in 1971 from Aston University and his PhD in 1974 from Bradford University. After working briefly for Trent Polytechnic, Nottingham, and the European Group for Organization Studies as a postdoctoral research fellow, he was hired by Griffith University in Brisbane, Australia, in 1976. At this time, he was re-socialized as Australian, “slowly losing [his] pining and allegiance to the other country, the other continent.” Later he worked at the Universities of New England, St. Andrews, and Western Sydney. Currently, he is professor of management at the University of Technology, Sydney, and Director of the Innovative Collaborations, Alliance, and Networks Research Center. He has authored or coauthored 30 books and has published more than 90 journal articles. Clegg’s first book, Power, Rule and Domination (1975), deals with the social phenomenology of power. In this work, he investigated a sociological topic but relied on assumptions formulated both in and outside the field of sociology. From sociology, the concepts of power, rule, and domination, as spelled out by Max Weber and Georg Simmel, are used. Conversely, Clegg borrows Ludwig Wittgenstein’s concepts of “language game” and “forms of life” to help him understand the grammar of power dynamics. Furthermore, Clegg used an ethnomethodological approach to examine the nature of power in organizations. This was unconventional for its time because sociologists of organization hardly examined organizational dynamics as a process in which “practical theorists” are actively engaged. Ultimately, Clegg’s study of a construction site in Northern England provided a nuanced relational and contextual analysis of power in which “deep rules” and “‘iconic’ systems of domination” are critical. Accordingly, he was able to avoid the flaws of previous theories that have limited themselves to the surface reality of power. In his later study of power and organizations, Clegg further extends his position on the need to transcend a surface analysis of power. This time, the subjects of his critical exegesis were theories that dealt with the behavioral dimensions of power and organizations. Because of their exclusive focus on the manifest operations involved in the decision-making processes and portrayed organizations in a pluralist fashion, these theories gave scant attention to the structural basis of power. According to Clegg, the analysis of power in organizations requires more than understanding which group has control over which resources. Rather, emphasis needs to be placed on structural arrangements that constrain social behavior. Yet his structural approach is based on a reconceptualized notion of structure. Structure is not viewed as a prearranged social relation. Instead, it is regarded as “sedimented selection rules,” the understanding of which entails historical analysis. In his Frameworks of Power (1989), Clegg further examines the relation between power and structure. Here, he takes seriously the insights of Niccolò Machiavelli, whose views on power are at odds with those of Thomas Hobbes. Hobbes was interested in legislating a grand narrative of power that acts as a political instrument that, by way of perpetuating sovereignty, brings together multiple social institutions. Machiavelli instead was focused on the interpretation of power that perceives it as a set of contingent practices that do not easily lend themselves to generalization. Accordingly, whereas theories that have followed the Hobbesian tradition portrayed power as a negative force, theories that followed the Machiavellian tradition, the most explicit of which is Michel Foucault’s theory, Coalition Theory consider the productive dimensions of power. Following the latter tradition, Clegg notes that power is not a zero-sum game; rather, it involves a set of practices that produce needs and impute interests. Consequently, Clegg has spelled out a novel theory of power that is multidimensional in its orientation. Where others see episodic, dispositional, and facilitative facets of power as disparate, Clegg, in his theory of “circuits of power,” sees them as interconnected. Episodic power is the most visible form of power in which rules, relations, and resources are translated, fixed, reproduced, and transformed. Yet episodic power is not a free-floating level, nor does it serve as a foundation for other forms of power. The strategies espoused in episodic power require that the “substantive rational conditions” need to be secured and reproduced. Two other macro circumstances, accordingly, are salient for its existence, social integration, and system integration, involving both subjective and material conditions for dispositional and facilitative levels of power, respectively. Whereas dispositional power mainly deals with the social construction of meaning and membership, facilitative power is concerned with “the empowerment and disempowerment of agencies’ capacities.” Clegg’s theory has the advantage of providing a micro–macro link between the diverse manifestations of power, although, as some critics have indicated, his theory tends to be too abstract to be labeled as postmodern. Alem S. Kebede See also Giddens, Anthony Further Readings Clegg, S. (1989). Frameworks of power. London: Sage. Clegg, S. (2005). “Vita contemplativa”: A life in part. Organization Studies, 26(2), 291–309. COALITION THEORY Politics can be seen as the art of coalition formation. Any political leader needs supporters that he or she must reward in some way and any opponent can only challenge if he or she allies. 105 Machiavelli himself understood this process, and every successful leader has applied it whether consciously or unconsciously. Coalition theory is normally applied to parties within a democratic legislature but can be applied to any political process, and it can be seen as the fundamental basis of the power of all political leaders and governments. The Model Coalition theory tries to provide answers to two basic problems: which coalition will form and what will be the outcome. If applied to an abstract setting that more or less ignores historical facts and institutional arrangements and also assumes rational agents, there seems to be a fundamental tension between the issues of coalition formation and outcome determination: the more definitely we can answer the one question, the less definitively we can answer the other. Both problems can be described with respect to a society—that is, a set of agents N, and a value function v that assigns a value v(S) to each subset S of N. We call S a coalition. This implies that the members of A can concert their actions such that v(S) can be achieved. S is a winning (or effective) coalition if it determines the outcome of (N,v). To accomplish this, S either selects an element x or a subset Y in the set of alternatives, that is, set of possible outcomes. The pair (N,v) describes a social decision problem with coalition formation: a coalition game. There can be a unique winning coalition for (N,v). Then N\S, that is, the complement of S, is a losing coalition. This often applies if (N,v) is a political game and the winning coalition S represents the ruling government. More generally, the underlying situation can be modeled as a simple game such that, for every coalition S, either v(S) 1 or v(S) 0, and S is called either winning or losing, respectively. In general, voting bodies such as parliaments and committees can be portrayed by simple games. However, an economy is formed by many coalitions that have an impact on the overall outcome so that each of them determines a component of the vector x that describes the selected alternative; so an economy is not a simple game. For instance, an individual firm can be modeled as a coalition. 106 Coalition Theory Coalition S and its complement N\S form a coalition structure. More generally, a coalition structure is a finite partition P of N such that the (disjoint) sets Sk and St are elements of P (and the intersection of Sk and St is empty) and subsets of N. Thus, P {S1, . . . , Sm} such that Sk St , k,t 1, . . . , m (and k t), where k and t are members of coalitions. A third question is often relevant for coalition formation: the distribution problem, that is, how to distribute v(S). The members of N are assumed to have preferences with respect to the alternatives in X, which can be summarized by a payoff profile u (u1, . . . , un). Here ui is the payoff function of member i of N and i 1, . . . , n such that n is the cardinality of N. It is not obvious whether the value v(S) is a utility or a potential such as power; however, if utilities are transferable, then we have (a) v(N) ui for i 1, . . . , n, and outcome u can be interpreted as the evaluation of the distribution of some divisible private good—money, patronage, porkbarrel benefits, and so forth. Correspondingly, coalition S can guarantee its members payoffs such that (b) v(S) ui for all members i in S. A payoff vector x dominates a payoff vector y if S can ensure that x prevails and xi yi for all members i in S. A minimum requirement such that i supports coalition S is that (c) ui(S) v({i}). Here ui(S) is the utility that i achieves as a member of S and v({i}) is the value of i if i “stands alone.” If ui satisfies (a) and (c) for all i in N, then u (u1, . . . , un) is an imputation. Solutions and Solution Concepts Now that we have a model for n-person games that allows for, or presupposes, the forming of coalitions, we can try to answer the questions of which, what, and how. We make use of alternative solution concepts that serve as shorthand to describe possible expectations of rational agents with respect to coalitions and payoffs in n-person games. The core is the most prominent solution concept that considers coalition formation. The concept gives conditions such that the grand coalition N is stable. For transferable utility games, the imputation u (u1, . . . , un) is in the core of a game G if there are no coalitions S (subset of N) such that v(S) ui. If the latter holds true, then u is coalitionally rational: the forming of S is not profitable for the members of S if S is a strict subset of N. More generally, the core is the set of allocations u such that u is (a) Pareto efficient, (b) individually rational, and (c) coalitionally rational. (Note that an imputation is an allocation that satisfies [a] and [b].) In general, the set of allocations u that satisfies (a), (b), and (c) is large and the outcome is subject to bargaining among the members of N, or the set that defines the core is empty. To illustrate the second case, assume that agents 1, 2, and 3 vote on the distribution of a (payoff) cake that is normalized to 1. Each agent has one vote and a simple majority of votes determines the wining coalition. The core of this three-person simple majority game v* is empty. For every imputation x, there is an imputation y such that a majority of agents prefers x to y. A plausible expectation is that a coalition of two agents will form and these agents will divide the coalition value in equal shares. However, there are three candidates of winning coalitions and the corresponding set of payoffs under the equal share assumption is V {(1 2,1 2,0), (1 2,0,1 2), (0,1 2,1 2)}. Note that the elements of V do not dominate each other (internal stability), but for every imputation x not in V there is an imputation y in V that dominates x (external stability). The multiplicity of coalition possibilities gives stability to the outcomes in V that describes a von Neumann–Morgenstern solution for the given voting game; hence, V is called a stable set. According to V, we expect equal sharing, but we cannot tell which coalition will prevail. However, V is not the only stable set of this game: there is an infinite number of triples of asymmetric payoff vectors satisfying internal and external stability—for example, V* {(x, 1 x c, c): 0 x 1} such that c is a constant smaller 1/2. The median voter solution for the case of singlepeaked preferences and two candidates can be interpreted as a stable set. The outcome is well defined by the median voter position but we do not know which coalition will form, that is, which candidate will win a majority and who are the voters in the majority coalition. The multiplicity of coalition possibilities gives stability to the outcome. Alternative coalitions can reduce the leeway of bargaining within coalitions to zero such that there is a unique outcome even if the core is empty. If x is a payoff vector and the core is empty, then Coalition Theory e(S,x) v(S) xi 0 where the sum is over all members i in S and e(S,x) is the excess of S with respect to x. The surplus of i against j is defined by sij(x) max e(S,x) where the maximum is taken over all coalitions S such that i is in S and j is not in S. Thus, sij(x) expresses the maximum possibilities of i to gain payoffs in coalitions that do not have j as a member: v(S) does not guarantee that i gets this value as payoff. The payoff vector x and coalition structure P are meant to be stable if, with respect to any coalition S in P, sij(x) sji(x) for all i, j in S. The set of combinations of x and P that satisfy this property describe the kernel K of a coalition game v. The kernel is a solution concept that both (a) helps select an element from the outcome set if the core is large and (b) determines an outcome if the core is empty. Consider the previous three-person simple majority voting game v*. If P {{1,2},{3}} then x (1 2,1 2,0) is the only payoff vector such that the payoff configuration 具x,P典 is in K(v*). If P {N}, then y (1 3,1 3,1 3) is the only payoff vector such that 具y,P典 is in K(v*). A comparison of these two examples illustrates the impact of the—exogenously given—coalition structure. Now consider the three-person game v° in which coalitions {1,2},{1,3}, and N win. Given P {{1,2},{3}},冓x,P冔 is in K only if x (1,0,0). Despite the given coalition structure, {1,3} is still feasible and player 1 can propose a counter-objection 具z,P典(with z1 1 and P {{1,3},{2}}) to any objection 具y,P典 with y1 1. The effect of this threat becomes obvious if we assume that 3 is ineligible for coalition membership, perhaps because of an extremist political ideology. Then we can predict that coalition {1,2} will form, but the outcome is indeterminate, that is, subject to bargaining. The “potential to object” a payoff configuration 具x,P典 is minimized, and thus the corresponding outcome “relatively stable,” if the excess e(S,x) is minimal. The application of this principle defines the nucleolus. For a given coalition structure P, the nucleolus is an element of the kernel. If the kernel is a singleton, the kernel and the nucleolus are identical. If the core is nonempty, the nucleolus is an element of the core. The possibility of objecting and counter-objecting defines the so-called bargaining sets. Their characteristic feature is that a payoff configuration 具x,P典 is 107 stable (and therefore a likely result of coalition formation) if for any objection 具y,P,典 there is a counter objection 具z,P*典 such that 具y,P典 is not profitable to the members of the objecting coalition. The bargaining sets can be distinguished by the alternative conditions that objections and counter objections have to satisfy. By minimizing the “potential for objecting,” the nucleolus endogenizes the forming of a coalition structure. More explicitly, S. Hart and M. Kurz propose a model that addresses the problem of why coalition structures form and predicts endogenously which one will indeed form. They assume that all coalitions bargain for the division of the total, which is the worth of the grand coalition. A coalition structure is stable if no group of players can reorganize itself in a way that is profitable for all. A reduction of the “potential for objecting” suggests that only minimal winning coalitions (MWC) will form, that is, winning coalitions that contain no surplus players. If the members of a coalition are meant to share the coalition value per capita, coalitions with fewest members are likely candidates. William H. Riker’s size principle proposes the forming of MWCs for an environment that can be described by an n-person zero-sum game and symmetry. The latter implies that the value of a coalition is a function of the number of its members only. Such a setting seems highly unlikely in the political arena; however, there are even logical problems with it. Russell Hardin proposes a five-person zero-sum game with possible outcomes x (20,20,20,10,50) or y (20,20,20,10,50) allocated to players A, B, C, D, and E, respectively. Let us assume coalition {A,B,C,D} has formed and payoffs are z (26,26,26,28,50). First, note that the security level of player D is 50 if coalition {A,B,C} forms and x or y apply. Thus, D could prefer side payments of 6 to A, B, and C each to ensure outcome x. Second, despite v({A,B,C}) v({A,B,C,D}), it does not pay for players A, B, and C to eject D from coalition {A,B,C,D} if z can be achieved with the help of D. However, if the outcome vector x is predetermined, then D has no incentive to bribe A, B, and C, and the MWC {A,B,C} will gain a total of 60, only. What outcome and coalition structure do we expect if no constraints are given on the imputations that describe the outcome? The answer depends on the choice of the solution concept that we apply. 108 Coercion, Analytic It seems that Riker’s size principle is relevant only for zero-sum games. However, this does not imply that MWCs are irrelevant for coalition formation. In simple games, the forming of MWCs ensures some stability because all members of a MWC are crucial for its success. In the political arena, however, political programs are often highly relevant cases and coalitions are connected with respect to an ideological space, which can imply that the winning coalition is not minimal. A number of corresponding coalition models have been developed with respect to the spatial model and should be discussed in this context. Manfred J. Holler See also Core of a Game; Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power; Minimal Winning Coalition; Public Goods Index; Simple Games every constituent feature of coercion that has been proposed. One reason why coercion is a matter of concern to many authors is because it means that someone is being made to do something against his or her will. This formulation, however, is somewhat misleading because in many cases it can still be said that, in a very basic sense, it is still the coerced who chooses to undertake that particular course of action. Certainly, in a case of coercion, the coercer has influenced this choice, but exactly what kind of influence has to be exercised for the influence to constitute coercion is a matter of vehement debate. This formulation does explain, however, why coercion is often regarded as the opposite of freedom— which is the traditional view—and why some others have favored presenting it primarily as the antipode of autonomy. The Concept of Coercion Further Readings Holler, M. J. (Ed.). (1997). The logic of multiparty systems. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer Academic. Holler, M. J., & Widgrén, M. (1999). The value of a coalition is power. Homo Oeconomicus, 15, 485–501. Reprinted in Notizie di Politeia (2000), 59, 14–28. Leiserson, M. (1968). Factions and coalitions in one-party Japan: An interpretation based on the theory of games. American Political Science Review, 62, 770–787. Miller, N. R. (1984). Coalition formation and political outcomes: A critical note. In M. J. Holler (Ed.), Coalitions and collective action (pp. 259–265). Wuerzburg, Germany: Physica-Verlag. Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. COERCION, ANALYTIC The concept of coercion plays an important role in many political, moral, and legal theories. Since Robert Nozick’s 1969 paper “Coercion,” the concept has become an important object of study in its own right, whereas before then, coercion was mainly analyzed as part of broader philosophical theories. There seems to be little consensus about the proper analysis of the concept at present because disagreement persists about practically The Social Nature of Coercion Coercion is a phenomenon that only occurs in a social, political, or interpersonal setting. In a case of coercion, a certain person, A, coerces another person, B, to perform a specific action, X. Both actors in this relation are generally deemed to be persons or collectives. Other entities such as animals or natural disasters may force or perhaps compel a person to do something, but this is generally not referred to as coercion. Similarly, animals (and perhaps even inanimate objects) can be forced, but not coerced. To coerce someone is to exercise power over him or her. This is clearly exemplified by the paradigm exemplar of coercion: the highwayman A threatens to shoot his victim B unless B hands over B’s purse. One of the less-contested features of coercion is that it is necessarily successful. A can only have coerced B if B actually performs the action A wanted B to perform. In the case of a threat (as in the highwayman example), A gets B to perform action X by negatively influencing the attractiveness of all other courses of action open to B. Threats, Offers, and Physical Coercion Some have argued that this is the essential feature of coercion, and that therefore only threats can coerce. The main problem for those who limit Coercion, Analytic the scope of coercion to threats is to determine the appropriate definition of what constitutes a threat. The standard way of tackling this question is to argue for some kind of baseline. If, as a result of the threat, B’s alternatives to X fall below this baseline, B is said to be coerced, whereas otherwise B is said to have chosen to do X freely or voluntarily. A large number of such baselines are possible, such as the course of events in which A did nothing, the course of events in which A did what A normally does, the course of events in which A acted as A may be expected to act, or the course of events in which A acted as A should have acted. The idea that coercion always (either implicitly or explicitly) implies a threat is challenged from two sides. Some wish to accommodate cases of what is sometimes called physical coercion, too; others argue that certain kinds of offers can be just as coercive as threats. Physical coercion covers cases where A makes it physically impossible for B not to do X. This may be achieved by direct application of physical force or by other means that make actions physically impossible, such as imprisonment. Opponents of this view often argue that in such cases B does not really do X. The position that offers may also constitute coercion is popular among those who regard B’s ability to resist A’s effort to make B perform X as the central feature of coercion. One way to address the issue of inability to resist is to focus on the effect of A’s efforts on B’s will; another is to analyze the nature of the options open to B. In this latter approach, the unavailability of (acceptable) alternatives is regarded as a fundamental feature of coercion. If B is in a deplorable situation and A offers B a way to alleviate B’s plight, then B may have just as little choice but to do X as B would in the situation where the unacceptability of the alternatives to X is the result of a threat by A. Usually, however, the unavailability of (acceptable) alternatives is merely regarded as a necessary condition, not a sufficient one. A central problem for this approach, which relies on the availability of alternatives, is to satisfactorily determine what constitutes a genuine or acceptable alternative. Moralized Versus Nonmoralized Accounts of Coercion A particularly prominent issue within the debate about the proper description of coercion centers 109 around the question whether it is possible to determine if someone is coerced without referring to a specific moral theory. Those who claim this is impossible thus advocate a moralized account of coercion. Moralized theories of coercion may be primarily concerned with B’s situation, arguing that B is coerced if it cannot be morally expected of B that he or she will bear the consequences of not doing X. Alternatively, theorists may focus on A, appealing to the immorality of A’s putting B in such a position, or of A’s taking advantage of the position B is in. However, a number of philosophers strongly oppose the idea of invoking a specific normative theory to identify cases of coercion, claiming that this is a purely factual matter or that it has to be a purely factual matter if coercion is to play any significant role in moral, political, or legal theories. One of the main challenges faced by advocates of moralized accounts of coercion is to accommodate cases of justified coercion in their theory, whereas those arguing in favor of a nonmoralized theory of coercion are more hardpressed by the challenge of adequately distinguishing coercing someone from other kinds of forcing or compelling. The Relevance of Coercion Coercion and Responsibility One of the main interests in coercion, in both moral and legal theory, stems from its alleged effects on a person’s responsibility for his or her actions. A person who is coerced is often regarded as not being responsible for the actions the person thus performs. This feature especially interested a considerable number of the earlier philosophers working on coercion. More recently, however, this relation between coercion and responsibility has been increasingly questioned. When analyzing coercion and its alleged responsibility negating effects, much depends on how “not being responsible for one’s actions” is interpreted. In the strictest sense of the term, coercion is regarded as a ground for excusing a person for his or her actions. The person’s actions are still considered wrong, but no personal blame is to be ascribed to the person. However, except for extreme cases, as when shock causes a person to lose control over his or her actions, it is unclear why coercion would have this effect on a person’s 110 Coercion, Analytic responsibility. As long as a person’s deliberative capacities remain intact, there seems to be little of special relevance in the presence of coercion that would explain why the person cannot be held accountable for the choice he or she makes, constrained though the person’s range of choices may be. A less rigid interpretation of not being responsible regards coercion as having a justificatory effect on a person’s actions, rather than an exculpatory one. Whereas it would normally be regarded as wrong to act in a certain way, the presence of coercion now makes it morally or legally acceptable to act that way. This implies that the “normal” moral or legal consequences are no longer to be applied to the person who performed the action, so some authors claim that this amounts to the person not being held responsible. The Wrongfulness of Coercion Although most authors agree that a certain level of coercion is often unavoidable, it is often deemed a necessary evil at best. Advocates of a moralized conception of coercion capitalize on this negative connotation of the term, using the fact that it can be seen as one of the features by which being coerced can be distinguished from merely being forced as support for their claim that this negative moral content is inherent to the concept of coercion. Whereas being forced to do something applies to many instances of human life, being coerced is immediately associated with some kind of injustice or wrongfulness. Some have described coercion as hostile to the individual, emphasizing that a coerced person is made to do something that does not suit the person’s own goals, but rather those of the coercer. In Kantian terms, the coercer uses the coerced purely as a means and fails to regard the coerced as a being with purposes of his or her own. In a perverted way, however, many kinds of coercion use precisely this fact that the coerced is a rational being who pursues his or her own interests by providing the coerced with practical imperatives that make him or her choose to act in accordance with the interests of the coercer. Another issue that is sometimes used to explain the wrongfulness of coercion is that it harms the coerced by taking away his or her freedom. This concerns not so much freedom understood as the (immediate) range of options for actions open to the individual—because those do not have to be affected by coercion—as freedom understood as the things the coerced can achieve by his or her choices of action. When confronted with a robber requesting one’s purse, for example, one can choose to give the robber the money or not. This range of options would be the same had the robber requested it without the presence of a gun; the (probable) results of the respective actions are very much affected by the gun’s presence, though. The coerced can no longer achieve the results or goals that were open to him or her before the coercer interfered, and the coerced must now subordinate the execution of his or her previous plans to the demands of the coercer. Because the coerced can no longer attain what he or she could before, the welfare of the coerced is typically reduced by coercion. Although this decline in welfare may be obvious in many cases of coercion, it remains problematic to explain the questionable morality of coercion purely by reference to its effect on the coerced’s welfare or well-being. Many cases of paternalism, for example, are also instances of coercion, and whatever the merits or demerits of paternalistic intervention, it need not be the case that either the immediate welfare or the long-term prospects of executing his or her own plans are diminished by the coerced being subjected to coercion of this kind at present; they might well be furthered by it. Given these problems, some have argued that coercion is not to be regarded as something that is absolutely wrong, but merely as prima facie wrong. As shown earlier, coercion often has negative effects on a person’s welfare or tends to harm his or her prospects, and it often signifies a lack of respect for the autonomy of the coerced, which provides us with a prima facie reason not to engage in it. Only when specific justifications can be given is it permissible to use coercive means. Despite having a certain initial degree of plausibility, the problem with this approach is that it merely postpones the question about the wrongfulness of coercion, focusing exclusively on first impressions. Furthermore, the prima facie approach only considers the instrumental qualities of coercion and disregards the possibility that the wrongness of coercion is to be found in its intrinsic value. According to this latter view, part of the moral significance of coercion is related to its inherent qualities, so that its wrongness may Coercion and Power be more fundamental than is a mere tendency to lead to morally undesirable results. The Coerciveness of the Law Laws are often regarded as coercive. Laws are designed to ensure that people exhibit a certain behavior, and they aim to achieve this compliance irrespective of the person’s agreement to that behavior or willingness to so comply. That laws are backed by sanctions indicates their coercive nature. Whether laws are necessarily coercive is debated, but in many instances, the law coerces those who are unwilling to abide by the rules to obey them nonetheless. The coerciveness of law is often unavoidable. Without the level of compliance ensured by the sanctions attached to breaking the law, it would be impossible for a society to function properly. Actually, the law often reduces the number of instances of coercion between individual citizens, protecting the weaker members of society from would-be aggressors. Most approaches to coercion have little difficulty in showing the coercive nature of unjust laws; however, when laws are just, problems often arise, especially for those advocating a moralized concept of coercion because they are bound to maintain both that something immoral is happening (otherwise it cannot be coercion under such a conception) and that it is moral at the same time (because it is just). Some appeal to other morally relevant factors outweighing the moral wrongness of the coercive act to explain this apparent contradiction, claiming that the lesser of two evils remains an evil nonetheless. This solution, however, remains open to the criticism that it cannot be morally wrong to do the best thing possible, and hence, that in such cases, coercion is not wrong. Others have denied that just laws are coercive at all. Just laws are in accordance with morality, so those individuals who are constrained by just laws remain fully free and uncoerced because none of their rights have been violated or because the just laws are the laws they would have willingly abided by had they known better. This position is highly problematic, however, and not just because it seems to presuppose an objective morality. Those who object to certain laws and in no way wish to abide by them, but do so nonetheless purely for fear of reprisal, seem to be 111 coerced by them, independently of whether or not such institutions can be justified. The thus-silenced political activist seems to be coerced, for instance, whether sufficient reason can be given to justify restrictions on his freedom of speech. Jan-Willem van der Rijt See also Coercion and Power; Domination; Threat; Throffer Further Readings Pennock, J. R., & Chapman, J. W. (Eds.). (1972). Nomos XIV: Coercion. Chicago: Aldine Atherton. Wertheimer, A. (1987). Coercion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. COERCION AND POWER Coercion can be thought of as a subset of power, but it is an important subset. We frequently think about the power of some agents over others as coercive. Weberian definitions of power often take the form, “Agent A has power over agent B to the extent that A can get B to do something that B would not otherwise do.” Such definitions of power can be seen as synonyms for coercion. Agent A gets B to do something B otherwise would not do through some kind of coercion. However, the definition as it stands allows for the possibility that A persuades B to do something B would not otherwise do, and persuasion is not necessarily coercive. Agent A might provide some information for B that leads B to want to do something for B’s own interests, or for the interests of everyone including A. Indeed Agent A might give B a reason for doing something by making it advantageous for B to take that action. In other words, Agent A might pay B to take that action, or reward B in some other way. Agents might have powers simply because they are rich and can pay people to do things for them. The problem for consideration of coercion in this regard is distinguishing coercion from market exchange or persuasion. We shall examine this problem first before widening the discussion to other areas of coercive activity and the relations between coercion, power, and other social concepts. 112 Coercion and Power Incentive Structures Generally speaking, we can say that one agent, agent A, can get another, agent B, to do something that B would not otherwise do by changing B’s incentive structure. Thus, the power, or social power, of one agent A over another agent B is the ability of A to deliberately alter the incentive structure of B. We say deliberately because A might alter the incentive structure of B without intending to do so. Indeed, to a minor extent we can do all sorts of things that change the incentive structures of others without intending to. Buying the last cake in a shop means the next person has to buy something else instead, but we do not ordinarily consider such market activity to be acts of power, let alone coercion. Incentive structures can be altered in four main ways. First, persuasion: agent A might persuade B that an option in B’s opportunity set is not what it might appear, so raising or lowering it in B’s estimation. Second, A might make a side payment to B, thus making one alternative more valuable because it also comes with an extra reward. In the literature, this is usually called an offer. Third, A might make a negative side payment to B, thus lowering an alternative in the estimation of B. Here, A will ensure that if B makes a particular choice B must also suffer a cost. In the literature, this is usually called a threat. Finally, agent A might combine an offer with a threat, simultaneously lowering one alternative and raising another alternative. In the literature, this fourth possibility is usually called a throffer—a combination of a threat and an offer. We can see how these work by considering B’s opportunity set, represented here as three alternatives within a set {N}. First, consider that B’s opportunity set is {x y z} (where the symbol “” is read as “prefers to”). Persuasion simply means that at least one of the items has changed places with another, thus if agent A persuades B that x is in fact a poor option, then it might sink to the bottom of order, thus {y z x}. This might come about because of information given about x or about any of the two other items. However, we can also represent this change in the preference ordering in the opportunity set by breaking down the alternatives into their component parts. If we take the original ordering and suggest that new information leads us to, say, believe there are other consequences of choosing the preferred alternative, we can leave the original ordering intact, but new alternatives come into play because of that new information. Thus information about item x might move it down the order because it is associated with some other consequence: {x y z} becomes (x y z x }, and because we now believe that x must come with then the choice becomes y, as we saw earlier. Similarly, if agent B is persuaded that y is a better option because it comes with addition , then y becomes the preferred option because it is y : {y x y z); or we could combine both types of persuasion to give us {y x y z x }. This might appear an odd way of representing the changed ordering of alternatives within an opportunity set, rather than simply switching the order originally shown. However, it demonstrates the problem of distinguishing coercion from other ways of changing opportunity sets. Consider the following three ways of representing the changing of the ordering of B’s preferences from the original {x y z}. Threat: (x y z x } Offer: {y x y z) Throffer: {y x y z x }. We can see here that the representation of threats, offers, and throffers simply looks like different sorts of persuasion; normally, however, we would think there is an important difference. In terms of persuasion, agent A would simply be pointing out the consequences of choosing item x or item y (with associated costs or rewards ); in the case of threats, offers, and throffers, we would think that these associated costs and benefits are brought about by agent A because of the choice of agent B. In other words, persuasion is a prediction about consequences that convinces agent B, but threats, offers, and throffers are more than mere predictions, they are consequences that agent A will causally bring about contingent on the choice of B. To be able to convince B to choose differently, agent A must provide convincing evidence of the consequences of the potential choices. Similarly, Agent A’s threats and offers must credible. Credibility places constraints on how good offers can be or how dire threats can be. If agent B simply does not believe that A will do what he or she says—the Coercion and Power reward is too costly for A, or the threat unrealistically dire, then B will not be persuaded to act differently. Offers Versus Threats There is an important asymmetry between threats and offers. Offers cost more when they succeed— agent A must pay B when B complies with what A wants; threats cost more when they fail—agent A only needs to carry out his threat when B fails to comply with what A wants. Again, this points up the importance of making threats and offers credible. If this were not the case, there would always be the incentive to make them as high as possible; there would be no limit on the cost of reward or threat. We can illustrate the credibility of threats with the example of punishment in modern states. We might think that the strongest incentives for citizens to obey the law would be to make the punishment for breaking the law as severe as possible. However, if the penalties are too great, then juries might be reluctant to find guilty those charged with crimes. This proved the case in the 19th century where juries were reluctant to find guilty defendants charged with minor crimes such as stealing apples because the penalties were so high. The asymmetry between threats and offers has certain behavioral consequences. If the cost of a threat or an offer to A is the same, then which is made depends on the likelihood of compliance. The higher the probability that B will comply with the incentive, the more likely it will be in form of a threat. The higher the likelihood is that B will not comply, the more likely the incentive will be in form of an offer. This is so because if A’s threat is successful, A will not actually bear any further costs, whereas A must pay if an offer is accepted. Thus, it is always in B’s interests to indicate that he or she will not back down to threats but will comply with offers of much lower cost to A. In that sense, it can be rational to be stubborn, even when threats of noncompliance seem to bear high costs for B—as long as those costs are also high for A. The Coercive Offer Some claim that capitalism is a power system that consists of coercive offers. The idea is that under 113 capitalism workers are offered contracts through which they sell their labor power. Here employers get workers to do something they would not otherwise do, namely work for the employers, by making an offer, namely a wage or salary. However, Karl Marx suggested that workers are exploited wage slaves and the offers they receive in compensation for working are really a form of coercion. How can this be? We can approach the idea by thinking of the notion contained in The Godfather where Don Corleone says, “Make him an offer he can’t refuse.” The amusing irony of the phrase is precisely that offers are, by their very nature, things that one can refuse. Slavery is a condition that an agent cannot get out of (except through death): the slave has no freedom. Wage slavery is an extension, in that although one might refuse any simple offer of a job, one cannot refuse all offers (unless one accepts death through starvation). So any offer of a wage might be refused with regard to other offers, but wage offers overall are coercive. A wage offer is coercive if and only if (a) an alternative “pre-proposal” state of affairs that the worker would prefer to the actual one in which the employer has made the offer is feasible, and (b) the employer (together with others) prevents this feasible pre-proposal state of affairs from obtaining. In other words, capitalists maintain capitalism, high profits, and great inequality by ensuring that the situation where workers could be paid more and profits kept reasonable is not allowed to occur. Two elements of this analysis are important: first, that there is a feasible alternative and second, that the feasible alternative is being blocked by capitalists. One might think that the coercion involved in a coercive offer, as described here, is being coerced into the situation of having to accept at least one job offer. We can compare this to the slave, who might be offered the choice of jobs by his master, but still has to perform some task. The slave cannot walk away from the master nor can the worker avoid ever having to work. The important element in both cases is that it is the slave-master—or capitalists—that ensure it is impossible for the agent (the slave or the worker) to alter the situation. Some argue that coercive offers cannot exist. They cannot exist precisely because the idea of an offer one cannot refuse is ironic. The meaning of an offer is something that one can turn down. 114 Coercion and Power Coercion is being forced into something. This leads us to an important aspect of coercion—its relationship to liberty. Jeremy Bentham defined liberty as the absence of coercion, defining the latter as being compelled or constrained in one’s actions. One is free to the extent that one is not coerced. A coercive offer—if “offer” does indeed entail that one has a choice whether or not to accept is meaningless in the same sense as “being forced to be free”—is meaningless. Importantly, some people deny the meaninglessness of both phrases. We can approach this issue by considering a paradigm example of coercion much discussed in the literature: the highwayman demanding “your money or your life.” Is this demand an offer or a threat? When the highwayman says “your money or your life,” is the highwayman altering one of the alternatives in your opportunity set or adding to them? Some would say the highwayman has altered them. Before the highwayman, you can keep your money and live; after the highwayman has uttered his cry, you have two alternatives: either hand over the money and live or keep the money and die. In other words, one highly valued alternative has been replaced by two low-value ones. Now one is coerced into handing over one’s money to survive. One has lost the freedom to keep the money and live. Others offer a different analysis. Assuming one can give away one’s money (that is what owning it means) and one could commit suicide, the person has, before the highwayman intervention, the alternatives of keeping-your-money-and-your-life; notkeeping-your-money-and-keeping-your-life; keeping-your-money-and-not-keeping-your-life; and notkeeping-your-money-and-not-keeping-your-life. The highwayman’s arrival on the scene, according to this second analysis, causes the first alternative to disappear, while the others remain. Dominant Strategies and Coercion Actually, both the standard analyses are misleading. The reality of the highwayman situation is you have “no choice,” in the sense that you have a dominant strategy of handing over your money. A dominant strategy in game theory is defined as any strategy that is preferable to all other strategies. If you do not hand over your money on his demand, the highwayman takes it after killing you. In other words, all the alternatives where you keep your money disappear after his intervention. Hence, you do have only two alternatives: “hand over your money” or “not hand over your money”— which is equivalent to “not die” or “die” because they are conjunctives. Handing over your money dominates not handing it over because you lose it anyway; by handing it over, you get to keep your life (which we assume is preferable to dying). The dominant strategy determines coercion. We might say that in any threatening situation a person could stand up to the threats, but if one has a dominant strategy forced on one then one is coerced. So we define coercion as occurring in any situation created by the coercer, where the coerced agent has a dominant strategy that is to the advantage of the coercer but to the coerced agent’s disadvantage relative to the status quo ante. This way of thinking about coercion as being in a situation where one has a dominant strategy to do as the coercer wishes, and where that situation has been created by the coercer, fits with modern republican ideas about the nature of freedom as being non-domination. The slave example is key for republicans. A slave might have a great deal of personal freedom allowed to him or her by the slave’s master. However, that freedom only exists because of the latter’s grace and whim and can be arbitrarily removed at any time. In that sense, doing what the master wishes is a dominant strategy for the slave because not obeying has dire consequences. When the master is indifferent to what the slave does, the slave does then have a freedom, within the constraints of the master’s indifference. But all this freedom means is that the slave’s dominant strategy gives the slave a great deal of leeway. And this leeway exists only through the grace and whim of the master. There are many means by which coercion might be obtained. We have mostly been considering physical coercion, such as the highwayman forcing one to hand over one’s money at gunpoint, or where the state has a monopoly of legitimate force to ensure people pay taxes, abide by the laws, and so on. Here, the state creates a situation where the dominant strategy (for most people most of the time) is to obey the law. Coercion might be psychological, however. Blackmail plays on the fears of the person being blackmailed and “emotional Coercion and Power blackmail” plays on people’s fears of being rejected by others. This might occur in friendships or emotional relationships where one person threatens to withdraw his or her love, kindness, or friendship unless the other person accedes to the first person’s demands. The threat of disapproval from one’s compatriots or close companions, as in denouncing people as traitors, is also a form of emotional blackmail. States can create such coercion through propaganda, most obviously seen in the Soviet Union and China. The Soviet Union held show trials where psychological pressures were placed on (often high-ranking) communist officials to admit to crimes; in China during the “Thought Reform” campaign (1951–1952) and the “Cultural Revolution” (1966) people were denounced by others, often children, to make them think in terms of communist strategy. In the latter case, this might be thought to be ideological coercion, and in that the situation was deliberately set up by the authorities, it does seem to deserve the title of coercion. However, ideological coercion is often used in contexts where it is not clear there is a coercer. Marx described religion as the opium of the people. The idea is that by concentrating on rewards in heaven people accept hell on earth. We accept the conditions of capitalism and wage slavery because we accept that there is no alternative. We live by an ideology that colors our thoughts and leads us not to recognize that we are being coerced. However, as we saw in the discussion of coercive wage offers, unless there are clearly agents who set up the situation that leads to an ideology that causes our dominant strategies to be to obey the rules of capitalism, it is not clear that the situation is coercive. A similar analysis can be offered of “cultural coercion” where people try to conform to their identity group—dressing and behaving in prescribed ways become dominant strategies. However, if I choose to dress like others, am I really coerced? Probably the most conformist humans are teenagers in Western societies (despite their reputation for being rebels): they tend to dress, talk, and behave similarly to those in their peer group. And if teenagers move from one area to another, they usually mix with those whom they resemble or soon take on the mores and conventions of the group they join. Is this coercion? It is not clear how coercive cultural coercion really is. Without an agent—the coercer—who sets up the 115 coercive situation, can we really speak of these situations as coercive ones? We might see teenagers as having dominant strategies to dress alike, but there is no particular person who has forced the situation they are in. Without such a person, there is no coercion. In that sense, ideological, cultural, and even economic coercion should be seen as no more than metaphors and not a correct analytic reading of the situation. Seen as the opposite of liberty, coercion is almost universally regarded as normatively bad. However, the coercive nature of the state is not necessarily seen as bad. In that sense, coercion is not intrinsically wrongful. One way of considering the matter is whether coercion is a violation of someone’s rights. The coercive powers of the state would not be wrongful if they do not abrogate citizen’s rights; indeed quite the reverse is true, as the justification of the state having a monopoly on legitimate violence, or coercion, is to protect rights. To the extent that laws are backed by the coercive forces of the state, and to the extent those laws are designed to protect individual rights to liberty, property, and the person, then the coercive force of the state is not wrongful. We might extend this analysis of coercion to other legitimate uses. Parents might use threats of loss of privileges, even some emotional blackmail, in the interests of their children. Such coercive practices might be considered legitimate. To be sure, one might argue it would be better if parents use not coercive force but other means to encourage their children to act in their best interest, but most parents would recognize that some degree of threats and coercion, however mild, is often required. In other relationships too, coercion might be justified on the grounds of the well-being and interests of the person being coerced. Again, we might recognize that coercion does involve a loss of liberty, but liberty is only one good among others and sometime a loss of liberty might be justified by another gain in well-being or interests. Conclusion Coercion occurs at many different levels. Seeing it as the obverse of liberty, we can see it anywhere we see lack of liberty: we can see it in coercive personal relationships; and we can see it in social and economic relationships within the state and at the international 116 Coleman, James S. level. Threats such as those posed by terrorism or by one state threatening another are more obvious examples of coercion, but coercion can be seen in a more diffuse and dispersed manner through all types of relationship. It is best seen in terms of the deliberate creating of a situation by one agent to ensure another has a dominant strategy to do as the first wishes. Thus, the highwayman example (as explained here rather than as is usually discussed) provides the paradigm situation of coercion. Keith Dowding See also Blackmail; Coercion, Analytic; Domination; Exploitation; Freedom; Subjugation; Threats; Throffers Further Readings Dowding, K. (1991). Rational choice and political power. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar Wertheimer, A. (2004). Coercion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Zimmerman, D. (1981). Coercive wage offers. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10(2), 121–145. COLEMAN, JAMES S. (1926–1995) James Coleman is widely acknowledged as one of the greatest empirical sociologists of the 20th century. His great work was Foundations of Sociological Theory (1990), but his work on education was very influential, if controversial. He pioneered the use of formal theorizing in sociology, publishing An Introduction to Mathematical Sociology (1964) and Mathematics of Collective Action (1973), formed the Rational Actor group within the International Sociological Association, and founded the associated journal Rationality and Society in 1988. Coleman’s work intersects with the concept of power in a number of interrelated ways. As well as a formal approach to power with the index named after him, he recognized that power was a concept of immense social importance. His first book, Community Conflict (1957), is a series of case studies examining conflict at the local level. He saw that crosscutting cleavages within the social structure help ameliorate conflict, a process that is also aided by stable social structures and organizations. In a sense, he was a traditional normative pluralist, believing that multiple centers of power enable efficiency. He also saw structured competition within markets, governments, and the state as promoting efficiency. He believed competition within education was a good thing, though he strongly believed in equality of opportunity in education. He was commissioned to write a report on educational equality in the United States, which was published in 700 pages in 1966. He argued that educational attainment had more to do with the socioeconomic status of children than with the differences in school funding then existing. This led the statistically incompetent to misunderstand his argument that differences in school do not matter to educational attainment—hence the controversy. He also argued that black students would benefit from racially mixed schooling, which led to bussing, though he later controversially argued that bussing had failed because white parents removed their children from schools where blacks were sent. Coleman’s other early work included an important study on medical diffusion. A central plank of his pluralism was that efficiency requires multiple sources of information. He found that doctors who were well connected into local medical networks adopted new drugs more swiftly than did those who were not. The idea of diffusion here has been enormously influential in later network studies, globalization, and organizational analysis. Coleman was interested in the unintended consequences of social policy, such as the white flight caused by bussing. He used formal mathematics in his social theorizing (he had been trained in chemical engineering). His formal work led him to considering the cooperative game-theoretic ways of measuring power, and he created the Coleman Index for measuring the power of coalitions. His later work was informed by rational choice theory and the methodology of microeconomics. He saw collective action as the key problem for social theory, perceiving that people working together can achieve more than can those working alone. Thus, he had an interest in measuring the power of individuals as collectives or coalitions. In both Introduction to Mathematical Sociology and The Mathematics of Collective Action, he uses mathematical models to theorize about attitude change, diffusion, voting Coleman Index behavior, group contagion, and other social processes. The ways in which social structures affect human behavior led him to use rational choice methods of interpreting human behavior under constraint. His Foundations of Sociological Theory applies rational choice theory to social behavior, demonstrating how individual choices create social outcomes and how those choices are affected by social norms and the pressures of interpersonal relationships. He first models social exchanges where individuals interact in ways that resemble contracting for personal gain. So, for example, he sees norms as a form of rights allocation where the norm-induced behavior of one actor is controlled by others. Here, the norms benefit those other than the actor himself or herself (though overall the actor may gain as well), the norm-controlled behavior cannot be governed by contractual social exchange, and a system of sanctions exists to keep norms in place. In that way, norm-induced behavior is rationalized. Coleman sees trust as a form of social credit that exists especially when mutual rewards are high and is kept in place when there is a strong third-party “guarantor” in place. His work has been extended by network analysis and game theory. Coleman is perhaps best known for his insights on social capital, though somewhat ironically given its use because Coleman believes social capital is only a metaphor that covers various other processes analyzed in Foundations. He defines social capital by its function of facilitating individual action within the social structure. Like other forms of capital, social capital is something that makes other things unachievable without it. Unlike capital, social capital inheres in the structure of relations between persons and among persons and is not fungible. Coleman first used the concept in his work on education. His emphasis on the significance of social background led him to suggest that social capital was an important resource. For Coleman, social capital is the networks of relationships that people have, bringing benefits in helping people overcome barriers to action. The great advantage that the higher social classes have is simply the networks they have as a class. But ethnic and other groups can develop social capital as they help each other. A poor urban black will have greater social capital within his or her community than will a richer white person who found himself or herself in the neighborhood. 117 Coleman saw that the collective action problem was the key problem for society and the key issue in understanding lack of personal powers. Many elements go into overcoming collective action problems, including information, network resources, and reciprocal bargaining contracts. Keith Dowding See also Bargaining; Capital, Neoclassical; Coalition Theory; Coleman Index; Collective Action Problem; Coordination; Exchange Theory; Power Indices; Social Capital; Unintended Consequences Further Readings Coleman, J. S. (1990). Foundations of sociological theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Marsden, P. V. (2005). The sociology of James S. Coleman. Annual Reviews of Sociology, 31, 1–24. COLEMAN INDEX In 1971, three indices of a priori voting power were introduced by James S. Coleman: the Prevent Action index (g ), the Initiate Action index (g ), and the Index of Collectivity to Act (A). The first two indices, suitably normalized, coincide with both the normalized Banzhaf index and the normalized Penrose index (see Banzhaf Voting Power Measure, Penrose Voting Power Measure). However, the Coleman indices have a greater conceptual value because they measure different aspects of the power to make decisions and to veto. The definitions of the three Coleman indices (in absolute and normalized versions) are presented here and illustrate the links between the other previously mentioned indices. An example follows. The Index of Collectivity to Act (A) measures the ability of a given collectivity to make decisions, that is, the potentiality that an act or bill has of being passed. In the collectivity of n members, there are 2n possible coalitions. The Index of Collectivity to Act is the quotient between the number of winning coalitions (i.e., the number of voting outcomes that lead to a decision) and 2n: v A5 n . 2 118 Coleman Index The essential element in the construction of the other two indices is the concept of “swing.” A swing for the i-th member of the collectivity is a pair of coalitions ðS; S\figÞ such that S is a winning coalition and S\fig is losing. The number of swings of each member i is denoted by ci. The Prevent Action index (g ) is a measure of the blocking power of each member in the given collectivity. For each member i, the Prevent Action Index g i is the quotient between the number of the member’s swings ci and the number of the winning coalitions of the collectivity: ci gi5 . v The Initiate Action index (g ) is a measure of the power of each member to have his proposals accepted by the collectivity. For each member I, the Initiate Action index gi is the quotient between the number of the member’s swings ci and the number n l52 2v of the losing coalitions of the collectivity, that is, of the outcomes that do not produce a decision: ci gi 5 . l The absolute Banzhaf index coincides with the Penrose index r. Both the prevent action and the initiate action indices can be regarded as rescalings of (and then of r). In fact, 0 gi 5 gi 5 b i ri , 5 2A A indices of Banzhaf and Penrose, in the group of the I-power indices (power as influence). For both g and g , the sum extended to all the n members S gj ; S gj j2N j2N one. Then the normalized indices are considered g i , gi . S gj S gj j2N j2N The normalized indices coincide with one another and with the normalized Banzhaf (–Penrose) index. However, the absolute indices offer more information than normalized ones do because the latter are leveled, much as is a drawing compared with a three-dimensional form. An Example Assume a parliament is composed of three parties (labeled 1, 2, 3), which have neither prejudice against forming, nor inclination to form, a coalition between them. Let (2, 1, 1) be the respective seats. Suppose that an act can be approved only if the favorable votes are equal to or greater than 3 (simple majority). In this case, the winning coalitions are {1, 2}, {1, 3} and {1, 2, 3}, so v53 . Party 1 is decisive for all winning coalitions (without party 1, all these coalitions become losing) so it has three swings. Parties 2 and 3 are decisive only for one coalition ({1, 2} and {1, 3}), respectively, so they have only one swing each. Thus c1 53 , c2 51, c3 51, and 0 bi ri . 5 2ð12AÞ ð12AÞ A¼ 3 3, 3 ¼ 8 2 g1 51 , g2 5g3 51=3 , In particular, both g and g coincide with (and then with r) if the number of winning coalitions is equal to the number of the loosing coalitions (i.e., v5l52n21 ) because in this case there is no difference between the power to prevent action and the power to initiate action. Moreover, the absolute Banzhaf index (and then r) coincides with the harmonic mean of g and g : 1 1 1 . 0 bi 52ri 5 1 2 . gi gi in general is greater than g1 5 1 1 3 3 5 . 5 , g2 5g3 5 3 2 3 5 2 3 5 3 Cesarino Bertini and Izabella Stach See also Banzhaf Value; Coleman, James S.; I-Power; Power Indices; Power to Initiate Action and Power to Prevent Action; P-Power; Voting Paradoxes; Voting Power; Weighted Majority Game Further Readings Dan S. Felsenthal and Moshé Machover classi fied A, g , and g as well as the (not normalized) Banzhaf, J. F. (1965). Weighted voting doesn’t work: A mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review, 19, 317–343. Collective Action Problem Coleman, J. S. (1971). Control of collectivities and the power of collectivity to act. In B. Lieberman (Ed.), Social choice (pp. 269–300). New York: Gordon and Breach. Felsenthal, D., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power: Theory and practice, problems and paradoxes. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. Felsenthal, D. S., & Machover, M. (2005). Voting power measurement: A story of misreinvention. Social Choice and Welfare, 25(2–3), 485–506. Penrose, L. S. (1946). The elementary statistics of majority voting. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 109, 53–57. COLLECTIVE ACTION PROBLEM To further their interests, individuals must sometimes act collectively. It is easy to assume that individuals with shared—that is, collective—interests will jointly pursue those interests: that workers will form unions and lobby for higher wages, that states will agree to cut carbon dioxide emissions to preserve the environment, and that commuters will use public transport to reduce traffic congestion. Yet as each of these examples shows, collective action can actually be quite problematic. Workers do form unions and states do sometimes sign environmental treaties, but it cannot simply be assumed that collective action will occur. Free riding is one particular problem that can stymie collective action. In situations where the benefits of collective action accrue to all the members of the group regardless of who contributed to its provision, individuals may reason that they are better off not contributing to the collective cause and instead free riding on the efforts of others. The problem is that if everyone in a group reasons in this way, then no collective action will occur, and all the members of the group may end up worse off relative to when they share the costs of collective action. The collective action problem was clearly stated by Mancur Olson in The Logic of Collective Action: Any group or organization, large or small, works for some collective benefit that by its very nature will benefit all the members of that group in question. Though all the members of a group 119 therefore have a common interest in obtaining this collective benefit, they have no common interest in paying the cost of providing that collective good. Each would prefer that the others pay the entire cost, and ordinarily would get any benefit provided whether he had borne part of the cost or not. (Olson, 1965, p. 21) Free riding is a particularly important source of collective action problems. There are, however, other reasons why collective action might or might not occur. Just a few will be mentioned here: Recognition of Interests. Groups will fail to act collectively if, for whatever reason, they fail to recognize that they have a shared set of interests that require collective action. Group Homogeneity. The more homogeneous a group is, the more likely it is that the members of the group will recognize any shared interests and overcome disputes about how to distribute the costs of collective action. Group Interactiveness. If the members of a group already interact frequently, it will be easier to monitor and so punish free riding. The members of a group who interact frequently may also already trust each other to act fairly in the absence of any monitoring. Opposition. The existence of a rival group can sometimes spur a group to act collectively. Alternatively, an opposition group may be able to undermine attempts at collective action. Collective Action, Power, and Luck Power is often defined as the ability to overcome resistance. Explicit collective action is not always required for an individual to exercise power and secure his or her goals. The owner of a large corporation who is considering whether to invest in a country may, for example, be able to secure, through direct negotiations with the government, a series of favorable tax concessions without having to form any explicit coalitions. However, such actions are a form of coalition with the government. Often, however, individuals can only acquire power by acting in explicit coalitions. Individually, farmers do not have any great power. Yet collectively, they have often been able to extract from 120 Collective Action Problem governments a range of economic privileges including subsidies, export credits, import restrictions, and price controls. There may well have been a time when governments supported farmers because the government wanted to reduce the country’s dependence on imports. Yet, more recently, it is perhaps the ability of farmers to operate collectively through such well-connected and lavishly funded groups as the National Farmers Union in the United Kingdom, the American Farm Bureau Federation, and the Fédération nationale des syndicats d’exploitants agricoles (FNSEA) in France that best explains their success. Finally, there are individuals whose powerlessness might be explained in terms of their failure to overcome collective action problems. Consider the situation of those living under a dictatorship. As successful revolutions in the Philippines (1986), Eastern Europe (1989), Serbia (2000), and Ukraine (2004–2005) have shown, only a small fraction of a country’s population needs to act collectively to topple a government. Yet, many dictatorships survive. One reason why they do so is the existence of the collective action problem. It is, as already noted, easy to assume that individuals with shared interests will act collectively in pursuit of those interests. It is also easy to assume that if a group of individuals is powerless that the group is powerless because powerful people are thwarting the group. In questioning this “blame fallacy,” Keith Dowding suggests that the powerless may sometimes be powerless because they are unlucky and that they may be unlucky because to achieve their goals they need to but are unable to act collectively. At the same time, however, one way in which people can both exercise and maintain their power is by undermining the efforts of others to act collectively. It is, in other words, an open empirical question whether the powerless are powerless because they are unlucky or whether they are powerless because powerful people are thwarting them. To see how the powerful might undermine attempts at collective action, consider, once again, the example of a dictatorship: Free Riding. Dictators can exacerbate an existing collective action problem by making it clear that they will punish those who attempt to act collectively and that they will reward those who betray the plans of others. Recognition of Interests. A dictator may also try to prevent people from recognizing that they share a collective interest in toppling the government. One way in which dictators can do so is by pursuing a policy of “divide and rule” in which the dictators use their control of the media to encourage individuals to believe that their interests are threatened by those living in different parts of the country or those who practice a different religion. Group Interactiveness. Groups that interact frequently with each other are more likely to be able to overcome a collective action problem. By either closely regulating or even dissolving institutions and spaces in which people are likely to come together— churches, sports associations, or even the family— dictators can therefore make it harder for a group to act collectively. Opposition. Finally, and most obviously, dictators can bolster their position by destroying any groups that do form. As the purges conducted by Joseph Stalin in the 1930s and Saddam Hussein in the 1980s also showed, dictators can strengthen their reputation for ruthlessness by persecuting loyal government supporters. Acting Collectively by Creating Power One way in which individuals can overcome collective action problems is by either creating or giving to an existing third party the power to punish free riding. Writing in the 17th century, during the midst of the constitutional upheavals wrought by the English Civil War, Thomas Hobbes famously argued that, when caught in a state of nature, every person would be better off if each respected each other’s property, but that everyone would be tempted to renege on any agreements reached. As a result of what we could now describe as this collective action problem, the life of a person, Hobbes concluded, would be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short.” Hobbes argued that people could eventually escape this dystopia by agreeing to establish a sovereign political authority, the Leviathan, with sufficient power to force individuals to respect each other’s property and lives. By forfeiting some of their own freedoms, or powers, and creating a Collective Action Problem body that could exercise a monopoly on the exercise of legitimate violence, individuals would be better able to achieve their interests. It is not hard to see why many people continue to proclaim the relevance of Hobbes’s analysis. In many states— Somalia and the Democratic Republic of Congo being, perhaps, the most obvious examples—the absence of a government that can command a monopoly on the use of violence has been associated with civil wars that have led to the deaths of hundreds of thousands of people. Yet it is worth briefly noting that actors other than the state can sometimes use their power to solve collective action problems. Diego Gambetta argues that weakness of the state in southern Italy during the 19th and early 20th centuries allowed the Mafia and other organized crime groups to acquire a great deal of power. This is, in one sense, obvious. The weakness of the state meant that the police and judiciary lacked the resources necessary to crush these groups. Yet there is more to Gambetta’s argument than this. The absence of a strong state in Italy was economically damaging because it raised the “transaction costs” of exchange. Because the state could not be relied on to enforce the terms of any deals, markets were paralyzed. In these circumstances, the Mafia fulfilled an important economic function by guaranteeing market trades in return for a share of the resulting profits. Collective Action and the Exploitation of the Powerful There are some groups that Olson calls “privileged,” in which one member of the group so values the collective good in which the group has a shared interest that that member is prepared to bear the entire costs of providing it himself or herself. Consider the example of a shared student apartment. Keeping the apartment clean or at least tolerably hygienic poses a potential collective action problem in that each resident has an incentive to free ride on any cleaning efforts. But if one student has a pathological hatred of squalor, that student may be willing to clean the apartment without any help from the others. The theory of hegemonic stability developed by international relations theorists in the 1980s provides a more substantive example of this basic idea 121 and allows us to link the existence of a privileged group to power. Proponents of this theory argue that a secure and prosperous international order requires the provision of collective goods such as a free-trading regime, a stable international currency, and a sense of security from invasion. In an anarchic international system in which there is no Leviathan to enforce order, the provision of these goods provides a serious collective action problem. Historically, this problem has often been resolved when a hegemonic power—once Britain but now the United States—so benefits from the existence of a stable international order that the power is prepared to bear the costs of enforcing free trade agreements, maintaining an international currency, and protecting state boundaries. The theory of hegemonic stability is, it almost goes without saying, a controversial one. Many would argue that far from providing a set of collective goods, Britain and the United States used their power to exploit the international system for their own advantage. In the context of this discussion of the relationship between collective action and power, the argument for hegemonic stability does, however, have some particularly interesting implications. First, it suggests that all the members of a group—in this case, the states in the international system—might benefit from the presence of an extremely powerful, hegemonic, state. Second, the theory suggests that, in at least this one respect, the powerless might be able to exploit the powerful by making the powerful bear most, if not all, of the costs of providing collective goods. Collective Action and Empowerment In studying collective action, political scientists are likely to focus on the circumstances in which collective action takes place and the extent to which the existence of the collective action problem disadvantages particular groups. Psychologists are more likely to focus on the distinctive personality traits exhibited by those engaged in high-intensity collective action and the effects participation has on them. One recent line of argument here is that collective action is, for many people, an empowering experience. In acting collectively, and, crucially, in acting against some other group, individuals achieve a greater sense of social identity, become more aware of the existence of other people who 122 Community Power Debate share that identity, and come to believe that they can, in however small a way, make a political difference. Consider, for example, the following statement made by a participant in the Reclaim the Streets demonstration, talking here about how the group overcame police resistance: That felt really brilliant, cos it was just . . . I don’t know, there’s something about overcoming opposition. Like if we’d just walked out of the tube station and walked straight onto the road, it wouldn’t have been as good, as having to have got round the police lines first. So it was that kind of, you know, makes you feel more like you’ve achieved something . . . if you’re left completely free to do whatever you want, it doesn’t feel as way-hey! Exciting as, the whole crowd, pulling together against some opposition and then achieving what it wants, cos you all feel this sense of unity, and purpose. (Drury, Cocking, Beale, Hanson, & Rapley, 2005, p. 316) Because those who act collectively are more likely to achieve a sense of empowerment and because those who feel empowered are more likely to engage in collective action, there is a potentially virtuous circle here. The sense of empowerment described by psychologists is, however, only likely to arise in situations where the collective action is considered by the participants themselves to have been successful. Andrew Hindmoor See also Chicken Games; Cooperation; Coordination; Dowding, Keith; Luck; Networks, Power in; Pluralism; Public Goods; Systematic Luck Further Readings Dowding, K. (1996). Power. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press. Drury, J., Cocking, C., Beale, J., Hanson, C., & Rapley, F. (2005). The phenomenology of empowerment in collective action. British Journal of Social Psychology, 44, 309–328. Gambetta, D. (1993). The Sicilian Mafia: The business of private protection. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kindleberger, C. (1981). Dominance and leadership in the international economy: Exploitation, public goods and free rides. International Studies Quarterly, 25, 242–254. Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. COLLECTIVE GOODS See Public Goods COMMUNITY POWER DEBATE The community power debate set the scene for several generations of scholarly research around the nature of power in society. In many ways, all of the central issues that continue to be discussed and debated in mainstream analyses of power were first set by the community power debate. That debate was probably first labeled as such toward the end of its first phase, in the early 1970s. First Phase In the interwar period, a number of sociological studies of small-town life in the United States were conducted. They did not, however, address questions of power directly; nevertheless, they usually identified key figures in communities, often bankers and leading businesspeople around whom much of the social and political life of communities revolved. The book that might be thought to have started the community power debate is Floyd Hunter’s Community Power Structure, published in 1953. Using a reputational method, he argued that there was a clear power elite in Atlanta (which he called “Regional City”). He argued that members of this relatively small power elite were socially and economically linked and included important businesspeople, corporate lawyers, and politicians. He viewed power as a set of interlinked power pyramids; although the same people dominated within different pyramids or issueareas, different people might be found at the head of each pyramid. At about the same time C. Wright Mills published The Power Elite (1956), arguing that the United States was dominated by a Community Power Debate political–industrial–military complex whose membership all came from the same social (and often also family) backgrounds, having attended the same schools and universities and belonging to the same clubs. Together, these two books created “elite theory” and provided the first side in the community power debate. The second side emerged through the work of Robert Dahl, whose book Who Governs?, published in 1961, examined the power structure of Dahl’s home university town of New Haven, Connecticut. Dahl and his researchers had a number of criticisms of Floyd Hunter’s methods and conclusions. The critique was that reputational methods were bound to produce lists of power elites and people who view some actors as more important than others; selecting people from those lists would simply reinforce the assumption that their colleagues and acquaintances were also powerful. Instead, Dahl chose a set of issues to study from what was being reported in the local newspapers and interviewed sets of people at all levels within those issue areas. For all the heat of the subsequent debate, Dahl’s conclusions were not that different from Hunter’s, though the manner in which they were expressed differed. Dahl also found that there were important elites who figured in different issue areas. However, he emphasized their differences rather than the fact they came from similar backgrounds. He suggested that power diffused among different competing elites in different issue areas. His pluralist view, despite similar evidence, contrasted sharply with the elite views expressed by Hunter, Mills, and others. This first stage in the community power debate differed both in methods—the reputational versus the behavioral methods—and in their conclusions, one emphasizing the elite domination and the other the plurality of centers of power. Second Phase The second stage of the debate centered around methods. Early critics of Dahl suggested that his methods were bound to miss important aspects of the power structure. Examining issues brought up in the newspapers would ignore those issues that were underground, off-message, or were, in E. E. Schattsneider’s phrase, “organized out” of political debate. Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz suggested that 123 what they called the “decisional” method of Dahl ignored “nondecisions.” These are decisions that are taken behind closed doors out of the purview of the media and public, ensuring that some interests are not represented. A second critique emerged from the neo-Marxist writer William Domhoff, who reanalyzed all the evidence collected and maintained by Dahl. Domhoff argued that Dahl’s team had identified elites who came from the same social backgrounds, belonged to the same clubs, and attended the same schools and universities; Dahl simply had not reported his elite findings. Dahl and his one-time research associates, Raymond Wolfinger and Nelson Polsby, responded by defending their behavioral and decisionist methods. They renewed their attack on reputational methods and suggested that we cannot study issues for which there is no evidence. Dahl expressed some surprise at the way his findings had been interpreted. Some textbooks still assert that pluralists claimed that power was equally dispersed among different groups of people. Dahl was clear that power was unequally dispersed, clear that an elite did exist, and that this elite included politicians around the mayor and businesspeople. However, he maintained that these elites were competitive and did not act as a single entity. He also maintained that although an elite governed in the interests of the majority of citizens, that the latter were less powerful did not show there was anything wrong with democracy. Indeed, in a short book After the Revolution? (1970), he poured scorn on those who felt that power could somehow be equally dispersed. Structural Accounts and Theoretical Critiques In the 1970s and 1980s, the power debate moved in two contrary directions. There were those who continued Hunter’s elite and structuralist line, alongside a more Marxist structural-functionalist account— both of which maintained a firm empirical base— and those who moved away from empirical studies to more theoretical critiques that ultimately seem to suggest that power cannot be studied empirically, at least in part because it is an essentially contested concept. The structural accounts begin with Matthew Crenson’s The Unpolitics of Air Pollution (1972), 124 Community Power Debate which demonstrates how structural factors affect the nature of power within communities. Examining two steel towns, he shows how one enacted air pollution ordinances earlier than others did because vested interests had more bargaining power and because the local population also had more invested in the steel companies. Although everyone can see the benefits of clean air, they were less keen on enacting ordinances in one city because of the costs of the ordinances, especially given the propaganda and threats of the steel corporations. In an award-winning book, Regime Politics (1989), Clarence Stone returned to Hunter’s original site of study, Atlanta, to defend the structural account of power—what he termed systemic power—he identified in Hunter’s book. Stone suggested that city government is formed through coalitions that take on governing principles that dominate decision making even when new elites take over. Thus, he argued that even when the African American community managed to wrest control of Atlanta’s governing structure, African American leaders soon took on the interests of the business elite (albeit with a black subsection) in development issues. The underlying idea is that within a democracy, politicians need reelection and they improve their reelection chances by forming a coalition with different groups. They need the support of local business for direct monetary support for their campaigns and to ensure that capitalists do not disinvest in their community. Part of the bargain will involve allowing businesspeople to create new development and ensuring that the local economy runs smoothly. Thus, political elites need to compromise their welfare objectives even if these serve the interests of their core supporters. Hunter also followed up his study of Atlanta with another, in which he reaffirmed his original findings albeit with the addition of a new black elite. The growth-machine model is a neo-Marxist variant of this elite story. Here, the argument is that developers want to maximize the exchange value of the properties they build or improve. Although this might bring some real value to a community, much of this value will be invested or spent in other communities. The local community wants to maximize the use value of its property: the use and exchange value do not always coincide. Hence, although development might be good for a community, the nature of the (local) capitalist state ensures that developers do not work in the best interests of the community. This is called the growth machine because local growth is created for its own sake and not for the benefit of the community. Again, the mechanism underlying the machine is that politicians need to support capital to promote the local economy for their own reelection chances. The second strand of the post-behavioralist examination turned away from empirical community studies. A key book, at least in Europe, was Steven Lukes’s Power: A Radical View, which suggested there were three faces or dimensions of power. These constituted the behaviorialist/decisionist view of Dahl, the nondecisions of Bachrach and Baratz, and a third dimension that recognized the importance of objective interests. One of the issues at the heart of the elite–pluralist divide is whether elites rule in their own interests or in the interests of the community as a whole. Both pluralists and elitists recognize that there are policy elites: the real question is to how far they govern in their own interests and how far they govern in the interests of the community as a whole. To the extent that nondecisions are taken out of the view of the media and the public, one would think that elites are conspiring in their own interests. However, simply because a given development brings great gains to the entrepreneur who risked his money on the venture and the building contractor and businesspeople who worked on it does not show that it was not also in the interests of the local community. Furthermore, we can judge whether elites rule in the interests of the many by how the many respond. In a democracy, if we are not relatively satisfied with decisions made in local government, then we can vote out the politicians and bring in those who suggest alternative courses of action. Thus, although elites might not do exactly what we wish, we may judge that generally they are ruling in the interests of the many. Contrary to this view, however, Lukes argues that both sides ignore the essentially contested view of what constitutes interests in the case. He suggests that people have objective interests of which they themselves might not be aware. Thus, even if we do not overturn our rulers, we cannot be sure they represent our interests because they might fool us about what truly constitutes our real Community Power Debate interests. Taking Crenson’s example of the two steel towns, Lukes suggests that people might think that air pollution ordinances are not a good idea because they will reduce profits for the company and put jobs at risk. However, it would be in their objective interests for health reasons to ensure all towns had similar ordinances so that that competition remained fair and such ordinances would not threaten jobs. He suggests that although we might think that development is in our interests, unaware of our real or objective interests, we can be wrong. Of course, once one has rejected any empirical process by which we judge the importance of issues—such as Dahl’s surfacing of newspaper reports or surveys asking people what is important to them—in judging interests, all we are left with is competing moral views. This lies at the heart of claims that the concepts of interest, and therefore power, are essentially contested. In the second edition of his book, Lukes goes even further and suggests that power is ubiquitous; following Michel Foucault, Lukes depicts the structures and systems of power ensuring a domination that does not allow people to recognize their own interests but ensures we are locked into a system of domination. In a late essay, Lukes quotes dialogue from John Steinbeck’s The Grapes of Wrath where a farmer being driven off his land is persuaded not to shoot the tractor driver who is just doing his job, having lost his own farm too. The farmer realizes that there is no point shooting the guy who gave the tractor driver the orders, nor in shooting the local banker, because he took orders from the east. The conclusion is that perhaps there is no one to shoot. Like Foucault, we might conclude that everyone in the machine of life, those at the top and the bottom, are all dominated by the power system. Such conclusions lead some to suggest that we cannot empirically study power; rather, its study is a normative exercise. In Rational Choice and Political Power, Keith Dowding argues that this view arises from a misunderstanding of the collective action problem. The pluralists are wrong that we can read interests separate from action because the collective action problem shows that people might not act in their own interests, even when they know what those interests are. However, Lukes is wrong in thinking that lack of action shows people do not understand 125 their own interests. Dowding recognizes that there might be objective interests—in the sense that we do not always recognize them—but argues that we can model objective interests by exploring what is good for the health and well-being of people and by examining the ways in which people make poor judgments between their needs and their desires. He argues that we can model situations to make empirical judgments about the relative powers of different agents. He suggests that the best way of measuring power is by examining relative resources and how these can be used in bargaining situations. Dowding argues against the idea of structural or systemic power, suggesting that the term power is best reserved for what agents can do. However, he develops the idea of “systematic luck,” which is very similar to that of Stone’s notion of systemic power. Based on Brian Barry’s notion of luck, which is getting what you want without trying, he suggests that the difference between the power of agents based on what they could achieve given their situation and resources, and how much they get of what they want, is a measure of their luck. If one systematically shares preferences with more powerful actors, then one gets a lot of what one wants without actually being powerful. Thus, the extent to which development takes place despite the wishes of the local community and the extent to which it is actually in the interests of the community is a measure of the luck of the community. The extent to which developers share the interests of politicians given that both want development— the latter for reelection, the former for personal gain—is the systematic luck of the developers. The idea of systematic luck has proved highly controversial: writers such as Lukes and Barry believe it downplays the extent to which capitalists and developers hold sway over communities at local, national, and international levels. Conclusion The community power debate has probably run its course. All sides seem content that they have won a victory and now show little enthusiasm to continue the debate. Key issues such as the nature of interests, how best to measure power (if it can be measured at all), and how far “power” is empirically demonstrable remain contested. Mainstream political science and urban politics tend to avoid 126 Complex Equality (Walzer) direct power study. One reason might be that empirical research now examines models of specific situations and specific coalitions. Although these are studies of power battles, they are not studies of power in the broad sense. The power of an actor, according to most definitions, is what the actor could attain, not what he or she does attain. Mainstream political science and urban studies tend to examine what people have obtained, and so concentrate on the actual narratives or the potential ones. Mainstream power debates, as represented in the newly established Journal of Power, concentrate more on theories of power and much less on direct empirical studies of power. So in that sense, too, the community power debate, which began with specific empirical power studies, has been left behind. Keith Dowding See also Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton; Collective Action Problem; Dahl, Robert A.; Domhoff, G. William; Dowding, Keith; Essentially Contested Concept; Foucault, Michel; Growth Coalitions; Hunter, Floyd; Interests; Lukes, Steven; Mills, C. Wright; Mobilization of Bias; Pluralism; Regime Theory in Urban Politics; Reputational Analysis; Systematic Luck; Systemic Power; Third Face; Three Faces of Power Further Readings Dahl, R. A. (1961). Who governs? Democracy and power in an American city. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Dowding, K. (1991). Rational choice and political power. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar. Hunter, F. (1953). Community power structure: A study of decision makers. New York: Anchor Books. Lukes, S. (2005). Power: A radical view (2nd ed.). Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Stone, C. N. (1989). Regime politics: Governing Atlanta 1946–1988. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. COMPLEX EQUALITY (WALZER) Michael Walzer in his book Spheres of Justice suggests that power and domination can be avoided if a society promotes complex equality. His definition of complex equality states: no social good x should be distributed to men and to women who possess some other good y merely because they possess y and without regard to the meaning of x. Complex equality does not mean that people have the same holdings of any good, so people will not have the same amount of money, status, position, or political power. But their holdings in any one social sphere should not give them advantage regarding their holdings in another social sphere. So, for example, a person holding some political office should not because of that office have greater access to some other social good such as health care. This account of equality in social goods is pluralistic. It has some affinities with Robert A. Dahl’s argument that power is pluralist when it is not concentrated into the hands of a single power elite. Walzer’s account of complex equality is much more radical than is Dahl’s account of pluralism in political power and influence. Underlying the idea of complex equality is that different spheres of life—the market, politics, the arts, and so on—have different social meanings. The just distribution of goods within each sphere will therefore use different principles of distribution. The principles of distribution within one sphere, and the distribution itself, should contaminate neither the principles nor the distribution in another sphere. Walzer’s account, if taken literally, means that people should not gain better health care simply because they have gained better education. Or, that someone should not receive more social status simply because they have more money. It is not clear, however, what this entails for political and economic practice. The unequal holding of monetary resources, for example, is bound to give greater access to many social goods, unless they are not distributed by a market. Greater education is almost bound to lead to greater access to health care because the more educated are better able to articulate their health needs and more confident in their dealings with doctors. It is hard to see how to persuade people not to give more respect to the leading lights of the arts world than to accountants or dentists. A less radical reading would be simply that political power should not lead to greater access to jobs or position. Such a reading is merely saying that politicians and civil servants should not be corrupt. Or that leading capitalists should not Compliance (International) have greater influence over politicians, or over administrative decisions, or have access to other resources provided by the state such as national health care and state education. The less radical reading makes more sense, but is simply part and parcel of constitutional liberalism. Keith Dowding See also Dahl, Robert A.; Justice Further Readings Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defence of pluralism and equality. Oxford, UK: Martin Robertson. COMPLIANCE (INTERNATIONAL) Power is a key concept in international politics, not only in realist thinking. Although power-based theories of international relations stress the relevance of power in explaining war and stability in the international system, institutionalist approaches focus on the exercise of power in both the formation and maintenance of institutions, and through institutions and within and among institutions. Recently, the legalization literature has triggered a debate about the extent to which international institutions mitigate the influence of powerful states. Irrespective of their theoretical approach, most scholars tend to treat power as a property focusing on a particular type of power resource, such as gross domestic product (GDP), demography, or military force. Compliance, defined as rule-consistent behavior, by contrast, lends itself to a more relational concept of power. Following Max Weber, power can be understood as the probability of getting an actor to comply against his or her resistance. Compliance is then a manifestation of power. Conversely, power becomes a major prerequisite to ensure compliance with international institutions. The so-called enforcement school in international compliance research assumes that states violate international norms and rules because they are not willing to bear the costs of compliance. This is particularly the case if international norms 127 and rules are not compatible with national arrangements, as a result of which compliance requires substantial changes at the domestic level. From this rationalist perspective, noncompliance can only be prevented by increasing the costs of noncompliance. Realist approaches point to hegemonic states, which in the absence of an international monopoly of legitimate force are the only actors with sufficient power to effectively sanction noncompliant behavior. Institutionalist approaches, by contrast, emphasize that international institutions can serve as substitutes for the enforcement powers of hegemonic states. Noncompliance or free riding becomes less attractive to states if they are likely to be caught and punished. International institutions can then provide mechanisms for monitoring compliance and for coordinating sanctions against free riders. Several studies have confirmed the importance of enforcement power, both of states and thirdparty authorities, for ensuring compliance with international institutions. At the same time, the original power-based argument of the enforcement school has been differentiated by various strands of the international relations literature. First, liberal theories draw attention to the domestic power of states to legally ratify and enforce international agreements. Domestic veto players can create problems of “involuntary defection” where states are willing to comply but lack the power to overcome domestic resistance against required legal and political changes. For instance, the U.S. president had signed the Kyoto Protocol but could not get the required two-thirds majority in the U.S. Senate to ratify it. Overall, however, compliance studies have found little support for the relevance of institutional veto players in explaining compliance. Second, powerful states do more than enforce compliance; they may also be less sensitive to costs imposed by sanctions and, hence, more resistant to external enforcement pressures. This can be called the power of recalcitrance. The United States is simply more capable of coping with punitive tariffs authorized by the dispute settlement procedure of the World Trade Organization (WTO) than are Kenya and Austria. The same applies to reputational costs caused by a loss of credibility (or social sanctioning). Weak states can hardly afford to exclude powerful states from international agreements, even if the latter have the reputation of being unreliable partners. 128 Compliance (International) Third, principal–agent theory draws attention to the relation between noncompliant states and those actors seeking enforcement. States (principals) delegate monitoring and sanctioning powers to an enforcement authority (agent), which, however, remains dependent on the former because the states can always renounce the power of the enforcement authority. This asymmetrical relation may induce the enforcement authority to act strategically and be reluctant to impose sanctions on powerful states. The latter can use their economic and political power to deter enforcement authorities but also use other states to sanction their noncompliant behavior (power of deterrence). Although the threat of financial penalties by the European Union (EU) brought smaller states, such as Portugal and the Netherlands, into compliance with the EU Stability and Growth Pact, Germany and France successfully prevented the adoption of punitive measures in the council. Fourth, negotiation theories point to a power variant that increases rather than decreases the propensity of powerful states to comply with international norms. Although some have argued that (strong) states are unlikely to enter international agreements that impose high compliance costs, powerful states may be able to shape international institutions according to their preferences. The extent to which a state has managed to impose its preferences during the decision-making process determines the costs of compliance and, thereby, the state’s willingness to comply with the decision (power of assertiveness). Studies on EU policy making confirm that some states are more successful in shaping EU legal acts than others are. However, shaping does not necessarily depend on the economic and political power of a member state. Bureaucratic efficiency and negotiation skills are more important both in the shaping of and passing EU policies. Nor do powerful member states deter the Commission and the European Court of Justice from prosecuting them for violations of EU law. But they are more likely to resist the enforcement pressure of the European Commission (though not the European Court of Justice). Other things being equal, member states such as France, Italy, and Germany, which yield greater (voting) power, violate European law more frequently than do weak member states, such as Denmark, Finland, Sweden, and the Netherlands. Even highly legalized institutions, such as the EU or the WTO, where monitoring and sanctioning powers are delegated to third parties, do not fully mitigate power differences between states. Although power (of recalcitrance) is a key variable in explaining (non-)compliance with international institutions, it is by no means the only one. First, strong states may be able to do what they want. If they choose not to comply, there is little other states and international enforcement authorities can do. However, the management school reminds us that compliance is not necessarily a strategic choice. Even states that choose to comply may be prevented from doing so if the very preconditions that enable states to comply are absent. The literature has identified three sources of involuntary noncompliance: lacking or insufficient state capacities, ambiguous definitions of norms, and inadequate timetables during which compliance has to be achieved. Empirical studies have found the lack of administrative capacity or bureaucratic efficiency as a particular source of noncompliance (see earlier). This may explain why Greece and Portugal are as poor compliers with EU law as France and Italy are. Second, even if we conceive of compliance as a strategic choice, how do we explain that some powerful states are more compliant than others? Germany and the United Kingdom comply much better with EU law than do France and Italy. Likewise, powerful states choose to comply in some cases but defect in others. Other factors than the costs of compliance and the power to avoid them also influence the choice of (powerful) states to comply. Unlike the enforcement and the management schools, constructivist compliance approaches stress that states follow a logic of appropriateness rather than instrumental consequentialism. They are socialized into the norms and rules of international institutions through processes of social learning and persuasion. Consequently, states comply because of a normative belief that a rule or institution ought to be obeyed rather than because it suits their instrumental self-interests. This sense of moral obligation is a function of the legitimacy of the rules themselves or their sources. Legitimacy can be generated in several ways. The rule is embedded in an underlying institution or a legal system, which is generally characterized by a high level of legitimacy (acceptance of the rule-setting institution). Or, a critical number of states are already complying with an international rule. As a result, other states are “pulled” into compliance Computer Algorithms for Power Indices because they want to demonstrate that they conform to the group of states to which they want to belong and whose esteem they care about. Some refer to this form of peer pressure as normative or discursive power. Finally, legitimacy can also result from certain procedures that include those actors in the rule making that are potentially affected and who engage in processes of persuasion and mutual learning (procedural legitimacy). Both procedural legitimacy and peer pressure focus more on compliance with individual rules (exactly those that result from “fair” decision-making processes or those with which other states already comply). The acceptance of the rule-setting institution, in turn, is more country specific because voluntary compliance is generated by diffuse support for and general acceptance of the rule-setting institutions and the constitutive principles of the law making and standing (support for rule of law). Compliance studies on the EU find that member states with a strong rule-of-law legal culture are the best compliers, and the support for the EU appears to be inversely related with compliance—the more antiEU a member state is, the better it complies with EU law, irrespective of its power. To conclude, power is key in explaining international compliance. However, its effect is mitigated by other factors, such as capacity and legitimacy. Empirical studies support explanations based on power, capacity, and legitimacy. Likewise, the EU and many international organizations use a combination of management, enforcement, and legitimacy mechanisms to induce member state compliance. Combining specific power-based explanations with other theoretical approaches might prove more fruitful than pitching the theories against each other. Tanja A. Börzel See also Anarchy in International Relations; Coercion and Power; Hegemony Further Readings Chayes, A., & Chayes, A. H. (1995). The new sovereignty: Compliance with international regulatory agreements. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Franck, T. M. (1990). The power of legitimacy among nations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 129 Hurd, I. (1999). Legitimacy and authority in international politics. International Organization, 53(2), 379–408. Martin, L. L. (1992). Coercive cooperation: Explaining multilateral economic sanctions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Tallberg, J. (2003). European governance and supranational institutions: Making states comply. London: Routledge. COMPUTER ALGORITHMS FOR POWER INDICES The calculation of power indices is a substantial computational task because it requires that each possible voting outcome be examined. For voting bodies with a small number of members, indices can be found with a computer by directly applying the definitions. But when the number of voters is larger, this is not feasible and another algorithm is required. Approximation methods such as Monte Carlo simulation and probabilistic voting assumptions work well and can be very accurate. For voting systems in which the voting weights are integers, the method of generating functions is an almost ideal algorithm that is very fast and completely accurate. To develop these points requires formal mathematical notation. Notation and Definitions A legislature that uses weighted voting and has n members is represented by a set N {1, 2, . . . , n} whose voting weights are w1, w2, . . . , wn . Members vote for or against an action. The combined weight of a subset of members voting “for,” and represented by the subset T (N), is denoted by wðTÞ ¼ S wi. The decision rule is defined in terms i2T of a quota, q, by which T is winning if w(T) q and losing if w(T) q. The weights and the quota are real numbers in general; although in most applications they are integers, this is not essential to the theory, but it is relevant to certain methods of computation, particularly the method of generating functions. Frequently a voting body is represented using the notation {q; w1, w2, . . . , wn}. In this definition, there is a single decision rule and one set of weights. In some applications, it is necessary to generalize this: 130 Computer Algorithms for Power Indices for example, the system of qualified majority voting in the European Union (EU) Council is formally a triple-majority rule in which three conditions must be satisfied in weighted votes, population, and number of member countries. But allowing for multiple majority rules is a minor complication that we can ignore for the present purpose of discussing algorithms. Each member has a power index measuring the relative number of times that member can be the “swing” member. Formally, a swing for member i can be defined as a pair of subsets, (Ti, Ti {i}), where Ti N {i}, such that Ti is losing, but Ti {i} is winning, that is, q wi w(Ti) q. The Penrose–Banzhaf power index for member i, i, is the number of swings, i, expressed as a fraction of the total number of subsets of N, which is equal to 2n–1. It measures the probability of i being the swing voter assuming all swings Ti to be equiprobable. i i 2n–1 (1) The normalized Banzhaf index, i uses the total number of swings for all players as the denominator to measure relative voting power among players, i i i, i i (2) This is a trivial normalization, so it is necessary to consider only the details of computing equation (1). James S. Coleman’s power indices are related to the Penrose–Banzhaf indices and require, in addition, the number of voting outcomes that lead to a positive decision, , that is, the number of subsets S (S N) where w(S) q. This imposes an extra computing requirement but enables us to calculate the three indices: v n 2 Power of the voting body to act: A¼ Power of member i to prevent action: PPAi 5 Power of member i to initiate action: PIAi 5 (3) hi v (4) hi n 2 v (5) Neither (4) nor (5) have meaningful normalized versions because they are both linear transformations of i and therefore normalizing would reduce them both to i. The Shapley–Shubik index (SSI) is the probability that i is the swing member if all orderings of players is equally likely. For a given swing, the number of orderings of the members of the subset Ti and its complement (apart from player i), N Ti {i}, is t!(n t 1)! where t is the number of members of Ti and n is the total number of voters, members of N. The index, i, is this number as a proportion of the number of orderings of all players in N, fi 5 + Ti t!ðn t 1Þ! . n! (6) The Method of Direct Enumeration The simplest algorithm is direct enumeration, that is, computing the indices directly from their definitions. This requires the use of an algorithm to find each subset of members, S N, exactly once. Thus, for each (proper) subset of N, the algorithm finds all swings and updates expressions i, for I 1, 2, . . . , n, and w repeatedly; for the SSI, the algorithm updates (6). Begin by setting i 0, i 0 for all i, and 0. Choose S. For each i 1, 2, . .. , n, the algorithm tests for a swing and updates as follows: If i 2 N S and q wi w(S) q then: Set i i 1. (Alternatively I I 21–n.) Set i i s!(n s 1)!/n! (for the SSI). If w(S) q then set 1. Then move to the next subset S and repeat. When all subsets have been searched, the indices (1) to (6) are found. The number of subsets of N that have to be searched is 2n. Therefore, computation time doubles each time n increases by one member and the algorithm becomes infeasible for large voting bodies. Despite this severe limitation, it is a practical method to analyze qualified majority voting in the European Council with about 27 members, though it is too slow for legislatures much larger than that. This method is not at all feasible, for example, for a voting body as big as the States game in the U.S. presidential Electoral College with 51 members, let Computer Algorithms for Power Indices alone the International Monetary Fund (IMF) or World Bank with 184 members. The advantages of direct enumeration are its simplicity, its generality in that it can be used for any problem, that its results are exact, and that it does not require excessive storage of data in the computer’s memory. The disadvantage is its exponential time complexity that severely limits its application to voting bodies with small numbers of voters. These problems have been overcome in various ways. One of the earliest alternatives to be proposed was Monte Carlo simulation, which does not search all subsets of voters but instead selects a large random sample of them. With modern computing power, this method is capable of giving results that are very accurate, although they are still approximations. The Method of Multilinear Extensions A second approximation is based on the method of multilinear extensions proposed by Guillermo Owen. Although this approach involves formally modeling the voting body as a cooperative game, the essential idea behind the approximation reduces to probabilistic voting and treating the power indices as probabilities. For the Penrose–Banzhaf index, each member is assumed to vote for or against with equal probability. Hence, the mean and variance of the total number of votes “for” an action are known for any subset S. It is then a simple matter to approximate the swing probabilities using the normal distribution. This method does not involve the calculation of the i s or directly. The generalization required to get the SSI is that the voting probabilities are different, say the probability that member i votes “for” is equal to t and the probability that i votes “against” is (1 t). The means and variances of the total number of votes “for” (hence, the swing probabilities) now depend on t. The SSIs are obtained by integrating out t from the swing probabilities, using numerical quadrature. The accuracy of Owen’s method depends on how good an approximation the normal distribution is. In some cases, this is a problem—for example, where there is a voter (or voters) with a very large weight relative to the others, so that the distribution of the total vote “for” is quite “lumpy.” A modification to deal with this problem has been suggested by 131 Dennis Leech in the form of an algorithm that achieves greater accuracy by combining direct enumeration with probabilistic voting: the normal approximation is taken to apply only to the (large number of) voters with relatively small weight, and direct enumeration is used for the (manageably small number of) voters with large weights. These methods are feasible for computing resources and can be applied to any voting body. The Method of Generating Functions In the event that the weights are integers, the method of generating functions provides algorithms for computing power indices exactly. It is extremely efficient in computing time and capable of giving results almost instantaneously for voting bodies with any number of members, although it can be demanding of storage capacity if w(N) is large. This is therefore an almost ideal algorithm. It is also one of the oldest approaches, having been first used for the SSI for the States game (with n 51) in a 1962 Rand Corporation working paper by Irving Mann and Lloyd Shapley after a suggestion by David G. Cantor, although it was little used until recently. Consider first how the approach can be used for the Banzhaf and Coleman indices. We need the number of swings for each member, i, and the total number of winning votes, . This requires first finding the number of subsets, S, for each possible size, w(S) 0, 1, 2, . . . , w(N). These numbers can be found using the generating function: n Y wj f ðxÞ5 11x (7) j51 where x is a dummy variable that has no significance of its own in the sense of measuring something, but whose role is to define the coefficients, which have an important meaning. Expanding the product in equation (7) gives a polynomial of degree w(N), in which the powers are the weights of possible subsets. The function ƒ(x) may be written in general as, wðNÞ j f ðxÞ5Sj50 aj x : (8) Comparing (8) with (7), it is easily seen that each of the coefficients aj gives us the number of 132 Computer Algorithms for Power Indices subsets with a given weight. That is, aj is equal to the number of subsets, S, such that wðSÞ5j , for j 0, 1, 2, . . . , w(N). Because only the empty set has zero weight, a0 1. Now the question arises of how to evaluate the coefficients in (8) from (7). Henceforth, we will use the notation w to represent w(N) for brevity. A simple rule can be found for numerically finding the coefficients aj by building up the generating function (7) by successive multiplications. n Y Thus, (7), f ðxÞ5 1 1 xwj j51 n Y w wj 5 ½11x 1 11x , j52 i h w1 w w 1w 5 11x 1x 2 1x 1 2 n Y w 11x j ; etc: j53 Let the successive polynomials inside the square brackets be denoted, in general, ðrÞ ðrÞ 2 at the rth stage, where r 1, 2, . . . , n. The final stage of this process gives the required coefficients: ðnÞ aj 5aj for all j. Analogously, f(x) can be built up recursively as follows: h i ð1Þ ð1Þ w ð1Þ f ðxÞ5 11 a1 x1 a2 1 . . . 1aw x n Y w 11x j j52 n h i Y ð2Þ ð2Þ w ð2Þ 11xwj 5 11a1 x1a2 . . . 1aw x j53 ð0Þ ð Þ It can be seen that, letting a00 51 and aj 50 for all j 0 , and applying the rule: ðr21Þ ðr21Þ 1aj2wr The coefficients aj can then be used to find the number of swings for each member, i, which depends also on the member’s weight, wi. This can be obtained by finding, for each j, such that q – wi j q, the number, cj, of subsets not containing i, then summing over j. Coefficients cj can be obtained by dividing the w generating function (8) by the factor ð11x i Þ. Thus, writing v wi f ðxÞ 5 11c1 x1c2 x1 . . . 1cv x Þ 11x 511a1 x1 . . . aw xw , where v5w2wi , gives the rule: (10) where a coefficient with a negative subscript is zero. Then the number of swings for member i, i, is q21 hi 5Sj5q2wi cj . This process is then repeated for each member I, and the indices are calculated in the usual way. For the Shapley–Shubik index, we use the generating function, n Y wj (11) f ðxÞ5 11x y with two dummy arguments, x and y, which can be written in general as, ðnÞ w 511a1 x1 . . . 1aw x . ðrÞ j$q j51 ... aj 5aj w v5 S aj : cj 5 aj 2 cj2wi for j 1, 2, . . . , v, ðrÞ w 11a1 x1a2 x 1 . . . 1aw x ðnÞ gives the required coefficients, aj, equal to the number of subsets with voting weight j. The total number of winning votes, , is the number of subsets of members with combined weight equal to or greater than the quota. Thus, (9) for j wr, . . . , Sr, and aðj rÞ 5aðj r21Þ otherwise, where sr 5wðf1; 2; 3; . . . ; rgÞ , after n iterations, this w n j k f ðx; yÞ5 S S djk x y , j50 k50 where djk is the number of k-member subsets with combined voting weight j. The (w 1)(n 1) matrix D is computed iteratively, as before, by the rule, ðrÞ ðr1Þ djk 5djk ðr1Þ 1djwr ;k21 : Consensual Power, Theories of The required matrix is D D(n). The index for member i is found by calculating the number of swings with k members with votes equal to j, cjk, using the rule, derived in the same way as before, cjk 5djk 2cjwi ;k1. (12) Then the index (1) is obtained from the expression, k!ðn212kÞ! q21 + cjk : n! j5q2wi k50 n21 fi 5 + (13) Then (12) and (13) are repeated for each member. Dennis Leech See also Power Indices Further Readings Leech, D. (n.d.) Computer algorithms for voting power analysis. Retrieved from http://www.warwick.ac.uk/~ecaae Owen, G. (1995). Game theory. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. CONSENSUAL POWER, THEORIES OF Contrary to the commonsense everyday view of power, in which power is thought of in terms of coercion or the threat of violence, most routine political and social power is based on some level of consent. To make sense of this consensual base, it is necessary to analyze power both from a sociological empirical stance and a normative philosophical one. The Concept The literature on power is essentially scalar regarding consensus and conflict. At one end of the scale, theorists such as Max Weber, Michael Mann, Robert Dahl, and Steven Lukes view power purely in terms of conflict. At the other end, Hannah Arendt, Talcott Parsons, and Barry Barnes represent the consensual end of the spectrum. Theorists such as Anthony Giddens, Stewart Clegg, Keith Dowding, Mark Haugaard, Peter Morriss, and 133 Michel Foucault encompass both consensual and conflictual aspects of power. In thinking about consensual power, two aspects have to be clearly distinguished. First, consensus can be defined in terms of outcomes or goals pursued, which gives a fairly narrow conceptualization of consensual power. In this case, any exercise of consensual power is directed toward an objective that is shared by all involved. Thus conceived, consensual power is a form of empowerment that entails only power to. The typical manifestation of this would be a group of like-minded people coming together to create an organization for a common purpose. Second, consensual power can be seen in terms of power over. Many exercises of power over others and acts of domination rest on some deep form of consensus. This can take two forms: on the one hand, conflict can be structured within a shared framework of consensus, in which case, consensus with regard to the rules of the game are a form of constraint whereby power over is managed. In this case, the consensus is not in itself part of a system of relations of domination. On the other hand, the other form of consensual power is where the consent is intrinsic to domination and thus considered somehow normatively problematic. In the Marxist tradition, hegemony, and in Foucault’s work, epistemes or discourse, are considered forms of domination that are built on the consent by less powerful or subaltern actors. To make sense of these more complex, compound forms of power, where a consensus and conflict are combined, we should distinguish between empirical sociological observations and normative claims appropriate to political theory. When there is de facto consent; in the Marxist, Foucauldian, and feminist positions, it is thought that there is potential, but as yet unmanifested, conflict. However, this hypothesis can only be justified based on a normative evaluation to the effect that weaker consenting social actors should not consent. When we assert that a given class suffers from “false consciousness” (three-dimensional power) or is subservient to a “hegemonic” discourse, the less powerful actor B consents to the power relations in question and the observing social scientist or theorists thinks (possibly for good reasons) that the actor should not be consenting, thus designating the situation as one of conflict, 134 Consensual Power, Theories of despite the empirical fact of consent. Here we have sociological consent, which is labeled conflictual for normative reasons. To justify such an evaluation, the observer/theorist must develop clear normative criteria for making such a judgment call. Perspectives on Consensual Power From a sociological perspective, the first serious attempt to theorize the consensual base of power was made by Parsons. Using a structural-functionalist paradigm, he proposed that power is a capacity for action, which is derived from consensus with regard to system goals. Aside from the fact that structural-functionalism is out of favor in sociology, the problem with this theorization was that the scope of power was unduly narrow, excluding most forms of power over, thus avoiding the interesting phenomenon of conflictual power with a consensual base. In The Nature of Power, Barry Barnes suggests a more plausible basis than system goals as a consensual base for power. He proposes that power relations are based on shared cognitions. Derived from Thomas Kuhn’s concept of paradigms, Barnes suggests that common interpretative frameworks give actors a shared base for collective behavior. Knowledge of the regularities of nature gives humans natural power; similarly, knowledge of the predictabilities of other actors facilitates shared social projects, thus social power. Imagine a “target” as a social object: what makes a target a target is not inherent in its shape (there are many circles that are not targets) but that people throw darts at it. All social objects are like targets in that what makes them what they are is purely a reflection of a shared socially constructed interpretative horizon or culture—for instance, what makes a cup a cup? The same applies to actors in authority, what makes the “leader” of a group, the leader is that others perceive the person to be a leader. Thus, what distinguishes the actual Napoleon from the “napoleons” in psychiatric institutions is how others perceive them as meaning-given entities. Although Barnes’s perspective is a substantial improvement over Parsons’, in that it provides a more plausible account of the consensual basis for empowerment, power over is theorized within a separate rational choice argument, which sidesteps the phenomenon of power conflict based on consent. The idea of cognitive consensus as the basis of social order is also found in sociological theory that is influenced by the phenomenological tradition. In The Constitution of Society, Giddens argues that our knowledge of social structures is based on “practical consciousness” knowledge, which is tacit knowledge. We also have “discursive consciousness” knowledge, which is knowledge that we readily know how to put into words. For Giddens, practical consciousness knowledge is the key to an actor’s ability to reproduce social structure, which he views as the basic ordering mechanism of social life, including the microroutines of everyday interaction. So, for instance, in an interaction between two socially competent actors from the same culture, they know how far apart to stand, when to interject, and to take turns in a conversation, and in speaking the same language, they share a structured system of sounds. This knowledge is largely tacit knowledge, which they do not reflect on discursively, although they do have the capacity to do so. The use of practical consciousness knowledge for structural reproduction enables them to use their discursive knowledge to focus on the desired outcome of their interaction, which can either be a practical goal or some kind of politeness aimed at mutual recognition of the other as a social agent. Thus, practical consciousness knowledge is inherently empowering. Every interaction that exhibits structured form (which all social action does) gains its structuredness because both actors follow the norms of structuration. If, in everyday interaction, one of the actors decides to disregard the norms of appropriate space (e.g., a relative stranger decides to hug the other), turn taking (continual interruption), and all grammatical norms (gibberish), no joint goals could be realized. Thus, following the norms of structuration enables these actors to do things that they could not otherwise accomplish, and in that sense, structural constraint is empowering. Giddens argues that the basis of structuration is a set of norms and rules that constrain social actors. However, I would argue this is not entirely correct. Although norms and rules are the only means available to actors to discursively express their disapproval of others who violate “normal” structuration practice, these structures exist more like cognitive categories that actors use to order the world. These categories are not universal but are particular to specific cultures that vary across time Consensual Power, Theories of and space. Following Foucault in The Order of Things, they are the tacit interpretative horizon that constitutes the particularities of a specific culture as an interpretative framework that is used to make sense of the world. Foucault used the terms episteme or discursive formation for this practical consciousness knowledge and argued that they are a kind of historical a priori. It is “a priori” in the sense that it constitutes a prerequisite for interpretation, and it is “historical” in that it is particular to a specific society in historical time. Space should be added to this to the extent to which cultures differ geographically, which is the basis of anthropology. This shared practical consciousness knowledge exists as a deep consensus on which social order is built. The shared internalization of this knowledge is what makes collective endeavor possible as a form of empowerment and constitutes the basis of our ability to act “in concert.” Because this ability is based on tacit knowledge, and it is central to the social construction of who we are, it is so taken for granted that theorists (including Foucault) usually do not reflect on this relative miracle of mutual empowerment. Because this knowledge is inextricably bound up with our ontology, or being-in-theworld, it is actually relatively stable, which is why it is not usually experienced as constraint or as norms and rules. This massive consent is the basis of power to and is the most effective basis (more effective than the threat of violence) of managing power conflict, or power over. This process can be paradigmatically seen in the democratic process. When parties contest an election, they engage in conflict with regard to outcomes or goals—both parties wish to win. Yet, this contest is premised on a massively complex epistemic system, with attendant norms that can be mobilized in the instance of their breach. “Standing” for election as a “candidate” and “voting,” are acts of structuration that are given meaning. Part of the meaning is a prior acceptance that whichever party, or coalition of parties, obtains the largest number of those socially constructed entities that we call votes (which are merely bits of paper with an “x” on them or an electric pulse generated by pressing a button, in the case of electronic voting) “wins” the election. In other words, engaging in “voting” entails a prior commitment to accepting defeat based on shared interpretation of a “vote.” Of course, there are instances when this consent 135 does not come automatically, if at all, as for instance in the U.S. presidential election of 2000, which is an exception that proves the rule. Similarly, in some instances, where democracy is unstable, coercion may be required as a substitute. The point remains, however, that the routine functioning of power conflict within modern democracies is based on a shared consent to structural reproduction, which is an extraordinary fact that is so taken for granted (or so part of our practical consciousness) that most social scientists who write about power ignore this phenomenon entirely. In Foucault’s work, we find a distinction between “deep conflict” and “shallow conflict.” A shallow conflict presupposes the “rules of the game,” whereas a deep conflict entails their contestation. In his genealogies of knowledge, Foucault describes how conflicts within systems of thought act as a shared basis of consent, and how social actors resist this taken-for-granted interpretative framework in deeper conflicts. Within this, what may appear like a substantive conflict is really based on consensus, and thus constitutes a shallow conflict. For instance, the conflict between Karl Marx and many of the bourgeois economists was a shallow conflict because the parties involved shared common perceptual categories, including the labor theory of value. Shallow conflict is a way of taming conflict. In several of his writings, Foucault refers to power as war by other means or as re-inscription of the rules of war through politics— which, within the present framework, means the use of social structure to facilitate an ordered exercise of power over. In this imagery, war is like a Hobbesian state of nature in which there are no rules to constrain conflict, whereas politics constitutes a shared interpretative horizon that tames conflict by making it predictable. This use of Foucault subverts Foucault’s intent in the sense that Foucault took for granted that this continuation of war through power was normatively reprehensible. However, in the instance in the democratic process or reasoned debate, these constraints are actually desirable, thus normatively unproblematic. Normative Implication In his critique, Foucault shares with Antonio Gramsci and Lukes the implicit judgment that 136 Consensual Power, Theories of certain social actors should not consent to the structures that routinely constrain conflict, thus creating power. In the case of Gramsci on hegemony, the proletariat has internalized a bourgeois worldview that makes members of the proletariat consent to capitalism in their routine social practices. In three-dimensional power, the actors consent because they do not know what their real interests are and, in the case of Foucault, because they mistakenly believe that their interpretative horizon represents the “truth” and the “natural order of things.” To be defensible, however, this critique of consent requires a robust normative theory to justify it. Otherwise, such a position is inherently condescending toward the social subjects because it entails an implicit assertion to the effect that they do not know what their real interests are or that they suffer from some kind of cognitive deficiency. However, most social theorists do not confront this need for normative justification. Rather, they give descriptive accounts of the creation of consent and use the reader to supply the normative content. For instance, the critical edge of Foucault’s analysis hinges on a two-stage move in which he begins by demonstrating, through a historical account of the differences between epistemes, that our interpretative horizons are essentially arbitrary social constructs particular to specific historical periods. This is followed by an account of how, in the modern period, this arbitrariness is disguised by a strategic use of truth to reify our taken-for-granted episteme. Such a strategic use of truth violates the reader’s taken-forgranted norms concerning the use of truth in social interaction. Thus, the normative base for Foucault’s critique is supplied, externally, by the reader. Once we recognize that the consensual basis of power conflict is not always normatively wrong or unjust, we are confronted with a problematic that neither Foucault nor those following Gramsci were. The problem of power becomes how to distinguish consent to power that is just and fair from consent that we disapprove of? This is particularly thorny if we take the view that actors who are empirically observed to give their consent to power may be mistaken in doing so. To give a comprehensive answer to this question is outside the scope of this entry. However, in broad outline, the answer entails two elements: it includes a sociological account of the process whereby consent is created and a normative theory that demonstrates why the empirical process of consent creation violates the norms of justice. Two instances illustrate the point: three-dimensional power and epistemes. In three-dimensional power, as theorized by Lukes, the actors suffer from “false consciousness,” which is theoretically unsatisfactory because it presupposes that Lukes has “true consciousness.” However, let us redescribe this phenomenon using some of the sociological vocabulary already outlined. We have already observed that the consent involved in most power conflict is part of practical consciousness knowledge. Practical consciousness knowledge and discursive consciousness knowledge are not entirely separate entities. It is possible to convert practical consciousness into discursive consciousness and vice versa. When we learn a language as a second language, we are moving discursive consciousness into practical consciousness knowledge. To reverse this, when, for instance we read Foucault’s description of Jeremy Bentham’s Panopticon, in Discipline and Punish, we recognize our old school or current place of employment and, in so doing, convert practical consciousness knowledge into discursive consciousness. If we look at the normative tradition of social contract, it can be argued that a “tacit” contract is not the same as a discursive contract. So, if instead of thinking in terms of true and false consciousness, we think in terms of a process of consciousness raising whereby the social critic (whether Marxist, feminist, or Foucauldian) is making practical consciousness into discursive knowledge, one could argue that three-dimensional power is a case in which actors give tacit consent to social contract, which is not a valid normative consent unless it also holds when it is made discursive. With regard to epistemes, Foucault in essence argues that epistemes are arbitrary ways of ordering the world that are made to appear other than arbitrary through the use of truth to reify the world. Truth is effective in this task because it is considered to be beyond convention. If something is “true,” then it is no longer considered a reflection of convention. So truth is used to make something appear other than it is (reification), which implies some level of deceit. Using a normative theory (e.g., Jürgen Habermas’s theory of “communicative Consent action”), one can show that when such a strategic use of truth takes place the consent that results is not a sound basis for justice. Contra Foucault, not all taming of war, and its institutionalization in a regime of politics, is inherently wrong. In this case, the use of truth is only reprehensible if it can be demonstrated that it is strategic and obscuring a deeper truth, which is that our interpretative horizons are social constructs. Indeed, this recognition is necessary to protect Foucauldian analysis from the accusation that it is inherently self-refuting—if all truth is domination, then Foucault’s critique is just another mode of domination. In conclusion, consent is central to power relations. At one end of the spectrum, we have pure consent where the structures and outcomes are agreed. Then we have conflict, which is managed through consent. This is central to ordered politics and is not inherently normatively reprehensible— routine democratic politics works this way. At the more conflictual level, there is also empirical sociological consent, which, as social critics, we consider morally reprehensible. To justify such a claim, however, the theorist in question must have both a clear sociological account of consent creation and a normative theory for critiquing this process. Mark Haugaard See also Arendt, Hannah; Clegg, Stewart; Dahl, Robert A.; Discourse; Dowding, Keith; Foucault, Michel; Giddens, Anthony; Haugaard, Mark; Hegemony; Legitimation; Lukes, Steven; Mann, Michael; Morriss, Peter; Power To and Power Over; Structuration; Weber, Max Further Readings Barnes, B. (1988). The nature of power. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings 1972–1977 (C. Gordon, Ed.). Brighton, UK: Harvester Press. Foucault, M. (2003). Society must be defended. London: Penguin. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Haugaard, M. (2003). Reflections on seven ways of creating power. European Journal of Social Theory, 6, 78–114. 137 CONSENT When one is affected by the actions of others that one might either approve or disapprove of, what is sometimes more important is whether one has agreed to be subject to the actions of others. If one has so agreed, then one has consented. Consent is important in a society because often events occur that disadvantage us. Whether we are entitled to compensation depends on the degree of consent. One might agree to medical procedures that are designed to make life easier but pose risks of a poorer quality of life, or even death. However, in agreeing to those procedures, one is consenting to the risk of those actions. Consent need not be explicitly expressed but can be implied. Many sports activities carry risks of injury as do fairgrounds, children’s playgrounds, and so on. As long as the authorities running these activities are judged to have taken reasonable care and have not broken explicit health and safety regulations, then using facilities or taking part in activities is considered consent. At times, people who are considered not competent to understand the implications of their actions are considered not to be able to give informed consent—that is, they are not capable of consenting to the activity because they are not capable of understanding the risks. In different legal systems, understandings of informed consent vary. In the United Kingdom, for example, as long as a medical practitioner can demonstrate a recognized standard of care, then it is understood that the patient has had sufficient or informed consent to the procedure. In the United States or Australia, for example, the medical practitioner has to demonstrate that he or she has specified the risks involved to the patient so that the law can judge whether the patient has given informed consent. The two different interpretations underlie different views of informed consent. One is more paternalistic and suggests that although due care has been taken according to professionally agreed practices, the subjects can be considered to have given consent because when they go to a doctor what they desire is the best treatment as suggested by that authority. The second view is more libertarian and suggests that people need to be given sufficient information so they can make their own judgments rather than leave this up to their agents. 138 Constructivist View of Power in International Relations Contractual theories of the state assume that citizens have given implicit consent to the law and governing authorities because they have not explicitly dissented through revolt or, in democracies, through the democratic process. Contract theories of the state are subject to the same interpretations as is informed consent in the medical case. More paternalistic analysts are content to accept that people can be considered to have consented to the authority of the state as long as it behaves reasonably. Libertarians give less authority to the state and demand that state actions have actual and not just tacit content. In that sense, the two sides are more or less demanding the discretion that should be allowed to the state in making laws without explicitly inquiring of the people. James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock’s The Calculus of Consent specifies this libertarian doctrine by requiring the contract to aspire to universal consent that can only be assumed when a state of affairs is Paretopreferred to all others—that is, when there is no state of affairs that would be chosen by one person to the actual one. Keith Dowding See also Authority; Hobbes, Thomas; Legitimation; Paternalism Further Readings Buchanan, J. R., & Tullock, G. (1982). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. CONSTRUCTIVIST VIEW OF POWER IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS In the 1980s, constructivism appeared as a new turn in the theorizing of international relations (IR). Its success was helped by the unexpected end of the cold war. Although the Soviet Union was militarily not less powerful than before—including even the early post-1945 period until the 1960s— it decided to peacefully retrench from its positions in Eastern Europe. If the balance of power was to be the main theory of IR, it met an anomaly here, not because IR theories did not predict the event, but because, according to their tenets, such an event was not going to happen in the first place. For constructivists, the end of the cold war shows that a materialist understanding of power, and balance of power theories that are part of it, are woefully insufficient, because outcomes in international politics could not be explained by shifting balances of capabilities. By criticizing the explanatory role of power, constructivism aimed at the core of established IR theories To more precisely establish the constructivist view of power, it is necessary first to introduce constructivism and develop its implications for understanding and conceptualizing power. Constructivism Constructivism can be understood as a meta-theoretical commitment that is based on three characteristics. First, it makes the epistemological claim that meaning, and hence knowledge, is socially constructed. It is constructed because concepts are the condition for the possibility of knowledge. Our senses are not passive receptors of “given” facts. The very identification of facts out of the ongoing noise depends on preexisting notions that guide our view of the world. This knowledge is moreover socially or intersubjectively constructed. Concepts are part of language. Language is not reducible to something entirely subjective or objective. Language is not subjective because it exists independently of us to the extent that language is always more than its individual usages and before them. Language is not objective because it does not exist independently of our minds and our usage (language exists and changes through our use). Language is intersubjective. Second, constructivism makes the ontological claim that the social world is constructed. As in John Searle’s famous example about a money bill, this piece of paper is “money” only because of our shared beliefs. As all people who have had to go through periods of hyperinflation recognize, the moment that this shared belief ceases to exist, the bill is literally no more than a piece of paper. This assumption does not entail that everything is constructed, but it covers that part of reality in which the social sciences are usually interested. Hence, the physical type of support for money (paper, plastic, etc.) is usually not the most relevant for Constructivist View of Power in International Relations social analysis. What is most relevant is the social or institutional fact—the ontological result of “our making.” Third, since constructivism clearly distinguishes and problematizes the relationship between the levels of observation and action, it is finally defined by stressing the reflexive relationship between the social construction of knowledge and the construction of social reality. In other words, it focuses on reflexivity. On the microlevel, reflexivity has to do with what Ian Hacking calls the looping effect. Categories we use for classifying/naming people interact with the self-conception of those people. Whereas it makes no difference to stones how we classify them, it can make a difference to people and affect their self-understanding and behavior: identity thus becomes a crucial term for constructivism. On the macrolevel, reflexivity refers to self-fulfilling prophecies. The concern in the response to Samuel Huntington’s clash of civilization thesis had much to do with this reflexive relationship between knowledge and the social world. Whether the main fault lines of conflict really have to be thought in this way, if all people assume they do, and act accordingly, the world would indeed become one of inevitable clashes of civilizations. Assuming the claim to be true, our actions would tend to produce the very reality the claim was only supposed to describe. But the relationship between social reality and the social construction of knowledge also works from social facts to knowledge, a component perhaps less touched on in constructivist writings. Constructivist Conceptualizations of Power This metatheoretical commitment has implications for the type of social theories that would be compatible with constructivism. And those theories, in turn, have implications for the types of power that can be conceived therein. Constructivism is part of the interpretivist family of social theories. As such, it cannot conceive of power in terms of resources alone. People act toward objects based on the meaning people give these objects: objects themselves do not determine their meaning. Nuclear missiles might be mighty weapons; small Luxemburg does not fear its huge French neighbor because of them. Thus, constructivism is not prone to repeat what Robert Dahl 139 once called the lump fallacy of power, where all possible power resources would be mixed and added. Such an aggregate power (resource) assessment, independent of the actor’s understandings and the contingent situational setting, would be wrong, and conceptually impossible. This makes constructivism more receptive to a relational understanding of power. Often confused with a relative understanding of power—one’s power resources are always to be seen in relation to the other’s power resources—such an understanding sees power defined by the specific relation between actors. Here, power lies not with given (re)sources, but can be established only once we know the precise scope and domain of the relation— that is, one must state who is being influenced and in what way. Hence, it includes an interaction and person-specific component. If, for instance, power is defined as the capacity to get B to do something he or she had not planned to do, then this implies knowing the specific plans of B before being able to assess whether A’s action had any effect. Yet, constructivist theorizing would give a communicative twist to this, insisting on the role of open or tacit recognition, which, in turn, relies on a wider social or cultural context. Such recognition is typically based on conventions because, as mentioned earlier, resources are given weight not by themselves, but by shared understandings in social relations and because the recognition of a general power status is social. Just as individual communications are part of and make sense within the context of a language at large, the relational aspect of power is conceived in this wider manner to allow social norms to become visible in their role for the assessment of power as authority. As a corollary of the interpretivist and communicative setting, constructivists will not use power as an efficient cause. Power is part of constitutive relations and effects (see also later): a master does not “cause” a slave, but both, and their respective powers, are constituted through master–slave relations. For the same reason, constructivism will view power in an often impersonal and, hence, not necessarily intentional way. Invoking certain metaphors or historical analogies can be very influential, whether intended or not, because they mobilize a pre-given understanding. The particular way issues are framed empowers certain arguments 140 Constructivist View of Power in International Relations and actors at the expense of others. If a situation is understood in terms of the lessons of Munich, pleading for negotiations becomes an indefensible act of appeasement; an understanding in terms of the lessons of World War I would make negotiations an act of prudence to preempt a further escalation nobody wanted. This power of existing biases is impersonal to the extent that it is done through a set of common understandings or discourses, rather than reducible to the interpretation of one person; it is intersubjective rather than subjective. But, just as with language, power requires persons mobilizing it to be effective. Finally, constructivism is interested in the power aspects of performativity, where constructivism relies mainly on speech act theories and Foucauldian approaches. If the categories with which we order the world are themselves part of, and can significantly affect, the order in the (social!) world, then they are a crucial element for understanding power in any society. So does, for instance, the category failed states interact with some states in their self-understanding and subjectivity and therefore describes the social world and changes it? Our categories and ways of understanding the world also prompt and legitimate certain actions, which would not have been legitimated by other categorizations, such as international interventions that overrule the otherwise fundamental norm of sovereignty. Applied to the concept of power itself, such a performative analysis can also look at the way the analysis of power affects power: the “power politics of power analysis.” Constructivism-Inspired Analyses of Power in IR Constructivism redefines power at the systemic and at the agent level in IR. Constructivists’ systemic analysis of power often looks at the origins of consent in terms of power relations—that is, at issues of tacit legitimacy. It is therefore close to power concepts of the family of authority. But rather than looking at formal or institutional authority, constructivism is interested in the intersubjective practices of power—not in the position of authority, but rather in what “authorizes,” “legitimates,” or “empowers.” Moreover, constructivists do not necessarily look at intentional or agent power, but rather at the impersonal effects of discourses or habits for the production and reproduction of order—particularly where they seem natural or go without notice. These discourses perhaps constitute the most effective power relations. At the actor level, such a view implies an emphasis on the process of interest formation as a primary locus for power relations. Constructivism insists in making this interest formation part of the analysis—and not just simply assumed—something that cannot be derived outside of the specific interaction and the wider culture or shared understandings within which it takes place (from relational to communicative, see earlier). And for constructivists, interests cannot be understood outside of such cultures in terms of shared constitutive norms, of shared knowledge and understandings, and through the effects practices have on self-understandings or identity. For constructivists, what we want follows from who we are. Such a view informs constructivists’ views of power, although they may not always be openly framed as power analyses. One larger research agenda is about the background knowledge or constitutive rules of the game that define the competent player and the effective moves. This has been applied both to the world of diplomats and to the world of experts. Richard Ashley in particular has analyzed how the “authorized” expertise most often defined through tenets of the realist school in IR systematically enacts conceptual blackmails and biases that marginalize other practices. Anna Leander has analyzed the “epistemic power” of private military companies when they shape the understanding of security and the self-understanding of their actors, as well as their structural power in reproducing a field of security characterized by experts that authorize an increasingly technical and military understanding of the field—just when the security sector had started to be demilitarized—and are, in turn, authorized through it. With regard to their focus on identity, constructivist scholars have looked at the impersonal effect of discourses or practices on self-understandings and on the power politics of identity. If identity is crucial for interest formation, then it is only a small step to analyze how diplomatic practices, sometimes intended, can try to blackmail actors by taking profit from contradictions in another actor’s self-understandings or between its action and self-representation. Janice Bially Mattern calls Control this process one of representational force. As her study on U.S.–U.K. relations during the Suez crisis in 1956 shows, the United States could exploit such tensions to make the British government change its behavior to conform to a certain selfunderstanding of what it stood for. Finally, performative or reflexive analyses of power study the conventions of power definitions, the definitional struggles, and their effects on the social world. As mentioned earlier, constructivists would reject any power index based on some resource aggregate as basically meaningless. Because different types of power resources are not commensurable and depend for their actual value on the meanings attached to them, their ranking and measure is but the effect of a shared convention that establishes their efficacy, their status, and the status of actors. This convention informs the type of interests and, hence, most rational policies. Before diplomats can start counting, they must first agree on what counts. If all diplomatic actors agree that the authority given by cultural attraction, but not by military resources, weighs much in our times of globalization, this shared idea will strongly influence the status and privileges of particular actors in world affairs. Less ambitiously and applied to one country only: if a certain understanding of power becomes predominant in one country, it redirects the foreign policy of that country, as can be seen in definitions that stress “soft power” (thus demilitarizing foreign policy) and other attempts to resist it. Given their conventional status, there is a power politics of power analysis. As a result, some of the constructivist research agendas converge with Foucauldian approaches in their understanding of order as diffused practices of rule, rather than as clear or formal hierarchies. Such convergence can be seen, for instance, in the analysis of how international standards, invented often by private actors, are practices of rule once they become accepted convention and interact with the actors and issues they were supposedly only neutrally measuring (e.g., credit rating). Similarly, to give a last example, Ole Jakob Sending and Iver Neumann analyze the role of nonstate actors not that much in opposition to the political power of states, but as part of a decentralized and self-disciplining logic of global order. Stefano Guzzini 141 See also Balance of Power; Bourdieu, Pierre; Consensual Power, Theories of; Diplomacy; Foucault, Michel; Fungibility of Power Resources; Governmentality; Knowledge and Power; Language and Power; Legitimation Further Readings Barnett, M., & Duvall, R. (Eds.). (2005). Power in global governance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Bially Mattern, J. (2005). Ordering international politics: Identity, crisis, and representational force. New York: Routledge. Guzzini, S. (2000). A reconstruction of constructivism in international relations. European Journal of International Relations, 6(2), 147–182. Guzzini, S. (2005). The concept of power: A constructivist analysis. Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 33(3), 495–522. Leander, A. (2005). The power to construct international security: On the significance of private military companies. Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 33(3), 803–826. Onuf, N. G. (1989). World of our making: Rules and rule in social theory and international relations. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. CONTROL If one is in complete control of some object or state of being, then one can be said to have complete power over that object or state of being. In some sense, therefore, control and power could be thought to be synonyms. However, often when we think of ourselves as in control of something, we do not have complete power with regard to that thing. Thus, although I can be legally considered to be in complete control of my car when driving down the road, I am not completely powerful with regard to the car. For example, I must rely on the car engine working properly for it to continue under my control. Being in control is also closely associated with freedom. One might be considered to be free to the extent that one is in control of one’s actions. Freedom as control can be reduced either internally, a loss of autonomy leading to a loss of control, or 142 Conventional Deterrence externally through outside constraints. Thus, if one loses control of bodily limbs through injury then one has lost some freedom of movement. If psychological problems lead one to be unable to control one’s temper or desires, then one might be thought to lose freedom. Addiction can lead one to carry out actions one does not, in some sense, wish to perform, the craving leading to actions one regrets. Thus, drug and other addictions can lead to a loss of control and thereby freedom. External constraints mean that one cannot control events around one. Physical constraints mean that one cannot affect the world in the way one would desire. The extent to which events occur outside of one’s control can be thought to lead to a loss of freedom. In surveys, the degree to which people say they are free is largely determined by how much they feel they are in control of their lives and the world around them, demonstrating that freedom and control seem to be directly linked in people’s minds. Some writers, such as Amartya Sen, have denied the link between freedom and control. While recognizing the psychological link, Sen argues that freedom goes beyond personal control. He suggests that state action, such as enforcing vaccination, can reduce the incidence of disease. Thus, we are made free of disease, even though that freedom is outside of our control. He calls such freedom well-being freedom, and it is an aspect of his capability approach. A person’s capability is the degree to which the person is able to carry out his or her desires, and these abilities are enhanced by state actions that enable us. Some writers, such as Peter Morriss, have argued that Sen’s capability approach is simple power as ability. We can see, therefore, that control, power, freedom, and capability are four very closely linked concepts. Keith Dowding See also Ability; Capability; Freedom; Morriss, Peter Further Readings Dowding, K. (2006). Can capabilities reconcile freedom and equality? Journal of Political Philosophy, 14, 323–336. Sen, A. (1982). Liberty as control: An appraisal. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 7, 207–221. CONVENTIONAL DETERRENCE Deterrence is a strategy by which one actor, such as a government or state, attempts to prevent another actor from taking a particular course of action. Deterrence has been most closely associated with so-called weapons of mass destruction: one state has threatened another state to deter that state from taking a particular course of action by threatening to inflict great damage as a consequence. This was most clearly demonstrated in the cold war with the adoption of mutually assured destruction (MAD) where both sides developed a sufficiently large nuclear arsenal to prevent them from going into direct conflict with one another. However, deterrence is a far older concept and is not solely the preserve of weapons of mass destruction or, indeed, the preserve of states and their governments. States can develop deterrent relationships with nonstate actors, and such actors can also develop deterrent relationships with one another, thus resulting in the emergence of a code of conduct and a ceiling on the level of violence between them. Conventional deterrence covers the various forms of deterrence using conventional weapons. Here, conventional weapons are deemed to be those that exclude weapons of mass destruction—that is, not nuclear, chemical, biological, or radiological weapons. Like forms of deterrence involving weapons of mass destruction, conventional deterrence can be subdivided into two forms: deterrence by punishment and deterrence by denial. Deterrence by punishment threatens an opponent that if that opponent embarks on a particular course of action, the opponent will suffer from some form of attack that will lead to damage being inflicted on the opponent or its interests. Thus, the targeting focuses on the opponent and what level of pain needs to be threatened to prevent the opponent from taking a particular course of action. Deterrence by denial involves threatening the gain from a particular course of action: in other words, preventing the opponent from taking control of the very thing they want. Success is measured by an opponent’s deciding not to embark on the opponent’s intended course of action—that is, nothing happening, rather than by some form of gain. For example, a state may Cooperation create its own air defense capability that threatens any incursion of its air space by another. Success would be evidenced by a lack of incursions, not by the number of aircraft shot down while infringing the air space. For deterrence to successfully work, a number of factors need to be in play. First, there need to be two parties who acknowledge that they are in a deterrent relationship—a deterrer and a deterree. Failure to appreciate that there is a deterrent relationship will ensure that deterrence will fail. Thus, when asked why Britain failed to deter the Argentinean military from invading the Falklands in 1982, Britain’s Defense Secretary John Nott stated that he was unaware such a relationship existed. There needs to be a clear objective—the deterrer wants to stop the deterree from taking a particular course of action. There then needs to be some form of mechanism to persuade a deterree from taking the proposed course of action, such as a threat or series of threats. To undertake a deterrent relationship, there first needs to be some form of communication between the two parties so that each is aware that there may be consequences if a particular course of action is taken. The degree to which this needs to be opaque is debated, with some scholars arguing that a lack of clarity can add to the value of the threat. Second, both deterrer and deterree need to be able to conduct some form of cost-benefit analysis to evaluate the relative pros and cons of taking the proposed course of action. Third, deterrence in general assumes rationality—that in making this calculation the relevant decision makers will make a rational decision and that they define rationality along similar lines. Not surprisingly, deterrence theory has been criticized for its assumptions about rationality on three bases. First, it has been argued that suicidal or psychotic opponents may not be deterred by either form of deterrence. More generally, if rationality defined by cultural norms and practice is sufficiently different between the two parties, deterrence may easily fail. Second, there is plenty of scope for misunderstanding. The role of diplomacy is important here but can lead to errors. Third, the most logical way to undermine deterrence is to be irrational and become unpredictable. The results of such errors can be an escalation of mutual perceptions of threat leading to an arms 143 race, thus increasing the risk of actual war. Moreover, there is no agreement that such relationships should remain at the conventional level, and thus, a failure in conventional deterrence may lead to an escalation toward weapons of mass destruction. In fact, during the cold war NATO adopted the policy of flexible response, which began with conventional deterrence and proposed to escalate to strategic nuclear deterrence. Andrew M. Dorman See also Appeasement; Coercion and Power; Deterrent Threats; Diplomacy; Legitimation; Offense/Defense Dominance; Realism in International Relations; Strategic Power Index Further Readings Freedman, L. (2004). Deterrence. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Morgan, P. M. (1983). Deterrence: A conceptual analysis. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. COOPERATION At least since Mancur Olson’s The Logic of Collective Action (published in 1965), cooperation between human agents has generated an enormous academic literature, almost an industry in itself. In a famous phrase, Olson said that unless a group is small or there is some other coercive mechanism, self-interested people will not act to achieve their common or group interests. This particular problem of cooperation to which Olson refers has become known as the collective action or free-rider problem. The problem of cooperation had been recognized by others, of course. David Hume suggested that although two farmers might agree to dig a drainage channel between two fields and would be confident that each would turn up on the allotted day to help dig the channel, 100 people would not turn up to drain a field. Although it is in everyone’s interests to have the field drained, it is also in everyone’s interest not to contribute. Where many people are involved, each person can figure that if he or she does not turn up (a) no one will notice, 144 Cooperation and (b) there will still be enough others to successfully carry out the collective act. However, if everyone thinks like that, no one will turn up, and then everyone will be worse off. When there are only a few people involved, neither condition will hold and cooperation can occur. Of course, cooperation does occur between large numbers of people, and this “puzzle” has generated the large literature. First, we note that Olson makes clear that the problem occurs for selfinterested people; other-oriented people might still turn up (we consider that below), but first let us see how cooperation might occur even if people are fully self-interested. The Collective Action Problem The collective action problem is a problem, but not an insurmountable one. Olson himself provides solutions. Selective incentives can be offered to self-interested people. These might be side payments given to those who turn up, or they might consist of nonmaterial benefits, such as reciprocal friendliness. The degree of interaction between group members is also as important as small size. Although smaller numbers of people find it easier to cooperate than do large numbers, large groups can consist of smaller groups. Often in collective enterprises, groups of friends agree to meet and go along to the event together. Collective organizations are created with subgroups; armies consist of regiments, broken down into units or platoons. It is often said that soldiers do not fight for their country but for their comrades, and armies try to instill a sense of mission and loyalty within their constituent units for precisely that reason. Hence, interaction is more important than group size in itself. Face-to-face interaction among a small group of people may lead to subgroup mobilization no matter how large the wider group, thus overcoming the perceptibility problem mentioned earlier. Often, coordinating activities is a key issue. To overcome coordination difficulties, some actor or set of actors may need to step in. These coordinators provide a key role in ensuring both that individuals work together and that subunits within larger groups also cooperate. It is often easier to get people to work together to provide a one-off or so-called step public good because all can work toward a specific aim—such as digging a drainage ditch. But often tasks are ongoing—the field might need constant work to keep it drained—and getting people to cooperate in the long run is harder. Here, reciprocity is the key. If I act to help you, and then you act to help me, I am more likely to reciprocate next time round. For long-term tasks, people often create rosters so that each person knows when he or she is expected to contribute, each person can see that everyone else is doing their turn, and there are no free riders. In that way, cooperation is ensured. These sorts of processes help cooperation in face-to-face interaction with people one knows and can interact with in the future. But what about cooperation in societies with large numbers of people that we do not know and may not expect to interact with again? Car drivers know the problems of moving into heavy traffic, where one needs someone to slow slightly to let one in. In most societies, drivers do allow other drivers to join slow-moving heavy traffic. Here conventions emerge. Where two lanes of traffic merge into one, the convention is often for one car in the left lane to proceed followed by one car from the right lane, so that some form of equity exists between the two lanes of traffic. If one driver tries to cheat and get into line out of turn or an excessively generous driver lets several cars in, other drivers get annoyed because the convention they accept is broken. Standing in lines or queues is also conventional and can cause problems across cultures if the convention varies. In many Western cultures, the convention is to queue in turn as one arrives, but elsewhere men may take precedence over women or the old over the young, and so on. If people from different cultures have different understandings of the convention then cooperation breaks down, and anarchy can occur. Jon Elster has called such conventions the cement of society. The idea is that we need a point or understanding on which we can all focus so we cooperate smoothly when such collective action problems arise. In game-theoretic terms, these conventions are equilibriums of games. The equilibrium strategy is such that although all others play that strategy, each person has an incentive to abide by that strategy. (In practice, as in the previous examples, people can have incentives to depart, especially when there is no direct face-to-face Cooperation interaction as in the car examples.) However, complex games have multiple equilibriums (the different queuing conventions in different cultures, for example) and the convention adopted might not be the optimal one. In the example of two lanes of cars merging into one, for example, the optimal strategy for both lanes would be to drive right to the end of the lane and then join. In that way, new cars joining the two queues could see which lane was shorter and join that for efficiency and equity. However, car drivers tend to move into one lane long before the other gives out. They might join it at different points, confusing the equitable convention and making it hard for the late-coming cars to judge which lane to join. Changing from suboptimal to optimal conventions can be problematic. Many of the conventions and ways of behaving that we adopt cannot really be sustained by fully self-interested people. There are too many ways in which we could cheat without being detected, but we tend not to. However, that is not to say there are not mechanisms that lead us to cooperate where we could cheat. The most obvious one is the internal feelings of guilt and shame that we have if we were to cheat. These feelings seem to be an evolutionary response to the problem of selfinterested behavior. Natural Selection and Selfish Genes In his book The Selfish Gene, Richard Dawkins first suggested that we can view our genes as selfish, which can help explain why we are not. Natural selection is the evolutionary process by which genes are replicated. The “selfish” aspect of the gene is the metaphor that it exists to self-replicate. Associated with genes are phenotypes, body shapes, and behaviors that enable the gene vehicle—plants and animals—to reproduce themselves and, hence, the genes themselves. In extended phenotypes, the genes manipulate the behavior of other vehicles to enhance the ability of their vehicle to thrive and survive and pass on its genes through sexual reproduction. Genes can be thought of as adopting game-theoretic strategies that will increase their chances of being reproduced; in that sense, genes can be thought of as equilibrium selection devices. They will select reciprocal cooperation when playing with another vehicle if that is in the interests of both. In some circumstances, gene 145 vehicles will cooperate altruistically, especially with kin, because those vehicles will also contain genes hosted by their own vehicle. William Hamilton produced the idea of kin selection where some behavior will be replicated more often if it considers the reproductive opportunities that behavior provides for its own vehicle and the extra reproductive opportunities it provides for other vehicles that are related. Illustrating this, J. B. S. Haldane, asked if he would give his life for another, joked that he would if he saved two brothers or eight cousins. In our cultural heritage, we often lived in small kin-related groups. Many of our reactions in cooperative situations that lead us to behave altruistically are based on internal incentives to cooperate derived from the reciprocity we expect from small groups and kinship. Cooperative behavior in animals has been documented in thousands of case studies that show that the degree of cooperation between different types and groups of animals is highly related to their degree of kinship. The complete social behavior of hymenoptera such as ants and bees, who share (almost) completely the same genetic structure is the most stark example. The genetic story can help tell us why we are not completely self-interested and how aspects of our individual makeup are social in character. However, it would be wrong to immediately conclude that humans are simply stimulus–response gene-vehicles. People do have beliefs and desires and do consciously strategize, sometimes for their own benefit and sometimes for the benefit of others to whom they are neither kin-related nor reciprocally interacting. Many of our beliefs about how to behave cooperatively with others are taught to us by our parents, teachers, and clergy. We also learn the conventions of our society unconsciously by watching and interacting with others. We are natural imitators (indeed the neural mechanisms that led to imitation have been identified). We learn our cooperative behaviors, and sometimes have to learn them anew when we move from one community to another with different conventions. As part of this cooperative enterprise, our own beliefs about cooperation can become important, whether they be “looking after Number One” or “do unto others as you would be done by.” These beliefs are learned, in part through the conventions and general morality of our own society, but then become enforced through behavior. Some of these 146 Coordination behaviors are acquired from a very early age. It has been suggested that the amount of trust displayed by people is related to how quickly they were attended to when crying as babies and that children whose families are highly geographically mobile are less trusting than are those who have always lived in the same community. But certainly adults can learn to become more or less trusting through the experiences they have as adults. A single traumatic event can cause someone to be less trusting and cooperative. Conventions might be the cement of society, but cooperation beyond conventions and norms ensures that people have much greater powers to gain more of what they want than they could attain on their own. Our evolutionary heritage has ensured that we can cooperate, but we also learn to cooperate through interacting with others around us, and because we can recognize that cooperation is good for us all in the long run. It is important that people are not too trusting, or they can be exploited, but cooperation is best attained through reciprocal action both directly and indirectly through learned norms. free-rider problem exists. In situations of pure coordination, there is no free-rider problem but, rather, a problem of agreeing on the mutually beneficial strategies. A simple coordination game is the decision about which side of the road to drive on. Two drivers meeting on a two-lane highway would sooner both drive on the left or both drive on the right so they can pass each other without problem. We can represent this as a simple two-by-two normal form game, shown below. Here, we can see there are two equilibriums, Left-Left and Right-Right. The coordination problem is for each to agree which of the equilibrium strategies to choose. Once one of the strategies is chosen, there is no problem in each maintaining that equilibrium strategy because neither has any incentive to depart from them. 1,1 0,0 0,0 1,1 Keith Dowding See also Alliances; Collective Action Problem; Coordination; Game-Theoretical Approaches to Power; Noncooperative Games; Public Goods Further Readings Axelrod, R. (1984). The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books. Dawkins, R. (1978). The selfish gene. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Elster, J. (1989). The cement of society: A study of social order. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Hamilton, W. (1963). The evolution of altruistic behavior. American Naturalist, 97, 354–356. COORDINATION Where each agent can realize mutual gains through making mutually consistent decisions, the problem is one of coordination—a simpler problem to solve than a collective action problem where the Often there might be no reason why we choose particular solutions to coordination problems, or the reasons are lost in history. It has been suggested that driving on the left-hand side in the United Kingdom was based on a convention that knights would pass each other with the sword hand (right-handedness being dominant) on the side toward the other, but this claim might be apocryphal (and does not explain the opposite convention in other countries). Thomas Schelling introduced the notion of a focal point that many people would regard as a good coordinating device, such as Times Square if they were meeting in New York but had not agreed a meeting place. When faced with this matrix, for example, most subjects in experiments opt for the top left-hand box rather than the lower right, suggesting that somehow that is the focal point where people can coordinate their actions. Keith Dowding See also Collective Action Problem; Cooperation Core Parties Further Readings Cooper, R. W. (1998). Coordination games. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. CORE OF A GAME The core of a game is a central concept in cooperative game theory. Core of a game refers to situations in which individuals can gain from cooperating in groups, but there is conflict over the allocation of the gains from cooperation. An allocation is in the core if no subgroup of individuals can unilaterally improve the position of all its members. An allocation in the core is presumably stable: once achieved, there is no incentive to move away from it. It is also efficient in the sense that no other allocation makes all individuals better off. The power of an individual can be measured by how favorably the individual is treated by the allocations in the core in comparison with other feasible allocations. Allocations in the core can be very extreme. For example, suppose a group of three voters must decide on the division of a resource. Three votes are needed to pass a proposal, with one voter controlling two votes and two voters controlling one vote each. The first voter has veto power because no proposal can be passed without that person’s votes. The core allocates the entire resource to the veto voter. Given any other allocation (say, one that gives a positive share to the second voter), the first and third voter together can pass a proposal that divides the second voter’s share between them. The core does not consider the possibility of forming voting blocs. In this example, the two nonveto voters together have as many votes as the veto voter. If these two voters are able to act together as a single unit, there is no compelling reason why the veto voter must obtain the whole resource. There may be more than one outcome in the core. If there are two voters that must agree on the division of a resource, any division that exhausts the resource is in the core because no voter can change the division unilaterally and it is not possible to make both voters better off. 147 The core may also be empty. Suppose a voting body with three voters must divide a resource by simple majority. Given any allocation, there are always two voters that would do better by dividing the third voter’s share between them. If the core is empty, the situation is potentially unstable because given any outcome, there is a subgroup that has the ability and motivation to enforce a different one. More generally, assuming that voters decide on the division of a fixed resource, the core is either empty (in the absence of veto voters) or distributes everything between the veto voters. Thus, the veto voters have all the power in the group according to the core. When voters are voting over a choice of policy or any other issue, the core is defined in the same way: a policy is in the core if no group of voters prefers another policy and can enforce it. If policies can be unambiguously ranked along some dimension, the core corresponds to the outcome preferred by the median voter. The core has been criticized as being a myopic stability concept: the existence of a profitable deviation automatically disqualifies an outcome as stable. However, even if a profitable deviation exists, individuals may abstain from deviating, fearing that whatever improvement they agree on may itself be overturned by subsequent deviations by other subgroups, with the ultimate result of making some of them worse off than they originally were. Maria Montero See also Coalition Theory; Shapley Value; Veto Players; Weighted Majority Game Further Readings Kahan, J. P., & Rapoport, A. (1984). Theories of coalition formation. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Myerson, R. B. (1991). Game theory: Analysis of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. CORE PARTIES In spatial voting games, the Condorcet winner is any policy or candidate that defeats all other 148 Corporatism policies or candidates in pairwise votes. However, what can we say about potential outcomes if there is no Condorcet winner? Let us define a set X as the set of feasible outcomes corresponding to vectors that denote the utility u of each player (ui, u2, u3,) to be a specific vector (i.e., point) in X. Assume that a coalition C prefers u to u if and only if ui u’I for all individuals I in C. Define the coalition of individuals C to be effective for u in X if the members of C can coordinate their actions sufficiently to ensure that each member i of C receives a payoff of at least ui. Let v(C) denote the set of all utility n-tuples for which C is effective. Now we say that u dominates u if there exists at least one coalition that is effective for u and that prefers u to u. A cooperative game’s core is then defined as the set of undominated elements of X. A core party is then defined as any party that in a voting game occupies the core of the game. In coalition theory, core parties will always form the government or be an element in a coalition government. Formal coalition theory has demonstrated that majority voting rules always generate a core in one-dimensional policy space, which means that there will always be a core party where politics is dominated by one dimension— such as a left–right ideological dimension. However, if we assume that the preferences of players are randomly assigned, then a core is generated only unusually in two dimensions and rarely if ever in three or more dimensions. It is usually assumed that under such circumstances voting cycles will be generated. However, if the public’s preferences are not randomly generated, but rather are socially determined to bunch together in policy space, then a core is more likely to form, and so will core parties. Empirically, in many systems, some parties are usually members of coalition governments, and such parties are core parties within those systems. Keith Dowding See also Coalition Theory; Core of a Game; Dominant Parties; Grand Coalition Further Readings Laver, M., & Schofield, N. (1990). Multiparty government. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. CORPORATISM The core meaning of corporatism is an institutional relationship between governing authorities and the representation of interests, notably capital and labor, with the central organs of the state. In this sense, corporatism is closely associated with fascist ideology, notably in Italy and Germany, which promoted capitalist enterprise but directed it into specific works and, with strong links to labor movements, ensured a harmony of control between the major interest groups in society. After World War II, sometimes with the prefix neo-, corporatism became associated with a dominant state that mediated, usually through formal tripartite agreements, macroeconomic conditions between employers and labor unions. During the late 1970s and 1980s, corporatism or neocorporatism was lauded by many academics as providing a high level of macroeconomic performance, both controlling inflation and maintaining relatively low levels of unemployment. At that time, corporatism was associated with Keynesianism. However, the precise form of corporatism and its relationship to state power structures has been much debated. Interest in corporatism revived among political scientists in the 1970s with Philippe Schmitter’s 1974 Review of Politics article, “Still the Century of Corporatism?” He contrasted corporatism (or neocorporatism) as a form of interest representation that differed from other state forms such as pluralism, statism, and syndicalism. He saw it as a distinct system of political power relations that affected macroeconomic and social forces within states. Within the literature were those who concentrated on corporatism as an institutional form through which interests are represented and by which contestation between different sides of the capital divide was contained and those who saw it more as a form of policy making that did not necessarily include specific institutional structures. In the first, specific formal institutional structures included social pacts made between government and the overarching capital and labor organizations, peak organizations that represented employers and workers within those pacts, tripartite negotiations led by government, and regulatory functions accorded to nonstate organizations such Corporatism as employers’ groups or major trade unions. Within the second, it was recognized that not all (or even any) of these formal institutional structures were necessary for corporatism to hold at least at times within a country. All that was needed was coordination by the state to guide agreements between different interests with a degree of integration into the state of organized groups. Within these structures, a host of types of corporatism were identified, such as mesocorporatism, which concerned clusters of groups around specific interests such as industrial or professional sectors, or private interest government concerning the selfregulation of professional groups. The central theoretical concern was how corporate states handled issues of public goods, statelevel collective action problems, and the national economy. In the 1970s, states were recovering from oil price rises, raging inflation, and higher unemployment, which were challenging the Keynesian orthodoxy of the postwar period. Many writers argued that corporatist states fared better than did more free market or pluralist ones. Under pluralism, the forces of capital and labor were ranged against each other as unions strived to bring about inflation-proof wage rises and resisted new work practices to maintain employment levels while firms struggled to contain labor unrest. The mix was not conducive to controlling inflation or enabling growth through capital investment. However, tripartite corporatist arrangements were thought to help overcome these problems. Through the facilitation of government, peak-level organizations on both the employer and labor sides could negotiate to ensure longer-term strategies over wages and work conditions, allowing government to manage the economy in Keynesian fashion, enabling growth to promote future profit, wages rises, and job security. Various comparative analyses of economies suggested that on issues such as inflation, employment, and investment, the nations that seemed more corporatist were doing better than were those that were more pluralist. It would seem that corporatist arrangements did enable the state to overcome state-level collective action problems to promote the public goods of low inflation, high employment, and economic growth, making everyone better off. Both the models of corporatism and the politicaleconomic analyses were not uncontroversial, not 149 least because identifying which countries were most corporatist was not straightforward, and how well countries were doing over a range of indicators was subject to the time frames of the econometric analyses that were conducted. Furthermore, by the end of the 1980s and into the 1990s, countries that were pluralist were perceived to be doing better, especially where the more informal corporatist relationships were replaced. Many of the formal corporatist nations such as Austria and Finland were not doing so well on the macroeconomic indicators in comparison with some pluralist nations such as the United States and United Kingdom. Analysts suggested that corporatism was not suited to the changing nature of capitalism, with the demise of heavy industry and manufacturing and the rise of the service industry (post-Fordism) in the developed world. New technology required faster reorganization and entrepreneurial activity flourished better in less regulated societies. Keynesianism was going out of fashion and the ability of countries to protect their economies from worldwide market forces reduced as globalization took off. Even in the heartland of corporatism, Sweden, centralized wage bargaining ended in the late 1980s. This seemed to be the death knell of corporatism as a distinct form of state organization, both empirically as a description of some states, and normatively as more pluralist states did better economically, suggesting that corporatism was also bankrupt as an ideal form of interest mediation able to supply important social and public goods. Some have argued that corporatism did not disappear but rather evolved into new forms of political exchange. To be sure, interest mediation involving the state still exists in many countries, albeit at more local rather than overarching national levels. Also the recognition of new social movements that represent interests outside of the capital– labor divide, such as environmental, feminist, and others, entered into the realm of interest mediation. However, these claims about corporatism becoming a state form where the central state authorities accept a role for interest groups as social partners in social, political, and economic exchange can hardly be termed a new form of corporatism because such a specification does not differ from the pluralism that corporatism or neocorporatism was supposed to rival. Corporatist arrangements 150 Corruption might once more come into fashion as states start to reregulate after the global financial crisis at the end of the first decade of the 21st century. Furthermore, the state-directed capitalist arrangement of Asian states such as South Korea and China has elements of corporatism contained within it. These states have managed to sustain growth and growing employment as capitalism takes off. In such semi-democratic and nondemocratic countries, especially in post-communist China, corporatism looks more like its original prewar form in Europe and might herald a more corporatist organization in developed democratic countries. Keith Dowding See also Collective Action Problem; Fascism; Globalization; Post-Fordism; Public Goods Further Readings Iverson, T. (1999). Contested economic institutions: The politics of macroeconomics and wage bargaining. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Schmitter, P. (1974). Still the century of corporatism? Review of Politics, 36, 85–131. Williamson, P. (1985). Varieties of corporatism: Theory and practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. CORRUPTION The general understanding of corruption involves the corrupt actor occupying a position that vests in him or her power, authority, or trust within a public institution or office. When the actor engages in an act that abuses this power, authority, or trust, the act is said to be corrupt. In some jurisdictions, the abuse of office is itself a criminal act. However, the act itself need not be criminal to be classified as corrupt. Thus, an employee of a private company who engages in embezzlement is guilty of fraud but does not, in the general understanding of the term, engage in corruption. However, if the organization were a government organization, the fraud may be considered corruption. Conversely, where a senior bureaucrat in a private firm uses his or her authority to sway potential voters, the act would be unlikely to be criminal in itself. If the firm were public, however, the act may be considered corrupt and, in certain jurisdictions, attract criminal sanctions. The difficulty of distinguishing between the legal and conceptual definition of corruption has led some theorists to define corruption as a purely legal issue. In this account, a corrupt act only occurs where formal laws or guidelines are breached. The rationale for this is that such formal definitions are stable and precise. One of the most prominent examples of this kind of definitions is that from J. S. Nye, who defines corruption as “behaviour which deviates from the formal duties of a public role because of private regarding (personal, close family, private clique) pecuniary or status gains); or violates rules against the exercise of certain types of private-regarding influence” (1967, p. 418). This type of narrow definition has been contested. Michael Johnston, for example, rejects the idea that corruption must be defined in formal terms. He also rejects the idea that corruption can only take place in the context of public office but does say that it generally involves “public power” or public resources. Johnston holds that corruption is the abuse of public roles or resources for private benefit where public, private, and benefit are contentions and ambiguous. This definition makes it difficult to classify any particular action as corrupt, so Johnston takes a view that systemic corruption problems are the proper subject of study rather than the attempt to forensically define the concept of corruption. The idea is that systemic corruption exists where wealth and power are used to weaken, prevent, or delay the development of participative economic or political institutions. As Johnston points out, this definition of corruption can include actions that are legal and therefore opens the way for a conceptualization that takes far more account of the cultural context than the strictly legal approach does. In this vein, Georg Cremer points out that the concept of corruption can only apply when the behavior of an official contradicts the norms of his or her society. Similarly, Carl Friedrich and Philip Jos hold that laws and codes of conduct are not nearly as important for the definition of corruption as is the extent to which an actor in a public role violates standards and expectations associated with that role. Coup d’État The notion that corruption entails the abuse of power has been challenged by some who downplay the perceived negative aspects of corruption in favor of the positive ability of corruption to “grease the wheels” of an inefficient bureaucratic system. For example, Cremer points out that bribery of public officials may be a way of circumventing highly intrusive bureaucratic practices as well as enabling competition where the government has attempted to restrict competition. Bribery has also been seen as an efficient means of speeding up bureaucratic decision making, particularly where public officials can threaten those waiting on their decisions with delays unless a bribe is paid. Detractors of this view point out that the empirical evidence indicates that higher levels of corruption are associated with lower levels of economic performance. Although this may be true for corruption in aggregate, there seems to be a curvilinear relationship between corruption and economic performance. Thus, at certain levels of corruption, high levels of economic growth are possible. Oskar Kurer gives the example of Thailand and Italy to illustrate such a situation and contrasts these countries with those of sub-Saharan Africa in which corruption has exceeded the “critical” level and has resulted in a collapse in public infrastructure. In the latter cases, the putative power of the briber to offer a bribe has been subverted by the power of the official to demand a bribe. Critics of the curvilinear account of corruption point out that there are actually very few countries that prosper with high levels of corruption and conclude that there is an alternative explanation for their success. Mushtaq H. Khan, for example, holds that economically successful countries with high levels of corruption prosper because they use “patrimonial” rather than “clientelist” networks as media for the flow of influence. The idea here is that the phenomenon of corruption depends on semiformal patron–client networks. There are two broad categories of such networks. Patrimonial networks enable state-based agents to protect their access to gains from corruption. These are usually extant in countries that have a long history of the division of access to property “rights” (as, for example, in Thailand, Italy, and South Korea). In such countries, the state has more power than any other individual interested party and can therefore allocate rights on the basis of economic considerations as the political 151 questions are largely determined. In contrast, clientelist networks are characterized by weakly defined access to gains and require state and nonstate parties to compete. These are the norm in developing countries because they tend to occur in countries without a long history of defined allocations of rights. Developing countries tend to have underdeveloped civic institutions supporting them, so it is therefore difficult for state officials to monopolize rents from newly emerging resources. Significant efficiency costs are incurred in the clientelist network because state officials are likely to award rights to resources more on the basis of political concerns than on prospects for value adding. Michael Dalvean See also Blackmail; Bribe Index; Fungibility of Power Resources Further Readings Cremer, G. (2008). Corruption and development aid. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Johnston, M. (2005). Syndromes of corruption. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Khan, M. H. (1996). The efficiency implications of corruption. Journal of International Development, 8(5), 683–696. Kurer, O. (2001). Why do voters support corrupt politicians? In A. K. Jain (Ed.), The political economy of corruption. London: Routledge. Nye, J. S. (1967). Corruption and political development: A cost-benefit analysis. American Political Science Review, 61(2), 417–427. COUP D’ÉTAT A coup d’état is an illegal change of government speedily effected by a group based within the machinery of state through the threat or actual use of violence. Coups d’état are important to the study of power in three ways. In being a means for overthrowing governments, they highlight the critical point of regime change and the implications that follow for the transfer of power under conditions of illegality. In using the threat or 152 Coup d’État actual use of violence, coups also direct interest to the debates about power and force as separate concepts. In being carried out by a group from within the state, coups also draw attention to the locus of power beyond the formal holders of political office. As a particular means for overthrowing government, coups feature similar techniques and the military is usually involved. Explanations for coups d’état vary, essentially depending on whether reasons for the military to intervene are sought or their general underlying causes are investigated. The Nature of Coups The ideal coup d’état is swift, impeccably planned, and perfectly executed. To avoid detection at the planning stage conspiracy is essential. By virtue of the similarities between the institutions of governments, the techniques employed usually include the capturing of the telecommunications center and other key points, such as police and military headquarters and the presidential palace and, of course, the arrest of the most powerful state personnel. Given the state’s monopoly of coercion, the active or passive support of at least some of the armed forces would also be sought at the planning stage. Because of the military’s particularly advantageous qualifications for staging coups—being within the state apparatus and possessing the means for threatening violence—the military is normally involved. Coups can be staged entirely by the military, though the involvement of both military and civilian personnel is more usually the case and sometimes entirely civilian governments are installed. Explaining Coups A number of explanations have been offered for why coups occur, including some concentrating on personal or military grievances. Following the spate of coups in the new nations of Africa and Asia in the 1960s, coups came to be seen as the agents of economic and political development with the military viewed as a modernizing force intent, eventually, on handing back power to democratically elected government. This does sometimes happen, and in more recent years, coups have become less frequent and democratic institutions, such as elections, have been more commonly used. By the 1970s, however, it became clear that coups could also result in repressive dictatorships. The growing numbers of subsequent coups within new nations also undermined the view of coups as agents of modernization. These also showed that the military could be in conflict within itself, a finding in line with the longer history of coups in Latin America and coups that occurred in Greece in 1967 and 1973 and in Portugal in 1974. More compatible with repeat coups, an alternative explanation focused on the effects of colonialism in creating ethnic and social cleavages through the drawing of artificial state boundaries and establishing economies to serve capitalist world markets. In this line of argument, attention has also been drawn to the role of the U.S. Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) in assisting coups that protect capitalist markets against left-leaning governments. Class analysis, too, has been employed— with the high-ranking members of the military viewed as the sons of the middle class and the taking of political power interpreted as the means to acquire economic power. Although the reasons why coups are staged may vary, some general underlying conditions can be identified. This is helped by their frequency: more than half of third world countries have had one or more coups d’état. Their general underlying conditions follow from the importance of the economy to government’s responsibilities: the types of economies that are especially vulnerable to economic instability and general uncertainty are likely, therefore, to lead to accusations of incompetence and corruption of even the most competent and least corrupt governments. These economic conditions are typical of countries whose economic sector is producing primary goods for export, trading them on the world market, with the government highly dependent on the revenues from these exports. Primary goods—coffee, bananas, copper, and the like—are highly susceptible to large fluctuations in their world market prices and vulnerable to variations in production. Of such countries, the most vulnerable to coups are those that are specialized in their exports: for where a single major export forms a large percentage of all exports, fluctuations in prices, production, and government revenues are especially likely to generate economic instability. Because of a lack of resources to alleviate the social Cox, Robert W. and economic repercussions, poorer such countries have an added vulnerability to coups. A coup is most likely to be staged at the height of the government’s loss of support, the culmination of export-induced economic instability, but in the conspirators’ calculations of success, other factors should be considered. The presence of foreign troops is one factor: they may intervene to reverse a coup attempt. Governments may be given some time in office before being apportioned blame for incompetence or corruption in managing the economy, and the conspirators are more likely to be apprehensive about staging the first coup. As a strategy based on careful planning in which conspiracy is of the essence, mistakes may also be made. A coup attempt offers no guarantee of success, but the presence of underlying conditions ensures that further opportunities will arise. It also follows from those conditions generating economic instability largely out of government control, that new governments installed by coups, too, will face the same accusations of incompetence and corruption. It follows also, therefore, that once a country has had a coup d’état, further coups are likely. Rosemary H. T. O’Kane See also Dictatorship; Legitimation; Military in Government; Right-Wing Authoritarianism; Terror Regimes Further Readings Jackman, R. W. (1978). The predictability of coups d’état. American Political Science Review, 72, 1262–1275. Luttwak, E. (1969). Coup d’état: A practical handbook. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin. O’Kane, R. H. T. (1987). The likelihood of coups. Aldershot, UK: Gower. O’Kane, R. H. T. (1993). Coups d’état in Africa. Journal of Peace Research, 30, 251–270. COX, ROBERT W. (1926– ) Robert W. Cox was born in Canada in 1926 and was educated at McGill University where he 153 completed a BA (1946) and an MA (1948) in history. Before embarking on an academic career, Cox spent 25 years at the International Labour Organization (ILO) from which he retired in August 1972 after serving as executive assistant to the director general, chief of the Research and Planning Department, and director of the International Institute for Labour Studies. After leaving the UN system, he held various professorial positions at the Graduate Institute of International Studies; Columbia University; University of Toronto; Yale University; and the Australian National University. Currently, he is emeritus professor of political science at York University, Toronto. Cox’s earlier scholarly contribution primarily reflected an interest in the study of the processes of international organization grounded in utopian functionalism and in a desire to contribute to the development of methods and approaches that would generate more scientific and nonnormative perspectives. However, the contributions for which Cox is best known are those that he develops influenced by Giambattista Vico, Antonio Gramsci, and Fernand Braudel and that form the basis of the neo-Gramscian perspective in international relations. Since the 1980s, unlike his prior scholarly contributions, Cox’s work detaches itself from positivism to embrace the method of historical structures or critical historicisms, namely a postpositivist approach primarily concerned with understanding the emergence of world orders within which dominant norms, institutions, and practices become established. Critical historicism, however, is not simply a theory of history concerned with the past but is also an “emancipatory” approach intending to identify which social forces could challenge the prevailing distribution of power at any given time. Cox’s method of historical structures is conceived as an interdependent and dialectical configuration of changing forces—material capabilities, ideas, and institutions—that create opportunities and impose constraints on human activity and social practices. This configuration of forces is said by Cox to create pressure across three interrelated levels, namely the basic level of production, state– civil society complexes, and world orders. Cox’s complex ontology serves the purpose of explaining relative stability (as opposed to equilibrium) within 154 Critical Theory a historical juncture or world order; stability is equated to the concepts of hegemonic and nonhegemonic historical structures that underpin Cox’s conceptualizations of power in international affairs. Unlike neorealists, Cox argues that relationships of dominance and control cannot rest on the preponderance of military and economic capabilities of a single state but ought to be understood as a configuration of material power, prevalent images of world order, and a set of institutions that administer that order; this particular kind of dominance would need to be based on a broad measure of consent while offering some prospects of satisfaction to the less powerful. Hence, this conceptualization presupposes that power emerges from social processes rather than being located within the result of relations of production; accordingly, at particular historical junctures, changing social relations of production give rise to particular social forces, leading states or social classes that become the base of power and can engender transformation within and across states and within a specific world order. As Timothy Sinclair and Michael Schechter illustrate, Cox’s approach has invariably been criticized for his ontological and epistemological eclecticism; the neglect of issues of importance such as security, gender, and ecology; and his shifting pessimism and utopianism. Nonetheless, he is generally recognized, even by his critics, as the first major scholar to use critical theory in international relations. Catia Gregoratti See also Gramsci, Antonio; Neorealism; Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Further Readings Cox, R. W. (1969). International organisation: World politics. London: Macmillan. Cox, R. W., & Jacobson, H. (1973). The anatomy of influence: Decision making in international organization. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Cox, R. W., & Schechter, M. G. (2002). The political economy of a plural world: Critical reflections on power, morals and civilization. London: Routledge. Cox, R. W., & Sinclair, T. J. (1996). Approaches to world order. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. CRITICAL THEORY A critical theory is a theory of society that aims to emancipate those subjected to relations of domination or power. In contrast to the contemplative model of knowledge implicit in the Greek etymology of theory—which comes from the word theǀros or “a spectator”—critical theory regards the pursuit of knowledge as a politically engaged activity. In part, this is because social power involves more than just manipulative resources or force. Relations of power and domination also depend on particular attitudes and beliefs, or purported knowledge. It follows that by confirming or refuting beliefs or attitudes, theory has implications for corresponding patterns of domination. Whether explicitly or implicitly, knowingly or unknowingly, theory always “takes sides,” whether in defense or in defiance of power. For critical theory, this political commitment is explicit and self-conscious. The Frankfurt School Critical theory in this sense is associated primarily with the influential branch of Western Marxism known as the Frankfurt School. This name derives from its association with the Frankfurt Institute of Social Research, which was founded in 1923 at the University of Frankfurt. The institute’s associates have included Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, Carl Grünberg, Erich Fromm, Otto Kirchheimer, Friedrich Pollock, Henryk Grossmann, and Walter Benjamin. It was originally set up for the pursuit of Marxist studies with the support of the wealthy philanthropist Felix Weil. However, under the leadership of its second director, Max Horkheimer, the institute’s most prominent members increasingly moved away from Marxist orthodoxy. Frankfurt theorists were disillusioned by the increasingly authoritarian course of the Russian Revolution after 1917. In the West, sporadic communist uprisings in Germany, following its defeat in World War I and the abdication of the kaiser, were short-lived. Later events only confirmed the need to rethink Marxist orthodoxy. Marxist revolutionary parties either drifted toward reformist social democracy or maintained a theoretically Critical Theory pure but practically ineffectual isolation. The prospects for genuine socialist revolution declined further with the cataclysm of German fascism and the Holocaust. After World War II, an affluent consumer society in the West ensured a mostly quiescent working class. By the end of the 20th century, communist regimes in Russia and Eastern Europe had collapsed and China was reverting to an authoritarian variant of capitalism. “Revisionist” social democracy, which originally promised a gradual advance toward socialism, had abandoned the socialist ideal altogether. Despite such gloomy historical prospects for socialism, the writings of Karl Marx remained an inspiring beacon of rigorous intellectual activity, pursued on behalf of the exploited masses of capitalism. Frankfurt theorists followed the lead of the Hungarian communist intellectual, Georg Lukács who, in “What Is Orthodox Marxism,” sets out to rescue the critical method embodied in Marx’s writings from what had become the unquestionable dogmas of the Third International. The valuable kernel of Marx’s method should not be sought in his detailed economic and sociological predictions, which had proved eminently fallible, but rather in his revolutionary understanding of the dialectical relationship between theory and practice, between philosophy and political action. In the famous words of Marx’s 11th “Thesis on Feuerbach,” until now “The philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the point is to change it.” A concrete example of Marx’s ideal of an engaged and activist philosophy is his “critique of political economy.” Marx became convinced that the ultimate basis of human alienation and oppression— most visible in the impoverished working classes but everywhere in evidence in 19th-century industrial society—was capitalism. His extensive studies of Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and other political economists convinced him, however, that “bourgeois” political economy would never penetrate beneath the surface of capitalism because it failed to recognize the historical contingency and exploitative nature of the capitalist mode of production. The political economists could not see either that the industrial proletariat would eventually become capitalism’s “grave digger.” Worse, by obscuring the exploitative reality and revolutionary possibilities of capitalism, the supposedly eternal and 155 objective truths of political economy—the prototype of contemporary economic science—only perpetuated this exploitative system. Bourgeois political economy, in other words, is not science but ideology. An ideology in Marx’s sense is a body of ideas masquerading as neutral and objective theory but, in effect if not intentionally, serving as the “ruling ideas” of the ruling class. Marx’s critique of ideology, conversely, uncovers concealed relations of power and so makes it possible to transform them. Marx reveals an otherwise hidden path of social development— the revolutionary overthrow of capitalism and the construction of communism—and corresponding political choices. In that sense, following Jürgen Habermas, we can see the critique identifying a “crisis” (krisis) in its original Greek sense of “judgment” or “decision.” The Frankfurt School’s further pursuit of critical theory has two major dimensions. In the first place, these researchers draw from Marx’s method a philosophical critique of traditional” (as opposed to critical) theory. What they often refer to as positivism derives from the term used by Auguste Comte in the 1830s to describe the final stage of modern, scientific civilization. After stages dominated by religious and metaphysical thinking, humanity finally attains to genuine science, which is based only on the observation of positive facts. The extension of the methods of natural science to the behavioral and social sciences, however, constitutes positivism in the Frankfurt School sense. Already in the 18th century, David Hume had proposed that the empirical method so successfully applied in natural sciences such as physics and astronomy should be applied to the “sciences of man.” But according to Frankfurt theorists, the positivist social sciences of the 20th century, like the bourgeois political economy criticized by Marx, are implicitly ideological. By representing society as a quasi-natural system whose patterns and regularities can be observed and predicted, these theorists obscure the possibility of transformative political action. Although the Frankfurt School’s critique of positivism ultimately derives from Marx, it can also be applied to the renewal of Marxism. This is because, after Marx’s death, the communist movement was itself drawn into the orbit of positivism, largely under the influence of Marx’s long-time 156 Critical Theory collaborator Friedrich Engels. The systematization of “scientific socialism” was, according to Frankfurt theorists, a retreat from genuinely critical philosophy with dire consequences for the socialist project. “Iron laws” guarantee that communism is the foreseeable goal or telos of history. It was correspondingly easier for Bolsheviks and Stalinists to dismiss merely “bourgeois” moral scruples because morally dubious means could never threaten the utopian outcome guaranteed by “science.” Assumptions about the inevitable course of historical development sit uneasily with V. I. Lenin’s “voluntarist” insistence on the essential role of political will. Revolution will only occur through the decisive and timely intervention of a militant party, whose authority is ultimately based on Marxism’s scientific knowledge of capitalism. Positivism, in other words, deforms the socialist project at the same time as it insulates capitalist power relations from renewed critique. The second, more constructive dimension of the Frankfurt School’s project involves members’ own contributions to the renewal of critical theory under the changed conditions of 20th-century, “advanced” capitalism. They also take advantage of intellectual developments since Marx’s time, including the iconoclastic writings of Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche had shaken complacent 19thcentury convictions: belief in God and the “lies” of idealist metaphysics, as well as Hegelian and Marxist assumptions about the advancing dialectic of history. Under the influence of both Nietzsche and the sociologist Max Weber—who was himself influenced by Nietzsche—Adorno and Horkheimer sketched the history of the West’s “overcoming of myth and superstition” as a contradictory and ultimately destructive “dialectic of Enlightenment.” A later product of rationalization of Western society is the positivist faith in instrumental rationality. Instrumental rationality is confined to the calculation of efficient means to given ends, but is indifferent to the intrinsic moral worth of the ends in question. According to Adorno and Horkheimer, this limited conception of rationality is implicated in the Marquis de Sade’s cruel and calculating fantasies as well as in the ruthless efficiency of Nazi Germany’s genocidal bureaucracy. Another important influence was Sigmund Freud’s psychoanalysis, which had unsettled the West’s self-confident rationalism in a different way, even though Freud tended to see his own psychoanalytic insights in conventional scientific terms. Freud drew examples from art and literature and based his theories on individual case histories, dreams, and slips of the tongue rather than any systematic empirical observation. His theory of the unconscious mind, with its defense mechanisms and self-deceiving rationalizations, dispelled any illusions—prevalent at least since René Descartes— of the self’s rationality and transparency. The emphasis on the unconscious and often irrational roots of belief and action helped explain popular support for National Socialism, Stalinism, and other oppressive regimes. Other studies suggested—for example, the work of Marcuse—that liberal values of autonomy, self-reliance, and responsibility were under threat from the social conformity and “organization” mentality of advanced capitalism. The condition of art and culture is a further factor, identified by Frankfurt theorists, crucial for the fate of relations of domination in contemporary society. Frankfurt theorists were dismissive of crudely determinist applications of Marx’s materialist approach, which saw art and literature as merely “superstructural” results of developments in the economic “base.” By implication, bourgeois art was dismissed as little more than a passive reflection of the realities of capitalist exploitation. In the Soviet Union, artists and writers were forced to abandon the “elitist” aspirations of artistic modernism for the sake of the more accessible and proletarian aesthetics of socialist realism. Adorno and other Frankfurt theorists insisted instead on the critical potential of genuine art and its at least relative autonomy from prevailing social conditions. Even bourgeois works of art could challenge the alienated social conditions of capitalism, albeit implicitly and indirectly. Marx himself was an enthusiastic reader of Homer and Shakespeare. He also appreciated such writers as Charles Dickens and Honoré Balzac who, though they frequently betrayed their middle-class origins, nonetheless gave acute and insightful accounts of commercial society. Trained as a musicologist, Adorno praised the demanding but rigorous musical compositions of Gustav Mahler, Arnold Franz Walter Schoenberg, and Alban Berg, which expressed the alienated condition of modern existence more effectively than the self-consciously Critical Theory political art of the communist movement. In a different way, the beauty of classical art—for example, the music of Franz Joseph Haydn or Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart—intimates a sense of harmony and freedom that makes us more aware of the drabness and aesthetic poverty of contemporary life. But the critical potential of genuine art is threatened by the emergence in the 20th century of what Adorno and Horkheimer term the culture industry— the systematic application of the capitalist profit motive and industrial techniques to the products of intellectual culture. Mass-market books, recorded popular music, Hollywood films, and later television are all products designed specifically to appeal to a mass of consumers. Ignoring the aesthetic standards of the cultural tradition, works of entertainment and escapism make few demands on workers who are exhausted by their daily toil. Genuinely free time is gradually eliminated, as the culture industry organizes our leisure to ensure a contented, productive, and, above all, uncritical labor-force. Such effects are reinforced by industrial techniques providing fatalistic messages or easily assimilated images of rebellion in standardized and saleable formats. In these ways, critical theory provides a sophisticated analysis of the obstacles facing the socialist project—not just the power of the capitalist class but also philosophical assumptions and psychological, sociological, and cultural factors. But its very success in depicting these obstacles presents a problem for critical theory. Its ability to account for the longevity of capitalism tends, paradoxically, to reinforce political pessimism and withdrawn quietism rather than engaged action to transform society. The relentlessly negative, critical, and often abstruse nature of these theorists’ writings has also led to accusations of elitism. For those closer to orthodox Marxism, elitism and quietism are the result of the Frankfurt School’s distance from Marxist political economy, communist militancy, and the working class (Marcuse is a partial exception who, at least in more optimistic moods during the 1960s and 1970s, recognized the radical potential from a variety of sources beyond the working class). Second-Generation Theorists More recently, a second generation of theorists, including such figures as Albrecht Wellmer and 157 Axel Honneth, has sought to renew the Frankfurt School’s approach to critical theory. Most influential, however, is the work of Jürgen Habermas who, in contrast to the aphoristic style and exclusively critical emphasis of some earlier figures, provides a highly systematic and constructive account of critical theory. Although Habermas’s position has evolved, his early attempt to define a secure epistemological position for critical theory reflects his enduring concern, characteristic of pragmatism, with the grounding of human experience, knowledge, and values in distinct modes of action and interaction. Our attempts to control external reality are formalized and refined within empirical-analytical natural sciences such as chemistry, physics, or engineering. Although for Habermas this essentially instrumental relationship to the physical world is legitimate, positivism theorists make the mistake of extending this model to relationships between human subjects. Human interaction or communicative action demands a different approach, which is reflected in the emphasis of so-called hermeneutic disciplines such as history, literature, and art criticism on the interpretation of meanings rather than on causal explanation and prediction. However, despite Hans-Georg Gadamer’s claims for the universality of hermeneutic understanding, even this approach has only limited validity. An exclusively hermeneutic approach cannot grasp the ways in which social meanings and traditions are distorted by relations of power. A hermeneutic approach is unable, in other words, to detect ideological beliefs, attitudes, and values. A genuinely critical theory must combine causal analysis of the mechanisms of social power with hermeneutic understanding of their ideological effects. Prominent examples of critical theory are, once again, Freud’s psychoanalytic investigation of mental disorders and Marx’s critique of political economy. Critical theory is all the more important because, in common with earlier Frankfurt theorists, Habermas rejects Marxist historical materialism’s positivist tendency to posit deterministic laws of history. In particular, it was a mistake to assume that technological development of the forces of production would result in a revolutionary transformation of society’s relations of production. Habermas insists on the independent (if not completely autonomous) developmental logic of the superstructural level of 158 Critical Theory legal, moral, and social relations or, in other words, at the level of “interaction” or “communication.” The independence logic of communicative action accounts for the failure of historical materialism’s predictions of revolution and for the onesided modernization of Western societies. The rapid growth of our technological ability to control natural processes does not necessarily lead to greater rationalization of our social relationships— our moral, cultural, and political life. It may, in the absence of a corresponding communicative rationalization of society, only reinforce existing relations of domination. Any challenge to the one-sided rationality of modernity requires, according to Habermas, normative standards grounded in a theory of communicative action. In the modern world, absolute religious or metaphysical guarantees for moral values are no longer convincing. Scientific or instrumental rationality delivers technological advances but is morally empty. We must rely instead, Habermas maintains, on procedural norms of discussion or discourse. Moral values are ultimately grounded in the agreement or consensus of human subjects. But as Marx’s critique of ideology has shown, belief systems, cultural values, and traditions may be distorted by power. So it is essential that agreement is reached through processes of communication that are undistorted by the power of some participants. Participants in communicative action reach agreement subject only to legitimate forms of argument, or what Habermas refers to as the “peculiarly constraint-free force of the better argument.” Habermas’s characterization of an “ideal speech situation” undistorted by power relies on the claim that particular moral values are presupposed in all our acts of communication—a claim fleshed out in his theory of universal pragmatics. Not surprisingly, the universalism of this account has been subject to considerable skepticism. In addition, because Habermas’s discourse ethics emphasizes the importance of reaching a universal consensus, he has been accused by Jean-François Lyotard of an insensitivity to “difference” and “otherness.” In this context, Habermas insists that nothing can ever guarantee the validity of our existing beliefs. If that were possible, it would indeed tend to encourage dogmatism. For Habermas, as for Karl Popper, scientific theories are never more than provisional hypotheses, always vulnerable to unanticipated counterexamples. Our moral principles and values are similarly vulnerable to the unexpected realization that they were imposed by power. Habermas develops his account of the intersubjective basis of values and norms into a manyfaceted theory of discourse ethics, law, and democracy. Of more direct political relevance, however, is his diagnosis of the pathologies of advanced capitalism. Modern society, according to this account, is deformed by the incursions of the bureaucratic state and capitalist economy into the domain of moral and cultural meanings. What Habermas describes as the “invasion of the lifeworld” by the systems of power and money substitutes instrumentally rationalized social subsystems (i.e., the modern state and capitalism) for what should be the communicative reproduction of human social existence. But the disruption of inherited cultural traditions also presents an opportunity for progressive reform according to the norms of communicative rationality. For example, the inherited tradition of patriarchy—a constellation of social meanings and values distorted by the power of men—can now be recognized as an ideological formation. This is reflected in the emergence of new “potentials for protest” in the new social movements of feminism, sexual liberation, ecology, and environmentalism, which are potentially progressive responses “from the lifeworld” to the invasive power of capitalism and the state (Habermas, 1987, pp. 391 ff). Radical Skepticism and the Renewal of Critical Theory In the last decades of the 20th century, the Frankfurt School of critical theory was overshadowed by more skeptical theorists espousing postmodernism and poststructuralism—also sometimes, confusingly, described as critical theory. Crucially, however, these theorists’ radical critique of philosophical notions of objectivity, universality, and truth implies a corresponding denial of the objectivity of power and power relations, removing them from the scope of critical theory in the sense considered here. Michel Foucault, for example, conceives relations of power as omnipresent and inescapable. There is no “outside” of power. The omnipresence of power may correspond to an equivalent omnipresence of Critical Theory “resistance,” but resistance in Foucault’s sense does not imply liberation (whether partial or complete) from relations of power. The radically skeptical and seemingly apolitical currents of poststructuralism and postmodernism have, more recently, been challenged by theorists who, though they diverge in significant respects, are much closer in spirit to the Frankfurt School’s brand of critical theory. With a renewed appreciation of Marx and the importance of capitalism as well as a strong concern with fascism and other varieties of authoritarian populism, theorists such as Judith Butler, Ernesto Laclau, and Slavoj Žižek share, in addition, the Frankfurt School’s positive evaluation of Freudian psychoanalysis, albeit as interpreted by the French psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan. These theorists reject postmodernism’s unqualified commitment to pluralism, “difference,” the “Other,” and the fragmentary struggles of identity politics and multiculturalism. Maintaining an uneasy truce between postmodern difference and Marxist universality, Laclau and Butler see the striving for unity and universality—whether in theory and ideology or in political organization and practice—as an unavoidable but always unattainable goal (Butler, Laclau, and Žižek). Žižek is most explicit in wishing to translate this relentlessly paradoxical stance into something like a revival of Marxist political economy and Leninist politics. Whatever their ultimate merits, the sometimes fascinating but theoretically strenuous writings of Žižek, Laclau, and Butler cannot avoid one of the perennial questions of critical theory, namely how such difficult and frequently obscure texts are supposed to relate to widespread and effective political action for the transformation of society. The self-conscious difficulty of Adorno’s work similarly provides endless scope for intellectual debate, but little obvious or direct inspiration to political action. For critical theory, which is defined by its anticipated role in social transformation, this is surely no trivial problem. A related concern is that critical theory will only ever exert influence on an intellectual elite and that, contrary to their best intentions, critical theorists are, after all, just proponents of an ideology for intellectuals. A further problem must also be resolved. A critical theory needs to diagnose and propose remedies for the pathologies of contemporary society, but it must also motivate political actors to undertake 159 difficult and sometimes dangerous actions. But intellectual theory seems ill equipped to inspire the kind of widespread political mobilization required for a genuinely emancipatory transformation of society. It is not obvious, for example, how the calmly dispassionate rationality embodied in Habermas’s exhaustively systematic project might contribute to the motivation of political agents. Critical theory in this style seems to assume an unlikely degree of rationality in its readers. Marx’s vitriolic outbursts against capitalism and Adorno’s passionate commitment to suffering humanity are perhaps more likely to motivate action—even if Adorno’s relationship to concrete political practice otherwise seems remote, and revolutionary Marxism’s practical difficulties made critical theory necessary in the first place. Similarly unpromising are attempts to revise or update Marxism’s identification of the industrial proletariat as the designated grave digger of capitalism. Marcuse saw new agents of revolutionary change in the “outcasts and outsiders” of Western societies as well as in these societies’ colonial and neocolonial victims in the developing world. Some theories of new social movements in the 1970s and 1980s extended this approach to movements of women, lesbian and gays, and greens and environmentalists, which were seen as the new agents of global social transformation. But such approaches, with their tendency to posit a foreseeable course of social development and predictable cast of historical actors, sit uneasily with critical theory’s criticisms of positivist social science and deterministic laws of historical development. Critical theory’s best hope for further renewal may lie in the more concrete and discrete critical discourses that emerged in association with the liberation politics and social movements of the late 20th century. Like critical theory, discourses of ecology, feminism, anti-racism, postcolonial studies, and queer theory combine factual claims with normative ideals and political proposals. But all of these are less systematic and less totalizing than is critical theory in classic mode. They rely not on some overarching philosophy of history or what Lyotard calls a “grand meta-narrative,” but on looser assemblages of historical and empirical findings, moral ideals, and practical recommendations. In that sense, they are closer in spirit to Nietzsche, Adorno, and Foucault than to either 160 Cuban Missile Crisis Marx or Habermas. They do resemble Marxism, however, insofar as they have emerged in the context of already engaged social movements that, like the 19th-century working class, have gone on to achieve substantial social and political change. Like workers’ movements, too, these movements and discourses have inaugurated new and distinctive modes of political action. Anti-racist, gay, and feminist practices of consciousness raising and identity politics testify to a direct and fruitful intersection of “theory” and “practice.” Culture, symbolism, and imagery have proved to be equally effective—and often less counterproductive—than are the sometimes intimidatory and coercive (let alone violent) political tactics of socialist politics. The role of critical theory, in these terms, is more akin to that of a political toolbox than to an architectural master plan, providing specific conceptual tools for particular political purposes. Indeed, it would be a misunderstanding to expect any critical theory to be resolved, or to resolve itself into a stable and selfsufficient discursive domain. The origins of critical theory lie, precisely, in the recognition that the permanence and stability of theoretical knowledge is achieved only at the cost of perpetuating existing relations of power. David West See also Adorno, Theodor; Foucault, Michel; Habermas, Jürgen; Knowledge and Power; Lukes, Steven Further Readings Bottomore, T. (2002). The Frankfurt School and its critics (Rev. ed.). London: Routledge. Geuss, R. (1981). The idea of a critical theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. New York: Cambridge University Press. Habermas, J. (1987). The theory of communicative action: Vol. 2. The critique of functionalist reason (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Holub, R. C. (1991). Jürgen Habermas: Critic in the public sphere. London: Routledge. Honneth, A. (1991). The critique of power: Reflective stages in a critical social theory (K. Baynes, Trans.). Cambridge: MIT Press. West, D. (1987). Power and formation. Inquiry, 30(1), 137–154. CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS The events of October 1962 are commonly regarded as the most dangerous moment in human history when, had all-out nuclear war occurred, hundreds of millions of people would have been killed. Indeed, the environmental and climatic consequences could have led to the extinction of human life in the northern hemisphere. Yet the crisis is also commonly seen as a turning point in the cold war that helped bring detente between the superpowers, cooperation in arms control, and reduction in the risk of nuclear war. Over many decades, a vast amount of historical research has been undertaken into the crisis. Yet debate remains about the interpretation of events and the implications for understanding the role and power of nuclear weapons in international politics. The crisis began on October 16, 1962, after U.S. spy planes discovered the construction of Soviet nuclear missile bases in Cuba. The Soviet leader, Nikita Khrushchev, had promised U.S. President John F. Kennedy that the Soviets would not place offensive weapons on the island. After a week’s deliberation, on October 22, Kennedy announced the imposition of a partial naval blockade and threatened a “full retaliatory response” against the Soviet Union (USSR) if missiles were fired from Cuba. On the morning of October 24, U.S. warships stood ready to intercept Soviet ships. When these stopped or turned around, Secretary of State Dean Rusk quipped, “We’re eyeball to eyeball and I guess the other fella just blinked.” The crisis reached its climax on the weekend of October 26, when both leaders maneuvered to reach a diplomatic settlement. A framework was agreed in which the United States would not invade Cuba if the Soviets removed their missiles. Kennedy also provided a secret assurance that he would withdraw U.S. nuclear missiles from Turkey and Italy. By then, however, Khrushchev had already decided to take the missiles out of Cuba, and on the morning of October 28, Moscow Radio broadcast the news. Final agreement was not reached until November 20 as the Cuban leader, Fidel Castro, was not consulted by Khrushchev and objected that Cuban interests were ignored. The reasons why Khrushchev deployed missiles in Cuba and why he withdrew them have attracted Cuban Missile Crisis much debate over many decades. In 1962, the United States enjoyed massive nuclear superiority over the Soviet Union. Missiles in Cuba would have reduced but not fundamentally altered U.S. nuclear superiority. Putting missiles into Cuba was also intended to deter a U.S. attack, though instead it provoked the United States into preparations for an invasion. During the last few decades, various incidents and circumstances have become known that suggest the risk of nuclear war was greater than recognized. These include near-accidents and failures of U.S. command and control, the revelation that the Soviets had deployed tactical nuclear weapons in Cuba unbeknownst to Washington, evidence that U.S. fighters sent to support a U.S. aircraft straying into Soviet airspace were armed with nuclear ordnance, and details of encounters between nuclear-armed Soviet submarines and the 161 U.S. Navy. As the crisis reached its climax, political leaders were increasingly determined to avoid conflict. Yet the risk of inadvertent nuclear war may well have been very real. Len Scott See also Chicken Games; Mutually Assured Destruction; War Further Readings Fursenko, A., & Naftali, T. (1997). “One hell of a gamble”: Khrushchev, Castro, Kennedy and the Cuban missile crisis 1958–1964. London: John Murray. May, E., & Zelikow, P. (Eds.). (1997). The Kennedy tapes: Inside the White House during the Cuban missile crisis. Cambridge, MA: Belknap. D between agents, whether these agents are individuals, groups, governments, or nation-states. Dahl suggests any complete understanding of A’s power over B must include references to the base from which A’s power emanates, the means by which A exerts this power, and the scope and amount of A’s power. A power base is an inert cache of resources held by A that may include, for example, a country’s ability to wage war or a politician’s capacity to bestow patronage, veto legislation, or gain media attention. Means mediate between A’s power base and B’s response and include threats and promises by A to marshal base resources for or against B. Scope pertains to whether A’s power extends to all, many, or a few spheres of influence within the domain in which A operates. Finally, Dahl calculates A’s amount of power as the difference between the probability of an event occurring given a certain action by A, and the probability of the given event given no such action by A. Thus, A has power over B to the extent that A can engage a particular tactic to increase the probability that B will do what A wants. This reference to the amount of power and probability is most critical to understanding Dahl’s take on power relations. Dahl consistently backs his theories with empirical research. Following his definitional discussions of power, Dahl moved to empirical power assessments. This empirical work began as a critique of the work of community power theorists such as Floyd Hunter, whose reputational studies of local notables concludes power is unequally distributed in Atlanta, and C. Wright Mills, whose 1956 book The Power Elite posits all decisions of national DAHL, ROBERT A. (1915– ) After almost 70 years of publishing, Robert Dahl is one of the most venerable and influential modern political scholars. Born in 1915, Dahl is the Sterling Professor Emeritus of Political Science at Yale University and former president of the American Political Science Association. Dahl published his first article in 1940, and is widely credited with initiating the modern theoretical debate about power and undertaking one of the most thorough early empirical investigations of the topic with his 1961 book Who Governs? Integrally connected to his notion of power, Dahl’s theoretical and empirical work on democracy is also widely cited, including his 1989 book Democracy and Its Critics and On Political Equality, published in 2006. Dahl’s first major contribution to discussions of power appears in his 1957 Behavioral Science article “The Concept of Power,” in which he builds and operationalizes a definition of power that forms the basis of his later empirical studies. Though criticized, Dahl’s concept of power is still frequently cited as a relevant starting point from which to understand power. For example, in a 2008 review of Dahl’s 1957 work, Philip Pettit states Dahl’s work is still an effective and valuable tool by which to understand other concepts such as freedom, albeit with some minor adjustments. In “The Concept of Power,” Dahl famously states, “A has power over B to the extent that he can get B to do something that B would not otherwise do.” Thus, Dahl understands power as relation 163 164 Decentering (of Subject, of Structure) consequence in the United States are controlled by a small group of 400 people sharing a common culture. Built on his earlier developed concept of power, Dahl’s 1958 article “A Critique of the Ruling Elite Model” highlights what he sees as methodological flaws in Mills’s and Hunter’s studies and elaborates on these flaws to discredit their conclusions. Following his criticism of elite theorists, Dahl then produced arguably the most comprehensive empirical community power study ever undertaken. In Who Governs? Dahl tests whether New Haven, Connecticut, is run by a single elite group. To do so, he longitudinally examines the role of various local actors in areas where important public decisions are made, including nominations in two local political parties, urban redevelopment, and public education. Although he finds an unequal distribution of resources in the city, his data suggest no single elite group dominates local policy making, with only the democratically elected mayor having influence in all three issue areas. Thus, Dahl argues that power in New Haven is pluralistic in that it is dispersed among a number of different and competing groups rather than exclusively commanded by one elite group. With Who Governs?, Dahl became the de facto champion of pluralism, a position that has brought considerable criticism from authors such as Peter Bacharach and Morton Baratz, Steven Lukes, and G. William Domhoff. Despite criticisms from these elite and Marxist theorists, Dahl steadfastly defends his claim that the United States is a pluralist state and that power is dispersed rather than concentrated in the hands of a few elite members of society. This is not to say that Dahl is not critical of pluralism. In his later works, such as “Pluralism Revisited,” Dahl acknowledges that inequality of resources and political knowledge and strong differences in personal motivations sometimes enable some groups to more frequently dominate group decision making—a concession that underlines the work of modern neopluralist writers. For Dahl, however, these inequalities still do not refute pluralism: although pluralist states might demonstrate inequality, unequal states are not necessarily elitist. Kennedy Stewart See also Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton; Elite Theories; Lukes, Steven; Pluralism Further Readings Dahl, R. A. (1957). The concept of power. Behavioral Science, 2(3), 201–215. Dahl, R. A. (1958). A critique of the ruling elite model. The American Political Science Review, 52(2), 463–469. Dahl, R. A. (1961). Who governs?: Democracy and power in an American city. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Dahl, R. A. (1978). Pluralism revisited. Comparative Politics, 10(2), 191–203. Lukes, S. (1974). Power: A radical view. London: Macmillan. Pettit, P. (2008). Dahl’s power and republican freedom. Journal of Power, 1(1), 67–74. DECENTERING (OF SUBJECT, OF STRUCTURE) Postmodernist or poststructuralist writers in general argue that political theory and other discourses have reified people as particular types of monads: rational, instrumental, self-centered, and autonomous agents. In the Enlightenment discourse, these rational instrumental beings choose their actions given the environments in which they find themselves. These rational beings are the agents fashioning the world around them and reacting to that environment in terms of their objects and desires. The agents are the subjects of history and explanation revolves around them. Decentering the subject is a process of recognition that what separates the physical form of a person and that person as a subject of inquiry is the linguistic cover that constitutes discourse. Different discourses about people constitute them as different subjects. People define their own beings within these different discourses, as mothers, as consumers, as workers, as political activists. There is no reason to suppose that these different discourses are complementary; they may contain many contradictions belying the person as a rational coherent agent. Rather, agents are fashioned by the dominant discourses in different domains. Predicating power to individual agents is an example of the centering of people as subjects: we need to decenter the subject to see the way in which discourses dominate human lives. Defensive Realism Decentering does not have to be applied to subjects, however. Rationalist approaches recognize that there is an interrelationship between agents as subjects and the structures around them. Structuralists make the opposite error of centering attention on structure and reifying that to give it rationality and coherence. In the same way that we must understand agents as subjects of discourse, so we must understand structures. The way in which we see environments, social processes, and interactions as constraints on the actions of rational beings can also be subject to decentering. Seeing social structure in terms of class relationships, networks of families or work colleagues, or institutions as conventions and norms are all also specific discourses, and we can decenter structures to recognize that these processes are themselves contradictory and self-defeating. In that sense, we should not see power in a structural manner, but rather as a process of discourse that leads us and the world into ways of behaving that have no center or focal point of rationality. Keith Dowding See also Discourse; Foucault, Michel Further Readings Nicholson, L. (1995). Social postmodernism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DEFENSIVE REALISM Defensive realism follows the basic neorealist assumptions that the anarchic nature of the international system compels states to seek self-help for survival. The impulse to survive is thus the primary factor that conditions state behavior. This line of thought is consistent with Kenneth Waltz’s theory of international politics, which posits the dominance of the “third image” (international system) in explaining the behavior between and among states. Anarchy and survival are thus the animating factors that privilege security over power. Unlike classical realism in which international politics is a struggle for power, in neorealism, power is just a means to an end, and thus the 165 ultimate objective is to maximize security to enhance survival. To highlight the central features of defensive realism, it is important to distinguish the differences between the more traditional (defensive) orientation and offensive realism. Although both variants maintain the central objective of states seeking security for survival, the debate between relative gain and relative loss and the appropriate strategies reveals fundamental differences in how states pursue their goals in conditions of anarchy. Defensive realism is driven by human behavioral assumptions that preventing loss takes precedence over pursuing gains and the risks associated with it. By constantly guarding their positions in the international system, states could pursue a cost-effective security strategy. Hence, it is a status quo–oriented theory predicated on maintaining an international equilibrium conducive for states to pursue minimal security strategies for maximum survival. Why would states want to challenge their positions in the international system when doing so would trigger a counterbalancing coalition, thus compelling the challengers to expend more on security while intensifying the security dilemma that may in effect reduce survival? Thus, pursuing a minimal security strategy precludes any ambition of improving its international standing until the basics are ensured— mainly staying alive in an anarchic world. There are rare opportunities for expansion because the hope of improving security through such provocative strategies may actually result in the opposite—endangering a state’s survivability. Although defensive realists envision a world in which security is abundant, offensive realists posit that security, like any other resource, is subject to competition. The competitive nature of international politics tends to intensify the security dilemma, thereby precluding the possibility for cooperation and drastically reducing the ability for states to maintain their positions. Offensive realism is thus a theory predicated on international political change in which the central goal is to maximize offensive capabilities to pursue relative gains. Survival is never certain until a state achieves regional hegemonic status, and therefore it is necessary to contain the aspirations of peer competitors, possibly resorting to preemptive war, to prevent the hegemon from being dethroned. 166 Deflected Wants Defensive realism promotes a more optimistic outlook on international relations. If all states maintain their positions and achieve a consensual cost-effective security strategy, then cooperation is possible. However, anarchy also exacerbates the ever-present security dilemma, increasing the likelihood of conflicts and misperceptions, questioning the prudence of international cooperation, and strengthening the concept of self-reliance in seeking security. The criticism of defensive realism is that the bias toward the status-quo deviates from international reality. If states are so well behaved and maintain their respective positions, why do states feel threatened, and why is it so difficult to mitigate the security dilemma? The sense of insecurity and the everpresent danger of military conflicts compel states to seek international political change to enhance survival. The rise and fall of great powers continues to capture the essence of international politics. The intra-neorealist debate therefore underscores the variety of strategies states pursues to maximize survival in an anarchic international system. Johnson Y. K. Louie See also Hegemony; Neorealism; Realism in International Relations; Security Dilemma; Waltz, Kenneth Further Readings Taliaferro, J. W. (2000/2001). Security seeking under anarchy: Defensive realism revisited. International Security, 25(3), 128–161. Waltz, K. N. (1979). Theory of international politics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. DEFLECTED WANTS Deflected wants may be described as the things such as fame, success, happiness, or power that a person wants for him- or herself, but the path toward achieving them has changed course. History is full of examples. Quite possibly the most famous illustration during the 20th century was Adolf Hitler. He was, without doubt, a troubled individual, but his desire to be an artist, starting as a young boy in Austria, stayed with him until the moment he committed suicide in his underground bunker in Berlin, as the victorious Russian troops approached. He himself said that anyone who wanted to understand him should realize that he was an artist, first and foremost, and that being chancellor of Germany took him away from his true desire—painting. Hitler’s wants and desires to be an artist were deflected onto politics and in his crazed manner of thinking, his actions as “Der Führer,” were indicative of his artistic nature, such as the plans for the building of Germania and his mania to rid Germany of all modern art (Cubism, Dadaism, etc.). A contemporary of Hitler, and his arch nemesis, was Winston Churchill. As a child, he strove greatly to win his father’s love, but in vain as the elder Churchill (Randolph, the chancellor of the Exchequer at the time) openly disliked his son and found him a great disappointment. Winston wrote numerous letters, begging his father to visit, but Randolph usually ignored the requests. Churchill was incredibly lonely, a feeling that stayed with him the rest of his life; likewise, the heartfelt wish to earn his father’s love never left. His desire for a loving relationship with his father was deflected onto politics, where he cultivated the image of ultramasculinity (smoking up to nine cigars throughout the day, his frequent imbibing of Johnny Walker Red whisky, etc.) in the hope that he was the type of man his father would admire. During his first few years as a politician, and again during the 1920s, Churchill used the phrase first coined by his father, “Tory Democracy,” as a means of describing his political beliefs. Significantly, many of his colleagues saw young Winston as being obsessed with his father and were amazed at his drive to further his father’s legacy. Another example concerns quite possibly the greatest artist, as well as one of the preeminent thinkers, produced by Western civilization—Leonardo da Vinci. According to Sigmund Freud, Leonardo’s wants and desires for homosexual contact were deflected first to his art, and second to his intellectual investigations. The key to understanding Leonardo (and other homosexuals), Freud wrote, was the relationship Leonardo had with his mother. Because of his mother’s doting and his father’s neglect, Leonardo experienced a powerful Oedipal conflict and saw women as dominant, Deliberation “causing” him to become homosexual. In essence, Leonardo’s strong desire for men was deflected and turned toward art and science. It has been argued that the personal power and determination of such individuals in their new fields develops from the strength of the their deflected wants. Cary Stacy Smith and Li-Ching Hung See also False Consciousness; Interests; Symbolic Power and Violence Further Readings Fest, J. (1974). Hitler. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Freud, S. (1989). Leonardo da Vinci and a memory of his childhood. New York: W. W. Norton. Manchester, W. (1983). The last lion: Winston Spencer Churchill—Vision of glory 1874–1932. Boston: Little, Brown. DELIBERATION Deliberation refers to a process of reflection undertaken by individuals or groups to reach reasoned and considered decisions. Deliberation has an epistemic function to improve decisions and uncover the best argument. It is often assumed that because of deliberation, individuals’ beliefs and judgments are transformed as they consider new facts, arguments, and points of view. In individual deliberation, the deliberator weighs and evaluates each possible solution and then arrives at a decision. Group deliberation consists of reasoned discussion. When groups deliberate, the process acquires a dimension of power. Deliberation can be either formal or informal. Examples of formalized deliberating groups are juries or legislatures. An example of informal deliberation is the ongoing discussion between different groups in civil society, but discussions within families and civic organizations are also examples of informal deliberation. Group deliberation is characterized by communication aimed at persuasion. Ideal deliberative processes should be reasoned, equal, and open 167 discussions where participants are prepared to change their views as a result of the arguments presented. In reality, deliberation does not live up to such a high standard. Some members of the group will be more powerful than others, and some arguments will be more persuasive than others, regardless of their merits. Although deliberation could ideally be aimed at reaching a common good for the group, in practice, the private interests of group members will be powerful forces. Inequality within the group leads to differences in the power each group member possesses. The socioeconomic background of participants can define their roles in the discussion. As an example, jury deliberations tend to be dominated by welleducated white males. Actors who are powerful outside of deliberation will be powerful in deliberative settings as well. In deliberations between states, the most powerful nation will wield more power. Inequalities also exist with regard to the ability of deliberators. Good orators are more likely to convince others, regardless of the merit of their arguments. There is a danger that intelligent and persuasive individuals could manipulate deliberation to serve their own interests. Other resources, such as time, information, or the respect of other members of the community, will also make some deliberators more influential than others. Arguments themselves will have different power. Although some place hope in the power of the best argument to defeat all others, this is not necessarily the argument that will resonate most with deliberators. Arguments that appeal to strong background beliefs and feelings will be more powerful. Arguments that support the views deliberators already hold will also be more persuasive. Deliberation is seen as a good way of increasing citizen involvement and participation in politics. In political theory, deliberative democracy has engendered a new interest in increasing deliberation in politics, as current democratic systems focus more on elections than on decision making through reasoned debate. Deliberative experiments and meetings are organized to increase citizen involvement in public policy making. Zsuzsanna Chappell See also Argument, Power of; Deliberative Democracy; Persuasion 168 Deliberative Democracy Further Readings Dryzek, J. S. (2000). Deliberative democracy and beyond: Liberals, critics, contestations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY During the last 20 years, democratic theory has taken a deliberative turn. An increasing number of political philosophers are arguing for deliberative democracy, a political process where decisions are reached through reasoned debate. This is usually contrasted with aggregative democracy, where decisions are reached through voting. Definitions of deliberative democracy vary considerably across the literature, but they do share some common characteristics. One of the aims of the deliberative project is to empower both individuals and arguments by providing a forum that facilitates equal respect. According to different authors, deliberative democracy can promote equal respect, empower underprivileged groups, and give power to the best argument. Some authors consider the problems that power inequalities pose for deliberation. Deliberation is also meant to yield other benefits, such as increased legitimacy or epistemically better outcomes. Democracy as Dialogue Deliberative democracy is based on open and uncoerced dialogue characterized by reason giving. Joshua Cohen defines its characteristics as free, reasoned, equal, and aiming for a consensus. Deliberators present arguments that justify their judgments and preferences. Others are expected to listen to these arguments and adjust their beliefs, judgments, and preferences as a result. This reciprocity of justifying arguments and listening to the arguments of others is a key feature of deliberative democracy. Deliberation is democratic if it is equal in that each individual has equal opportunity to speak and each point of view and argument has an equal opportunity to be put forward. Deliberative democracy is a theory of democracy that gives power to arguments through the introduction of a number of different viewpoints and beliefs. Thus, it is not brute numbers, but well-argued cases that lead to the selection of policies. If participants scrutinize the reasons for judgments and preferences, then it is more likely that genuinely good policies will be adopted. Proponents of deliberative democracy believe that because of the transformative power of deliberation, deliberators will be convinced by good arguments and eventually the majority of citizens will come to believe in them. Deliberation also empowers all citizens to advance their arguments as equals in the political forum. In the ideal form of deliberation, each deliberator has equal opportunity and power to advance his or her argument and influence the beliefs, judgments, and preferences of others. Deliberative democracy is assumed to give more weight to other-regarding than to selfish arguments. The reason for this is that deliberators will have to convince others to adopt their position and this is more difficult to achieve if arguments are put in terms of what would benefit them, rather than what would benefit everyone. In the long run, this is assumed to lead to a genuine orientation toward the common good. To exclude discriminatory or otherwise offensive arguments from deliberation, it is required that deliberators launder their preferences. This means that deliberators use generally other-regarding arguments and that they would cease using arguments that discriminate against others. In practice, who would block such arguments and how this would be achieved is problematic. Thus, it is possible that arguments that discriminate against some group in society would become dominant through deliberation. Alternatively, some reasonable arguments may be laundered out through such a process. Deliberative democracy and aggregative democracy can be located on a continuum. Purely aggregative democracy would consist solely of citizens voting in isolation, whereas purely deliberative democracy would arrive at decisions purely through deliberation. Current liberal representative democracies fall somewhere between these two extremes. Actually, all empirically feasible democratic systems would be located somewhere among these extremes. Habermas’s Model One of the earliest and most important philosophers to endorse deliberative democracy was Deliberative Democracy Jürgen Habermas. His discourse ethics had a great impact on the literature, and many authors refer to his ideas of deliberation and communicative rationality to support their own arguments. Thus, the deliberative model has some of its roots in critical theory’s challenge to existing power structures. Habermas sets out his model of deliberative democracy most clearly in Between Facts and Norms. For him, ideal deliberation takes place in an ideal speech situation and is governed by communicative rationality. This consists of communicative action that is aimed at developing understanding between individuals. According to his model, informal deliberation takes place in the public sphere, which is followed by an election and leads to further deliberation between legislators. This leads to the implementation of laws that give deliberative decisions legal power. Habermas’s theory of deliberation is highly normative and addresses the way in which deliberation could increase legitimacy and communicative rationality in political decision-making. Contemporary Democratic Theorists The current literature on deliberative democracy encompasses a wide range of authors, some of whom emphasize the role of deliberative democracy to empower minorities and challenge existing power structures. Some democratic theorists who advocate deliberate democracy, often called difference democrats, argue that the deliberative processes described by much of the literature are too exclusive and that they tend to favor dispassionate, logical argumentation as it is practiced by educated white men. This leads to power inequalities between different deliberators, where women and minorities are not fully included. These ideas are strongly influenced by feminist theory and critical theory. This argument is set out most clearly in Iris Marion Young’s Democracy and Inclusion. According to her, deliberative theories are based on logical reasoning that leaves little space for emotions and is not sympathetic toward the norms of other cultures. For participants to become truly equal in deliberation, the arguments of women, minorities, and those with relatively little education should be given a voice as well. This could be achieved through including emotional talk, narratives, rhetoric, and other nonargumentative utterances, such as greetings in deliberative discourse. Young argues 169 that deliberation cannot always be calm and dispassionate, but should also be a forum where political protest can be expressed. Thus, deliberation should increase the legitimacy of democratic decisions and lead to better choices through requiring reasoned arguments and justifications for judgments, and it should serve as a tool to empower minorities through giving them more voice and influence in the policy-making process. Deliberation could allow the perspectives and narratives of hitherto less privileged groups to enter the political forum and, as a result, would make democracy more inclusive and equal. These theories also had considerable effect on the way in which the success of local level deliberative reforms is evaluated. Deliberative democracy is often portrayed as a normative or ideal theory of democracy. It describes an ideal decision-making procedure. But recent research is moving deliberative democracy out of the realm of the purely theoretical. There are an increasing number of empirical studies and quasiexperiments. Real-world deliberation will need to sacrifice some of the characteristics, benefits, and advantages of ideal deliberation, but is still seen as a goal worth aspiring to. The most obvious deliberative forums in current liberal democracies are legislatures. As the form of debate practiced here often falls short of the ideals of deliberative democracy, the primary focus of the literature is on new deliberative institutions. Practice and Problems There are two broad ways of imagining deliberative democracy in practice. The first is face-to-face deliberation between a defined set of participants, based roughly on the model of a town hall meeting. The second is deliberation diffused among a wider public sphere, as it is portrayed by Habermas. This is the ongoing informal deliberation that takes place between citizens, in the media, and in civil society. Face-to-face deliberation that follows the town hall format is more formalized, and the number of people taking part and the issues to be debated are well defined. Many deliberative projects emphasize that the deliberative group should be representative of the wider population. There are a number of ideas for larger-scale deliberative reform in the literature. One of the 170 Deliberative Democracy most well-known and ambitious is the concept of deliberation day, developed by Bruce Ackermann and James Fishkin. Deliberation day would be held a few weeks before presidential elections and would require U.S. citizens to come together to deliberate on candidates and issues. This would allow them to make more informed decisions on the day of the election, as well as encouraging day-to-day informal deliberation. This model is significant because large-scale deliberative quasiexperiments called deliberative polls have been based on it all around the world, from the United States to China. These experiments provide a rich source of data for empirical analysis. During these deliberative polls, participants often change their preferences in the way in which the model predicts. Other practical models of deliberation include citizen juries, which are groups of citizens getting together over time to reach a judgment on an issue, or deliberative juries, which serve the same role for policies that traditional juries do for legal cases. Participatory budgeting is one of the major reallife examples of deliberation in practice. It was first adopted in Porto Alegre, Brazil, and other cities have followed suit in that country. Traditional town hall meetings and online deliberation are also discussed in the literature. These mechanisms could also encourage informal deliberation within the public sphere in the form of increased participation by citizens in reasoned political discussions. Many of these deliberative policy-making mechanisms can empower underprivileged groups that would normally have only limited access to the policy-making process. In Porto Alegre, residents from poorer districts gained a voice in municipal matters through a system of participatory budgeting. In Chicago, local schools and police departments involved residents in deciding priorities and policies. These policies were intended to improve education and policing, especially in poorer areas. But even in well-off localities, this form of deliberative participation transfers power from local or central government to citizens. Research on real-life deliberative meetings reports mixed results. There are cases of success where deliberators appear to change their mind as a result of the arguments put forward during debate. There is, however, relatively little research about the effect of power and inequality on the results of deliberation. Deliberative democracy can suffer from a number of problems or pathologies. It is unlikely that deliberators will be genuinely equal. It is more likely that the deliberative group will be made up of individuals of differing abilities and backgrounds. Those who are more powerful outside of the deliberative process are likely to be more powerful in deliberation as well. Individuals also have differing natural abilities to express themselves and convince others. This gives those with better abilities to reason coherently and convincingly more power. Thus, it is not guaranteed that deliberative democracy will give power to the best argument because the best argument may not be the most persuasive argument. It is also argued that deliberation could favor vivid theories that are easy to understand and where the role of individuals is easily identifiable, rather than more complex theories using invisible hand explanations. Cass Sunstein identifies two mechanisms that lead to problems in deliberation. First, deliberative groups can become polarized. Within-group polarization means that if similar arguments are advanced most of the time, those arguments reinforce each other and the position of the group as a whole becomes more extreme. Second, informational cascades can develop that lead large groups of people to assume something is true simply because everyone else seems to think it is true. Although these mechanisms will not always be necessarily present during deliberation, they could lead to the adoption of suboptimal policies. Conclusion Deliberation is a time- and resource-consuming activity that not everyone will find enjoyable, so we cannot assume that all will participate on equal terms. Those with less time and opportunities to participate will be at a disadvantage. Even if deliberation becomes a dominant mode of decision making in politics, many are unlikely to participate because of a lack of motivation, just as many citizens are not motivated to turn out to vote. The problem is likely to be larger than in the case of voting, because genuine deliberation is very resource-intensive, regarding both acquiring information and the actual process of deliberation. This will lead to a bias regarding who participates in Democracy deliberation. Those who do not participate in politics will have less power than those who do. This bias might also reduce the legitimacy of any decisions reached through deliberation. Deliberative democracy gives individuals the power to voice their arguments and can possibly empower underprivileged groups. Some also argue that it gives power to the best argument by requiring clear justifications for beliefs and reasoned arguments. However, it will be difficult to keep existing power relationships out of deliberation, which can make the process less equal. This could potentially undermine the legitimacy of decisions made through deliberative procedures. Despite these potential problems, deliberative democracy continues to be one of the most influential theories of democracy because it offers an attractive theory of democratic decision making. Zsuzsanna Chappell See also Argument, Power of; Critical Theory; Deliberation; Democracy Further Readings Ackermann, B. A., & Fishkin, J. S. (2004). Deliberation day. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Cohen, J. (1997). Deliberation and democratic legitimacy. In J. Bohman & W. Rehg (Eds.), Deliberative politics: Essays on reason and politics. Cambridge: MIT Press. Dryzek, J. S. (2000). Deliberative democracy and beyond: Liberals, critics, contestations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Why societies need dissent. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. DEMOCRACY Democracy refers to (a) a political system, (b) a political aspiration, and (c) a key term of political rhetoric. As a name for a political system, it refers to the fact that power to rule is invested in the people themselves in some tangible or formal sense (in the modern period, indirectly, through elected representatives). As an aspiration, democracy stands for the desire to deepen and extend the ideals of political equality and popular control, including in systems that are already regarded 171 as democracies. These two approaches are often in tension. Contemporary representative democracy, for example, is sometimes criticized as remote and bureaucratic, granting power only minimally and episodically to ordinary citizens. This criticism has given rise to aspirations for forms of more direct citizen empowerment, or more participatory institutions. Democracy is also a term of political rhetoric. It is a word that signifies, at the most general level, a good, if not the best and most desirable, constitution and allocation of political power. Leaders, writers, and people of varied political persuasions will want to be classed as “democrats” by their audiences. The standard definition of democracy is “rule by the people,” from the ancient Greek (demos kratia). Today, a people normally means citizens of a nation-state or country. But in an age of globalization and the revival of local and secessionist movements, it has become evident that there is no obvious democratic way to decide who constitutes “a people.” In what sense can the people rule? In an influential account, Jack Lively set out a sliding scale of possibilities. Rule by the people could mean that all should be involved in deciding and administering policy, or that all should be involved in crucial decisions. Perhaps democratic rule can involve only a select minority, normally elected representatives, in ruling? Is it enough if these representatives are chosen by, or accountable to, the people as a whole? If rulers are chosen by the representatives of the ruled, is that too distant from any substantial sense of the people ruling to be classed properly as democratic? There is wide scope for specifying democracy’s meaning and requirements, and therefore too wide a scope for scholarly and political debate about the proper character and demands of democracy. Some observers regard democracy as having universal value, but just why it has value is a matter of some contestation. Is it because democracy produces beneficial outcomes in stability and relative social peace? Is it because democracy embodies intrinsic values, such as equality? Or is it because democratic participation produces more educated and confident citizens? It seems reasonably clear that adequate answers will involve a range of these and other concerns, and further, that the ways in which democracy is defined and justified bear a close link to each other. 172 Dependency Theory in International Relations Debates about democracy’s meaning and value are often conducted as timeless philosophical debates, but such debates draw on a long history of institutional and theoretical innovation. Ancient Greek democracy, most notably in Athens from around 500 BCE, was practiced in city-states rather than in nations or empires. This democracy featured direct citizen participation in a face-toface assembly making decisions for the community, rather than representation (though there were representative elements). However, women, slaves, and resident foreigners were not “citizens” and so were excluded from the public political life of the city. Only a minority of male citizens actually took part in the direct democratic assemblies and were eligible to be chosen (by lot, or random selection) for public offices. Aspects of democratic practice were evident in ancient Rome and in Renaissance Italian citystates. Several ideas, such as the separation of powers between executive, legislature, and judiciary, which are evident in many of today’s democratic systems, grew out of the experiences of both. But national and representative democracy as we know it today awaited what Robert A. Dahl calls democracy’s “second transformation” in Europe around the mid-18th century. This second transformation involved a shift in the basic scale of political organization from the city to the nation. The increase in political scale created political communities that were much more heavily populated, territorially large, and diverse than were ancient or renaissance city-states. Most observers at the time, and subsequently, understood that in these circumstances direct participation was no longer feasible and that it needed to be replaced by representation. Although historically democracy preceded liberalism, liberalism has preceded democracy for all intents and purposes in the modern era. The idea of the universal franchise, for example, emerged fitfully throughout the 19th and 20th centuries, in the West at least, on the back of developing liberal ideas about individual responsibility, autonomy, and freedom. Liberal ideas about protecting individual rights and limiting the scope of government are not intrinsically democratic ideas, and what we now call representative democracy emerged from liberal ideas as much, if not more than, from specifically democratic ones. The idea and the practice of representation arguably kept the apparatus of government at some distance from the power of the people themselves, thus creating an institutional space in which more timeless and universal rights could be protected against populist and democratic vagaries. Liberal values, not least the inviolability of legitimate property rights, strongly limits the scope for legitimate government intervention in society. In the early 21st century, more than half of the countries in the world can reasonably be classed as democratic, in the sense of minimal electoral democracy at least. This historically unprecedented spread of popular government came about because of the rapid (though often difficult and halting) spread of democracy across Eastern Europe, Latin America, and Africa toward the end of the 20th century and the beginning of the 21st century. The practice of democracy varies according to region, culture, and degree of economic development. In sum, democracy is a rich set of practices that embody the idea that political power should be held, and used, in a way that derives from the ongoing consent of the governed, and with formal accountability of the governors to the governed. Michael Saward See also Dahl, Robert A.; Deliberative Democracy; Elections; Voting Further Readings Dahl, R. A. (1998). On democracy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Saward, M. (2003). Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Policy Press. DEPENDENCY THEORY IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Dependency theory is a school of thought that explains underdevelopment as the result of the processes by which poor countries and regions are incorporated into the capitalist world economy. Emerging in Latin American writing during the 1960s as a response to concerns about inequalities in economic power both between and within Dependency Theory in International Relations nations, dependency theory claims that features of the global capitalist economy produce a metropolitanperiphery system of unequal relations between developed and underdeveloped states. Theorists also claim that such inequalities condition the social formations and political processes internal to underdeveloped states. According to this account, the economic preponderance of metropolitan capitalist states creates structural asymmetries in power over peripheral societies, limits the sovereignty of dependent states, and conditions their social structures in line with global capitalist imperatives. Starting from the Marxian premise that capitalism is an expanding global system in which national economies constitute subsystems, dependency writers emphasize the importance of the process by which the developing world was brought into this system by European capitalist powers. In this process, colonial relations based on economic extraction and penetration by foreign capital established a set of metropole–periphery relations. These relations are seen as creating a pattern of dependency in the international system, in which metropolitan predominance in processes of technology, capital, and commerce ensures that development of peripheral states is conditioned by, and occurs as a reflection of, the development and expansion of capitalist metropoles. Both development and underdevelopment are therefore seen as processes simultaneously constituted by global capitalism. This dependence is seen not merely as an external economic condition, but as a political phenomenon encompassing the entire institutional framework embodied in the economic, social, political, and cultural formations of the periphery. The international economic relations produced by global capitalism provide the structural cause for power asymmetries in the dependency approach. Impelled by the expansion of European capitalism from the 17th century, penetration by metropolitan capitals in the colonial period saw the economies of peripheral societies reoriented toward the needs of the metropole, through the production of primary commodities in exchange for Western manufactures. This is argued to lead to unequal exchange in trade between low-value resources and high-value manufactured exports, resulting in a cross-border appropriation of value by the metropole. “Dual economies” form in the 173 periphery as a result, where expanding export sectors tied to the needs of the metropole exist alongside stagnant traditional industries serving local markets. Control of these industries by metropolitan capitals siphons off what economic surplus is produced in the foreign-dominated export sectors, which Andre Gunder Frank labels the development of underdevelopment by global capitalist relations of dependency. However, the specific forms of economic dependence are said to vary according to the period in which parts of the periphery were incorporated into the global capitalist system. Fernando Cardoso stresses the contrast between a colonial form of economic dependence based on the exchange of raw materials for manufactures under European imperialism that produces “underdevelopment,” and a neocolonial system based on the exchange of labor-intensive manufactures for technological and capital goods in the postcolonial period, characterized as “dependent development.” However, the economic basis of dependency relations extends to constitute an internal conditioning factor for the entirety of the dependent society. Dominant groups in dependent societies clustering around economic interchanges with metropoles form transnational class alliances with international capitalists. This produces a class structure based on “comprador” capitalist domination of the state over local interests. Social formations also become fragmented between groups associated with the respective dual economies, and the political, legal, and cultural institutions of dependent societies become strongly influenced by those of the core through its influence over peripheral elites. A political structure of foreign rule results, reinforced at the interstate level through formal colonial relations during European imperialism and informally in the postcolonial period through relations based on the dominance of an internationally connected clientele bourgeoisie whose interests correspond to those of the capitalist class in dominant nations. Today, this political asymmetry manifests at the level of the international system as neocolonialism, where peripheral states have formal sovereignty but remain structurally unequal and subject to control by capitalist cores. Thus, dependency theorists argue that underdevelopment in the periphery can only be overcome by a qualitative change in both external 174 Determinacy (economic) and internal (political) systems, leading to national development autonomous from the conditioning international capitalist structure. In stressing an explanatory connection between international capitalism and domestic social formations, dependency theorists critique state-centric analyses of international relations. The penetration of international class structures into peripheral societies and the ensuing fragmentation of social formations along class lines challenges the notion that the state can be considered as either a unitary actor, or the core unit of analysis in international relations. Instead, the state is considered as an institution that articulates international class processes into domestic political settlements, with its form constituted externally by global capitalist imperatives. Furthermore, the presence of dependency relations questions concepts of state sovereignty and interdependence by drawing attention to structural asymmetries in power between states, owing to the economic and political domination of the periphery by metropoles. This implies differentiated economic functions for states in the international system, and redefines the concept of dependence from its traditional usage in international relations as reliance, to instead entail the determination of the social structures and development paths of peripheral states by imperatives emanating from the capitalist core. This position was later adopted and extended in Immanuel Wallerstein’s world systems approach, in which the expansion of capitalism was argued to partition the world into core, semi-periphery and periphery, impelling differential development processes within, and unequal power relations between, each region. Jeffrey D. Wilson See also Imperialism; Marxist Accounts of Power; Structural Power Further Readings Amin, S. (1976). Unequal development: An essay on the social formations of peripheral capitalism. Hassocks, Sussex, UK: Harvester Press. Cardoso, F. H. (1972). Dependency and development in Latin America. New Left Review, 74, 83–95. Frank, A. G. (1967). Capitalism and underdevelopment in Latin America. New York: Monthly Review Press. DETERMINACY Determinacy belongs to a set of interrelated concepts concerned with causation and causal relations in the natural or social worlds—a set that includes determination, contingency, dominance, overdetermination, determinability, and undecidability. For the social world, determinacy also raises questions about event and structural causation, the agency–structure problem, and issues of free will. This entry focuses on (1) causation, (2) social agency, (3) the relation between structural and agent causality, (4) the attribution of responsibility for events, and (5) ecological dominance as a type of structural causality that escapes one-sided structural determinism. Causation and Agency Causation is no more, but certainly no less, than the production (or, better, coproduction) of effects and, as such, occurs throughout the natural and social world. Causation is always relational. The capacity of a given force (or set of forces) to produce effects depends on its own causal powers and on the liabilities of the substance(s) or forces on which it acts and the circumstances in which it does so. Capacities and liabilities always exist in the first instance as potentials: they may remain latent and, if activated, may be reinforced, countered, or modified, intentionally or not, by other causal powers and liabilities. This suggests that power can be defined as a specific form of causation that entails the production of effects that would not otherwise happen. Of particular interest in the social sciences is the connection between power and agency, that is, the issue of whether and how agents’ conduct makes a difference. This raises difficult questions about intention and the unintended, mediated effects of its exercise. Empirically, it is often hard, sometimes impossible, to identify unambiguously, let alone uncontroversially, which, if any, agent(s) made a—let alone the—decisive difference to the occurrence of a given event. This is partly because events lack natural boundaries and can be defined in different ways for different purposes. This is especially true in complex conjunctures with multiple time horizons and temporalities, with a complex interweaving of Determinacy scales of action and spatialities, with interaction among many mechanisms, processes, and events, and with many types of agency and social force on the stage and behind the scenes. Identifying the agent(s) that made a decisive difference involves the selection, from many possible causal linkages, of those judged causally effective for a given result. Given that agents always act in specific circumstances, with distinctive constraints and opportunities that condition and mediate the exercise of power, one can attribute responsibility to circumstances, non-agential mechanisms, or actors. Any attribution will in turn relieve, in whole or part, other contributing circumstances, mechanisms, or actors of responsibility. However, because all actions occur in a continuing flow of actions, one can always redefine responsibility by redefining the event, extending timelines backward or forward, or looking at the origins of circumstances previously bracketed out. Redefining the event to be explained (i.e., the explanandum), extending its spatiotemporal context, and identifying a wider range of relevant causal factors would all change the attribution. Further complications can be introduced by inquiring into the origins of identities, preferences, modes of calculation, and so on, rather than taking these too as given. This may prove especially important when explaining events, processes, and outcomes that involve relations of power and domination or where the nature, causes, and solutions of major crises or analogous events are at issue. Such complexities generate debates about the one-, two-, or three-dimensional nature of power (see, classically, Steven Lukes). There is a risk of a manifold, infinite regress here, such that attributing responsibility so far, and no further, can be seen as a “political” act with its own social consequences. Determinacy and Contingent Necessity Whereas determination refers to the process of causation, determinacy involves the probability that a given effect will occur through the actualization of different sets of causal chains. This bears critically on structure and agency. Where a given causal effect is highly constrained structurally, it is strongly determinate. Moreover, where many structural forces interact to generate these constraints, the 175 effect is causally overdetermined. Where the constraints are loosely coupled and many outcomes are possible, structural determinacy is correspondingly looser. This increases the scope for the actions or interactions of particular social agents to make a difference. The same point can be made in terms of the dialectic of path dependency and path shaping. Loose coupling confronts actors with multiple choices. If no set of decision-making rules unambiguously determines the single correct course of action for actors when they assess relevant circumstances, the situation can be described as (algorithmically) undecidable. This forces actors to exercise free will. In such contexts, choice, however interpreted, becomes a key part of the explanation. This analysis points to the importance of contingent necessity. This apparently self-contradictory concept highlights the fact that, whereas the combination or interaction of different causal chains produces a determinate outcome (necessity), no single theory can predict or determine how or when such causal chains converge or interact (contingency). This is one feature of the asymmetrical nature of causation. We must analyze the many determinations in a concrete conjuncture and show how they interact as necessary or sufficient conditions in a contingent pattern of causation. This excludes all pretence to construct the theory of power and instead shows the need for theoretical and empirical tools to examine specific conjunctures. Exploring contingent necessities (or, better, contingently realized interactive causal necessities) requires one to combine concepts, assumptions, and principles of analysis from different theoretical domains and to link them to a given, theoretically defined explanandum. An explanation is only more or less satisfactory relative to a given explanandum that has been isolated (hence, “constructed”) by an observer from inexhaustible complexity. Max Weber spoke here of the practical impossibility (and, in many cases, theoretical redundancy) of following causal relationships down to the microscopic level of necessary links among the elementary constituents of reality. This applies regardless of the relatively macro–micro nature of the problem or the generality of the historical developments and outcomes to be explained. So it is vital to explain specific events in terms of specific causal antecedents, noting how 176 Determinacy specific causal processes or causal intersections from among many possible intersections intervened to produce an event that would not otherwise have occurred. The more macroscopic the explanandum and the greater its spatiotemporal reach, the more likely that structural rather than agential choice causation will be privileged in the explanation. This is where questions of determinacy invoke the specter of determinism. This involves offering one-sided causal explanations for complex, contingently necessary events, processes, or outcomes. Notorious social science examples allegedly occur within Marxism, including technological determinism, economic determinism, class reductionism, politicism (an exaggerated emphasis on political class domination and struggle), and ideologism or idealism (an overemphasis on ideological or more general ideational factors, respectively). But similar forms of one-sidedness occur in other modes of social explanation. Thus, technological determinism characterizes declarations that one cannot “halt the march of progress.” Economic reductionism is common in muckraking and attempts to identify the material interests at stake in any decision, enduring structure, or continuing process. Class reductionism occurs whenever actions are explained in terms of location in the relations of production, opportunities for profit in the market, levels of income or accumulated wealth, housing status, lifestyle, self-identification, or social status. Politicism is common in realism in international relations, in state-centered analyses of politics that emphasize the special logics, identities, and interests of states, state managers, parties, and political movements, and in theories that prioritize war, preparation for war, and its impact. Finally, idealism occurs when analysts focus one-sidedly on the role of ideas in history and disregard structural and conjunctural factors that select among ideas with the result that no idea is as powerful as one whose time is “ripe.” Economic Determinacy The complexity of causal relations precludes such one-sided causation and excludes “determination in the last instance” by a single set of causal forces, however tempting this might be for simplifying (the presentation of) an explanation or, for practical purposes at least, holding some factors/forces responsible. This problem can be exemplified through the historical materialist approach to economic determinacy. This may involve no more than strategic essentialism (privileging some causes or forces over others as a basis for decisive strategic action) but it may also (and often does) involve definite ontological claims about the relative importance of causal forces. Typically at stake here is the relationship between the logic of a profitoriented, market-mediated economy and the development or roles of other institutional orders or everyday consciousness and action. This directly touches the circumstances, if any, in which onesided explanations can be legitimately deployed. First, following Weber, we should distinguish among the directly economic moments of social relations, extra-economic moments that affect economic performance, and moments liable to economic causation. Neglecting this distinction leads to conclusion that the economic is determinant in the last instance because almost everything belongs to at least one of these categories so that the “economic” will figure somehow in every event and its explanation. Second, surveying work on economic determinacy proper, we can distinguish among economic determination in the first instance, economic domination, bourgeois hegemony, and ecological dominance. These involve quite different forms of economic determination. Economic determination in the first instance refers, legitimately, to the primacy of production inside the economy. In short, wealth must first be produced before it can be distributed or, in more Marxist terms, value must first be produced before it can be realized, redistributed, and reallocated. The more that profit-oriented, market-mediated exchange invades new areas, such economic determination will be greater, whether other types of exchange existed there before. This is a feature of contemporary neoliberalism but has no immediate bearing on the primacy of the economy in relation to residual extra-economic institutional orders or social life more generally. Economic domination rests on the capacity of those controlling strategic resources vital for a given branch of production or the economy as a whole to influence economic decisions or performance through the exercise of veto, strike, or blackmail power. Such domination may also affect other social relations insofar as the operations of Determinacy public or private institutions, organizations, or agents require access to such resources. Note here that economic bodies may depend in turn on access to resources that are generated outside the economy. Bourgeois hegemony also has a dual significance. It can refer to the capacity of specific economic forces to win hegemony for their techno-economic paradigm, business model, or broader economic strategy within the wider economy, or to the capacity to win such hegemony within the wider society, so that the hegemonic economic imaginary enters the assumptions and operations of other institutional orders and becomes part of common sense. Ecological dominance is the most interesting, and least explored, dimension of economic determinacy. It refers to the capacity of the profitoriented, market-mediated capitalist economic order—including its extra-economic supports—to influence the performance and, hence, evolution of other societal subsystems or institutional orders more than they can influence it. Originating in biology, this concept does not refer to the influence of the natural environment but to relations of dominance within a given social ecosystem. As such, the concept does not imply that the economy will inevitably become the ecologically dominant system in a given ecosystem. Ecological dominance is a property of the interaction among different systems and ways of life rather than one possessed by a given system considered in isolation. Thus, a given system can be more or less ecologically dominant; its dominance will vary across systems, institutional orders, and spheres of everyday life; and the extent and form of its dominance will depend on the overall development of the relevant social ecosystem. This implies in turn that the development of any ecologically dominant system will be shaped by the operation of other systems or the attempts by specific social forces to reverse, brake, or guide that dominance to advance their own logics or modes of understanding. Thus, as Edgar Morin argued, ecological dominance is an ecological relation in which one system becomes dominant in a complex, co-evolving situation; it does not entail a one-sided relation of domination whereby one system unilaterally imposes its logic or will on other systems. There is no last instance in relations of ecological dominance; they are 177 always contingent. So there is no economic determination in the last instance in this regard if the profit-oriented, market-mediated capitalist economy is, as Marxism indicates, more likely to become ecologically dominant. This suggests new ways to study economic determination as well as other forms of determinacy in a complex social world. Economic determination was always problematic for historical materialism as the economy lacks the autonomy (in the sense of being “a cause without cause”) to fully determine the extra-economic in the first, middle, or last instance. Indeed, as many theorists (including Karl Marx, Max Weber, Émile Durkheim, Karl Polanyi, Joseph Schumpeter, or Friedrich von Hayek) have noted, the market economy has important extraeconomic conditions and operates best when embedded within an appropriate form of market society. Conversely, a theory of internal relations, in which everything is related to everything else in a unified totality, cannot explain the causal asymmetries in interactions within and among institutional orders and everyday life. Ecological dominance is a third option. It highlights the scope for asymmetrical causal relations based on differential capacities and liabilities in a social ecosystem, such that, although one system may be ecologically dominant, it will nonetheless be differentially influenced in turn by its specific relations of reciprocal interdependence with other systems. Where the coevolution of interdependent institutional orders and social life occurs in the always contingent shadow of the ecological dominance of capital accumulation, however, a certain coherence is likely between what Marxism often, albeit misleadingly, describes as the economic base and its superstructure (see the entry on superstructure and substructure). Such structured coherence is particularly clear in the tight coupling among the economic, juridical, and political systems as operationally autonomous but materially interdependent institutional ensembles within capitalist societies. Conclusion Determinacy is a crucial aspect of power and domination. It is best explored in terms of the nature of causation, causal powers, and causality; the complexity of the natural and social worlds and the problem of contingent necessity; the need 178 Determinism to engage in complexity reduction; the contingent nature of attributions of responsibility—to circumstances, structures, or agency—in a given situation; and the range of theoretical approaches to social inquiry and their differential privileging of particular variables and entry points. This entry has focused on economic determination and determinacy in historical materialist explanation. But the arguments are easily generalized to other forms of domination, such as patriarchy, institutional racism, uneven development, or center–periphery relations, where one-sided explanations may prove tempting. The notion of ecological dominance is especially useful in exploring determinacy because it entails no commitment to one-sided causation or explanation. Bob Jessop See also Agency–Structure Problem; Causation; Domination; Free Will; Lukes, Steven; Marx, Karl; Racism, Role of Power in; Substructure and Superstructure; Weber, Max Further Readings Hausman, D. M. (1998). Causal asymmetries. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Jessop, B. (2007). State power: A strategic-relational approach. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Teubner, G. (1983). Law as an autopoietic system. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. DETERMINISM Determinism is the thesis that historical processes occur following scientific laws that ensure that all constituent events and states of the world are necessary and inevitable. Every event is caused by a previous event, all the way back to the Big Bang at the start of the universe. The way things are now could not have been otherwise. The deterministic thesis is developed in various ways, but the important aspect for the consideration of power is how this affects our attitudes toward agency: that is, how it affects the power of individuals to influence the world. If everything is caused, then everything I do is caused, and I have no independent causal powers. Thus, the correct explanation of any event in which I am involved must include previous events that caused everything I did. Agents can then be dropped from historical explanations. Such a thesis has obvious implications for theories of freedom and free will because our usual notion of free will is that we do have independent causal powers. When we act, we have choices, and “having choices” means that we could have chosen differently. This has to be a necessary feature of free will and independent human action. We consider here whether determinism and free will are compatible, and whether, even if determinism is true in some sense, we can still talk about humans having causal powers. A view that suggests both determinism and the meaningfulness of claims that humans have independent causal powers is usually called compatibilism. We note that the determinism versus free will issue is separate from or at least orthogonal to debates about structure and agency. Structure is, to some extent, the sets of social relations of agents acting, so if we act as we do because of structural constraints, we are not discussing determinism in the usual sense. Determinism as it is usually considered would mean that structures are created through historical inevitability just as human agency is so caused. Both agency and structure are caused by past events, so how agents and structure interact will not affect the fundamental causal story. Thus, if determinism is true, then either we have to consider the structure–agency debate otiose or we have to conclude that our compatibilist stance might have little effect, in itself, on our attitude to the relationship between structure and agency. Certainty and Probability We should get one issue out of the way before proceeding further. One way of construing the world is that nothing occurs with certainty. At the subatomic level, events seem probabilistic in the sense that we can only say with some probability what has occurred. One way of thinking about the universe is that one event does not follow another precisely with a probability of 1, but rather a probability that might approach 1 but never actually attains 1. Thus, a billiard ball striking another at a given angle and speed on a baize surface of given Determinism qualities under specific atmospheric conditions will lead the other to move at given speed and angle, not with certainty, but only with very high probability. The universe might very well be like that. However, this is of little comfort to those who worry that a fully determined universe leaves no room for free will. After all, what is the difference whether my actions are determined with probability 1 or with a probability approaching 1, when the difference between the probabilities has something to with things going on at the subatomic level and nothing to do with me? The issue is whether I can have any effect. To what extent am I in control or being determined? Whatever I do, with a probability approaching 1 or with a probability approaching zero, all that matters is whether these were determined (at the relevant probabilities) by events that went before. Causation In much of modern physics, the notion of causation has been jettisoned. The fundamental mathematics of physical processes do not include any causal arrows. Physicists usually consider that our notion of cause is simply a psychological imprint on the universe, given entropy. We see the causal arrow where entropy is greatest—that is, where there is least disorder in the sense that energy is more dissipated. One way of thinking about this is that the universe can be described by sets of mathematical equations, none of which involve any notion of causation (each side of an equivalence can be thought to describe or explain the other), but that we impose a notion of causation by the way in which we view the order of events. Causation is thus an imposition on the physical universe by us as living creatures. This is important because it might help us understand what we mean when we suggest that the events we have witnessed were inevitable or that they could have been otherwise. Taking an example of Daniel Dennett, was the assassination of John F. Kennedy determined at the time of the Big Bang? Let us assume determinism is true, and thus, given the precise conditions at the time of the Big Bang, every event in the universe followed its course until the moment Kennedy was shot. Do we consider that a full causal account of President Kennedy’s assassination must include the entire history of events that led from the Big Bang 179 to that moment? Did the Big Bang ultimately cause Kennedy’s death? Well, only in the sense that it caused everyone’s death. That is, the Big Bang was necessary for the assassination of Kennedy, but it was not sufficient. Imagine Kennedy was assassinated much as he was but that Lee Harvey Oswald’s bullet entered Kennedy at a slightly different angle and stopped his heart faster than it did in the actual world. In the deterministic universe, if we run the story back we must find that the Big Bang had to have been slightly different in some way. Hence, it is not true that the Big Bang as it actually occurred was necessary and sufficient for the assassination of Kennedy. It is these sorts of counterfactual notions by which we ordinarily think of the contingency of events such as the assassination of Kennedy. So we consider issues such as, “had I left the house slightly later, then I would have been on the road at that time, and thus would not have reached the junction at the same time as the motorbike.” We know the world has to be the way it is in the sense that once it is that way, it has to be that way. But we consider how the world could have been had we acted differently. Thus, our sense of something not being inevitable is in a counterfactual sense. But how could this reassure us about our independent powers in a deterministic world? Reactions and Addictions Consider certain actions that are reactions, things we do automatically, not unconsciously but quickly almost without conscious thought, such as braking hard to avoid hitting a motorbike at a junction. Your actions were caused because your car was going to hit the motorbike. It was caused by whatever causes our desires not to kill people on motorbikes. It was caused by the learned behavior of driving and stopping cars. And the evolutionary pressures led humans to have fast reactions, so fast we act almost without conscious thought to avoid danger. We know all of these facts—determinism does not teach us anything here—but we also know that we could have hit the motorbike: we might not have braked in time. But we do not worry that our reactions are outside of our control and not subject to free will. The latter consideration might be a little too fast. After all, we do worry about things we do 180 Determinism that we do not want to do. We want to lose weight, but have the chocolate cake and the extra biscuit. We might want to lie to our partner, but know that when we do we will blush or stammer or give something away so the partner knows we are lying. We are aware that we are not fully in control of our desires and our behavior. And often when we describe these behaviors we use the language of determinism. Addicts talk about being driven to drink or to gamble; we talk about “not being able to resist” the cake or the biscuit; or knowing that we are not in control of our blushes or “tells” that give us away when we are lying. Nevertheless, we do not consider that these facts mean that everything we do is determined. These facts do not lead us to think we do not have free will. After all, we use them to contrast with the other actions to which we are not driven. We might think about such activities that we are driven to as being ones where the incentives to act differently are just too high. If we have really strong incentives to lose weight—to fit into the wedding dress—then we might overcome the chocolate temptations when otherwise we could not. It has been shown that the brain states of addicts demonstrate pleasurable highs just before indulging in the addictive behavior (taking the drug, pulling the arm of the slot machine). Here the temptations are too great to resist in part, for the addict, because the pleasure comes about through the temptation rather than the actions in themselves. What is the difference then between the driven behavior and other behaviors where we do not feel driven? The actual outcomes, the actual behavior, cannot be changed: whatever happens, happens. However, where the temptations were not so great, we can imagine not doing the actions we actually did do. In the car example, we probably could not have avoided braking: our evolutionary heritage gave us the reactions and the training did the rest. We do not mind that; indeed we are pleased that our reactions and training were so good, and we do not worry about the deterministic universe. After all, what we did was what we wanted to do. In most of our actions, even those we regret, we say we did what we wanted to do. Only when we do not want to do what we do, in some sense, at the moment we take the actions do we feel driven. But here the distinction is not between one sort of action and another, but our attitude to that action even as we are doing it. Something is inevitable for a person if that person can do nothing about it. Once driving the car, hitting the motorcycle is inevitable if it pulls out too close for me to be able to brake in time. In that case, I might say that it was inevitable that I knocked down the motorcyclist given my speed and his or her actions. What I mean by that is that there is nothing (reasonable) that I could have done to avoid that collision. Indeed, the unexpected leads us to say there is nothing we could have done. We expect cars to pull out from junctions if they have priority, so we slow down or stop to see if there are any cars that are going to do so. In such a case, it is no excuse to say, “Given the speed I was traveling and given how he pulled out, it was inevitable I was going to hit him.” Any such excuse leads to the response, “Then why were you traveling at that speed?” The more predictable or, if you like, the more determined the environment the more control we can have over our actions with regard to it. Feeling and Being Braking quickly to avoid hitting the motorbike is a result of reactions created during our evolutionary history and the driver training we received. Nevertheless, we feel as though we are in control, and indeed, we are. Even if the reaction occurred faster than I can consciously think about braking, I still braked. Indeed driving a well-functioning car might give the strongest sense of control that one can have. Paradigmatic examples of making choices might actually lead to feelings of being in less control. I might be faced with a tough decision: do I hire or let go a probationary employee? I might take a long time weighing the pros and cons, and reluctantly decide to let him or her go, thinking it best for the company and for the person, who might always struggle in that role. Surely this is a paradigm example of choice, yet I might feel in less control because I like the person and would like to have him or her continue, but feel in the end it would be best not to hire that person. It seems out of my control because it is the nature of the role the person is being asked to perform and his or her fitness to carry out that role that have forced my hand. So feeling in control is not anything to do with the nature of the decision making as such. Whether Deterrence Theory one’s actions are reactions or behavior that occurs after careful consideration one might feel more or less in control of the situation. However, how one feels, it might be objected, is not the same as whether one is really in control. And that is the issue with regard to determinism. But is it? In a fully determined world as perceived by modern physics, causation has no role except as measured by entropy. For most physicists, causation has no role in fundamental physics so it is best described as a psychological imposition on the universe by creatures like us. And we have that psychological impetus because it is to our advantage. The reactions that we have developed through evolution have fitted us well in this world, and these reactions, like our way of viewing the world, are part of our psychology. Thus, to the extent that causation in the universe is a psychological imputation, then our feeling of being in control in those situations where we impute a causal role for ourselves is the causal role in those situations. Determinism and our view of ourselves as agents are completely compatible. Independent Power Agents have independent powers because they are part of the fabric of the universe and act and react in relation to structures and the environment around them. Those powers are independent in the same way that anything is independent. They can be described without reference to anything else. The extent to which nothing can be described without reference to anything else gives the limit to that independence. Even if all processes are historically determined, agents still have independent powers, and the extent to which they feel in control is the extent of that control because it is the extent to which their actions can be described without reference to anything else outside of them. Keith Dowding See also Agency; Agency–Structure Problem; Autonomy; Control; Free Will; Freedom Further Readings Benci, V., Cerrai, P., Freguglia, P., Israel, G., & Pellegrini, C. (Eds.). (2003). Determinism, holism and complexity. New York: Kluwer. 181 Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom evolves. London: Allen Lane. DETERRENCE THEORY Deterrence theory in international relations concerns the conditions under which a state i is able to prevent another state j from attacking i by convincing j that it runs the risk that this attack will be answered by a retaliatory strike that will inflict catastrophic damage. The theory has primarily been developed by U.S. strategic thinkers—most notably Bernard Brodie, Albert Wohlstetter, and Thomas Schelling—since the 1940s against the background of the nuclear arms race between the United States and the Soviet Union, which lasted until the end of the 1980s. Given this background, deterrence theory in international relations has particularly focused on the requirements and implications of a “stable balance of terror,” a situation, that is, in which each of the states involved has acquired the capability, in case it is the victim of a surprise attack, to launch a counterattack that will severely punish the aggressor. Until the beginning of the 1930s, there existed only two ways to make sure by military means that an adversary refrained from armed aggression. One way meant that a state, with or without the assistance of allies, attempted to dissuade the opponent from attacking by building a defense strong enough to convince the opponent that it would not be worth its while to attack. The other way was aimed at compelling the adversary, again with or without the help of allies, to disarm. Thanks to a successful surprise attack on the adversary’s territory (or by threatening to carry out such a preemptive strike), a state could compel its enemy to reduce its weapons arsenal or its military forces. Note that a credible defense means that the adversary is prevented from behaving in a certain way, though in the case of successful “compellence,” the adversary is forced to behave in a particular manner. For this reason, it is easier to prevent aggression through defense than through compellence. The preparations for war by the opponents were furthermore geared to fighting a war on the ground. Everything turned on the conquest of territory, or, conversely, on the prevention 182 Deterrence Theory of the conquest of territory. The development of long-range bomber aircraft added a third method for preventing an adversary from attacking: deterrence. This means that a state threatens to punish its opponent in case of attack by “strategic bombardments” of the attacker’s population and industries, rather than fighting it out on the ground. The aim of deterrence, just like defense, is to discourage a potential aggressor from attacking. Here, however, a state does so not by ensuring that the state’s defense is so strong that it would never pay the aggressor to attack, but by seeing to it that an attack will be severely punished with the large-scale destruction of the aggressor’s resources. Defense is a strategy based on denial, and deterrence is based on punishment. To explore the relationship between defense and deterrence still further, if a state succeeded in building a perfect defense, so that it was completely invulnerable to whatever offensive weapons a possible attacker might employ against it, then this state could no longer be deterred by any other state. The crucial chain in the theory’s line of argument must be that a nuclear surprise attack will elicit a nuclear counterattack that will wreak havoc on the attacker’s cities and population. As many have pointed out, it is highly problematic whether this will happen in fact. It may be rational to threaten with Armageddon to prevent an attack, but is it rational to carry out this threat when the deterrent has failed and the dreaded attack has started? Deterrence theory is apparently based on the assumption that the leader of a state that becomes the victim of a nuclear attack will act like an envious individual: that she or he will prefer the outcome that both states are destroyed to the outcome of defeat. But surely we can imagine that the leader who has to take the fatal decision to launch a retaliatory strike will not always be capable of willingly ordering the destruction of the lives of tens of millions of people out of revenge? A retaliatory nuclear strike therefore can never be a certainty, only a possibility. But if this is correct, then the credibility of the deterrent is undermined in advance and has thereby lost any effectiveness it might have had. Schelling recognized this problem and argued that the threat of inadvertent war and its consequent horrors—the suggestion that a disastrous all-out war can be the result of an accident, panic, or misapprehension, that there might be no time to reflect coolly on the fatal decision to launch the retaliatory strike—will lend the deterrent its credibility and convince the potential aggressor not to attack. In view of the possible terrible consequences, a “threat that leaves something to chance” will be credible, when in other circumstances it would fail. Accepting Schelling’s argument, a state i will be successful in deterring another state j from attacking i, if i has been able to convince j that a surprise attack or a preemptive strike on i might lead to a devastating counterattack. In this situation, state i must have succeeded in convincing state j, first that the latter will never be able to destroy in a first strike i’s capability to strike back and inflict unacceptable damage on j, and second that j can never be sure that i will not use this second-strike capability in retaliation. If state j for its part has also succeeded in acquiring a second-strike capability, as well as in convincing i of the possibility that it might be used in retaliation, then both states find themselves in a situation of what has come to be known as mutually assured destruction (MAD). The term and its acronym were introduced in 1964. Originally, the concept was to be known as assured retaliation, but as Lawrence Freedman has pointed out, “this was felt to be too bland. The harshness of the term and the inescapable tragedy described in its definition were intentional.” Later, the term mutual or common deterrence was also introduced to emphasize that states that find themselves in this situation have a common interest in avoiding their annihilation. A balance of deterrence can only work if it is stable. This means that the retaliatory capacity of the states must remain more or less invulnerable to a surprise attack. The states will therefore constantly worry about the consequences of possible technological advances that may increase the effectiveness of the other’s first-strike weapons and thereby the vulnerability of its own second-strike force. This susceptibility to technological innovation is one of the reasons that induced Wohlstetter to speak of a “delicate” balance of terror. Were one of the states able to steal a march on the other in greatly strengthening its first-strike forces as a result of a technological breakthrough, then this would have a highly destabilizing effect on the balance, and increase the chances of nuclear war. The more vulnerable the second-strike capability of the one state becomes, the more that will be tempted Deterrence Theory to use the capability before the state is destroyed by the other state’s superior first-strike forces. Common deterrence can only work if the states involved, even in case of an all-out surprise attack, will always have the capability of destroying the cities, industries, and the population of the attacker. Second-strike weapons must be not precision weapons, but weapons of indiscriminate destruction. Seen from this perspective, a stable balance of terror, in Schelling’s words, “is simply a massive and modern version of an ancient institution: the exchange of hostages . . . a tacit understanding backed by a total exchange of all conceivable hostages.” Although this analogy, as Michael Walzer has shown, is not fully correct, because hostages are kept under restraint, whereas the peoples of the states that mutually deter one another are able to lead normal lives (in the case of the United States, they were even free to emigrate), it has to be admitted that mutual deterrence can only work if both parties accept that their societies should not be protected against a second strike. For this reason, the attempts by the United States and the Soviet Union in the 1960s to build an anti-ballistic missile (ABM) system to protect cities from the effects of an enemy attack, as well as the U.S. Strategic Defense Initiative (SDI) in the 1980s to develop a system to detect, track, and shoot down incoming rockets, apart from being not feasible, flatly contradicted the logic of common deterrence. Although it is perfectly understandable that states finding themselves in a situation of mutual deterrence will want to protect their populations as much as possible against the disastrous consequences of a nuclear war that may be the result of miscalculation or accident, mutual deterrence can only be effective if they refrain from taking such measures. Strategic thinkers or “defense intellectuals” may stoically resign themselves to this unpalatable truth, but one can readily understand why this is too much to ask from the leaders and the general populace of the states that face MAD. Already in the early 1950s, in the wake of the launch of the “New Look” by the Eisenhower administration in an attempt to get defense spending under control by cutting conventional forces and relying more on the U.S. capacity for “massive retaliation,” U.S. defense analysts came to realize that an exclusive reliance on vast thermonuclear 183 forces to deter acts of aggression would be untenable. In view of the terrifying consequences, the use of nuclear weapons is only conceivable in situations where the vital interests of the state are at stake, which means that a state possessing only an arsenal of nuclear weapons would be powerless to deal with minor acts of aggression, in particular when the latter were committed by an adversary that possesses a second-strike capacity. To counter limited aggression, a state must have the capability to fight with success a defensive war on the lower rungs of the escalation ladder with conventional and perhaps even battlefield nuclear weapons. This is the doctrine of graduate deterrence. A state that possesses nuclear weapons must have at the same time the weapons that enable it to repel aggression at any level lower than all-out nuclear war. Many have noted with Hans Morgenthau that this doctrine seems to spell disaster. Does it not follow that nuclear states will be more prepared to get involved in low-level armed conflicts, which subsequently escalate to higher and higher levels, thereby increasing the chances of a thermonuclear war, the prevention of which was the purpose of the enterprise in the first place? The conclusion therefore can be no other than that the same rule applies to these conventional and tactical nuclear weapons as to the nuclear weapons making up a state’s second-strike capability—they are there to deter but not to use. The understanding that a state possessing nuclear weapons will only use these weapons in situations where its vital interests are at stake is highly relevant in the case where a nuclear state has not excluded the possibility that it will use its nuclear weapons to punish an attack on a nonnuclear ally, again particularly when that ally is attacked by a state that also has a second-strike capacity. Is this “extended deterrence” credible? This question lay at the heart of many disputes between the United States and its West European allies during the cold war, once it had become clear that U.S. territory had become vulnerable to a Soviet nuclear attack, at first with long-range bombers and later on with missiles. Was Western Europe vital enough to the United States for it to use nuclear weapons to punish Soviet aggression, thereby risking a nuclear counterattack on its own territory? Seen from this angle, the primary function of the U.S. troops and weapons stationed on 184 Deterrent Threats West European soil was not so much that they could contribute to a successful defense were Soviet troops to cross the Elbe River, but that they acted as a threat that leaves something to chance. They were hostages, this time in the true sense of the word, to the U.S. commitment to Western Europe, and the Soviet Union could never be sure that U.S. anxiety and anger about their fate following a Soviet invasion might not trigger a fatal nuclear response. Edward Carr observed in 1939 that war “lurks in the background of international politics,” and it should be added that war has retreated even further into the background after World War II, at least as far as the relationships between the nuclear powers are concerned. In a situation of common deterrence, strategy is no longer necessarily related to the actual use of the means of violence. For these powers, the distinction between strategy and politics (diplomacy) has disappeared. In the nuclear age, arms are for influencing potential opponents rather than for defeating them, and this perception led Kenneth Waltz to the conclusion that, as far as the spread of nuclear arms is concerned, “more may be better.” Robert H. Lieshout See also Extended Deterrence; Mutually Assured Destruction Further Readings Freedman, L. (1989). The evolution of nuclear strategy. London: Macmillan. Schelling, T. C. (1980). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Waltz, K. N. (1981). The spread of nuclear weapons: More may be better. London: International Institute for Strategic Studies. Wohlstetter, A. (1959). The delicate balance of terror. Foreign Affairs, 37(2), 21–33. DETERRENT THREATS The fundamental idea of deterrence is simple enough. A party is deterred from some action when it decides against the action to avoid a response threatened by a second party. Note the two conditions: (1) the threat by the second party must be explicit and contingent on the initial action and (2) absent the threat, the first party must prefer to carry out the action. Deterrence has long played a role in human life—for instance in law enforcement systems designed to deter crime, in the efforts of parents to deter children from misbehaving, and in policies of empires aimed at deterring attacks on their possessions and client states. Also common is the two-sided variant of deterrence, in which two sides reciprocally deter each other, as in an armed standoff. Deterrence has always been a fundamental component of international politics. But at the end of World War II, the demonstrated power of nuclear weapons persuaded many thinkers that the success of deterrence was now of ultimate priority: the proper aim of deterrence based on the threat of nuclear retaliation seemed to be to ensure that the threat never had to be implemented. Success in deterrence was declared to be the keystone of U.S. foreign policy, and U.S. military strategist Bernard Brodie famously suggested that the main purpose of the military had been to win wars, but from now on its main purpose is to avert them. But deterrence based on a threat that cannot be carried out seemed problematic. The debate about rationality and deterrence began in the decade immediately following World War II when the rapidly developing field of game theory was exploring the concept of rational choice, defined as choosing alternatives that are most in the chooser’s own interest. To see the terms of the debate, represent unilateral deterrence as an extensive-form game shown in Figure 1, where the first party is called Initiator and the second Defender. Deterrence occurs when the Initiator chooses Do Not Act, and the outcome is Status Quo (SQ). Other possible outcomes are Revision (Rev), if Initiator acts but Defender does not respond, and Confrontation (Conf), if Initiator acts and then Defender responds. To understand deterrence, one must understand when each possible sequence of actions will be selected. Before addressing the conditions for the success of deterrence, we make the assumptions that (A1) Initiator prefers Revision to Status Quo. (A2) Defender prefers Status Quo to Revision. Deterrent Threats Confrontation Respond Act 185 Defender Initiator Do not act Do not respond Revision Status Quo Figure 1 Unilateral Deterrence Without (A1), there is nothing to deter. Without (A2), there is no reason to deter it. Consistent with these assumptions, Initiator is a revisionist state and Defender a status-quo power. For games such as unilateral deterrence, game theory recommends a solution concept called subgame perfect equilibrium, which models each player (party) as making choices to achieve its most preferred available outcome, on the assumption that any subsequent choices will be made according to this same principle. Assuming rationality and full information, choices depend solely on each player’s relative preferences over the three possible outcomes: barring ties, Initiator has three preference orderings consistent with (A1), and Defender has three consistent with (A2). As it happens, there is always a unique subgame perfect equilibrium, which is shown in Table 1. In particular, the outcome is Status Quo when Defender prefers Confrontation to Revision and Initiator prefers Status Quo to Confrontation. Thus, for deterrence to succeed, Defender’s threat must satisfy two conditions: (C1) Credibility: Defender prefers Confrontation to Revision. (C2) Capability: Initiator prefers Status Quo to Confrontation. Here, credibility means that, should the situation actually arise, Defender would prefer to execute the threat, and capability means that Initiator prefers that the threat not be carried out; in other words, the threatened response would hurt Initiator. For the unilateral deterrence game, game theory has a second, weaker solution concept. A Nash equilibrium is a pattern of planned choices (a “strategy profile”) that, if anticipated by all parties, motivates each party to choose according to the pattern, in its own interest. The pattern (Do Not Act, Respond) is a Nash equilibrium if condition Table 1 Unilateral deterrence (Figure 1) outcomes consistent with (A1) and (A2) Initiator’s Preference Defender’s Preference Outcome Conf Rev SQ Conf SQ Rev Conf Conf Rev SQ SQ Conf Rev Conf Conf Rev SQ SQ Rev Conf Rev Rev Conf SQ Conf SQ Rev Conf Rev Conf SQ SQ Conf Rev Conf Rev Conf SQ SQ Rev Conf Rev Rev SQ Conf Conf SQ Rev SQ Rev SQ Conf SQ Conf Rev SQ Rev SQ Conf SQ Rev Conf Rev (C2) holds, and does not depend on (C1). Thus, the Nash equilibrium analysis says that deterrence works as long as the threat is capable, without regard to credibility. The crucial idea is that, if Initiator believes Defender’s threat, then its capability is sufficient to deter Initiator. For nuclear deterrence immediately after World War II, and throughout the cold war, that was exactly the issue. Many arguments were advanced to explain the remarkable stability of deterrence despite the lack of credibility of the threat of nuclear retaliation. Structural theorists argued that broad structural parameters, such as the bipolar nature of the system and the nuclear retaliatory threat, were responsible. The missile war model essentially sidestepped the credibility issue, deriving stability conditions from the balance of offensive and defensive capabilities. The simultaneous 2 2 chicken game was posited as the fundamental model of bilateral deterrence, combining actions and threats; the decision-theory approach considered a continuous 186 Deutsch, Karl sequence of these games, and calculated optimal choices based on a model of the opponent’s decision making (rather than the assumption of rationality). Thomas Schelling, in particular, was the first to emphasize the non–zero-sum nature of the chicken model, and his ideas of making threats credible were developed into so-called manipulative bargaining theory, which included such strategies as manipulating one’s own payoffs (to make a threat more credible), and even feigning irrationality. Schelling also proposed the threat-that-leavessomething-to-chance, an idea that was eventually incorporated into game-theoretic analyses of deterrence as probabilistic beliefs that a threat is beyond control and may therefore be executed. These game models showed that deterrence is an outcome that rational players might attain, though they did not explain why the players might construct such a situation. Finally, perfect deterrence theory offered a new and unified model of all deterrence, making it fully rational and replacing the credibility requirement with uncertainty about the other side’s true preferences. Deterrence, Frank Zagare and Marc Kilgour argued, is based on the Initiator’s probabilistic belief that the Defender prefers to execute the threat; nuclear deterrence is different in degree but not in kind. Marc Kilgour See also Chicken Games; Conventional Deterrence; Deterrence Theory; Extended Deterrence; Mutually Assured Destruction; Rationality; Threats Further Readings Schelling, T. C. (1980). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Zagare, F. C., & Kilgour, D. M. (2000). Perfect deterrence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DEUTSCH, KARL (1912–1992) One of the foremost U.S. political scientists of the post–World War II period was Karl Deutsch, whose work helped expand the frontiers of knowledge of politics and political development. The creation of a network of scholars, a lifelong dedication to teaching, a commitment to data-based research, and the publication of numerous academic works were among Deutsch’s major contributions to the field of social sciences. Karl Wolfgang Deutsch was born on July 21, 1912, to Maria Scharf Deutsch and Martin Deutsch in Prague. Karl had a brilliant academic record from German Staatsrealgymnasium, the German University, and Charles University in Prague, where he took a law degree. An outspoken opponent of Nazism, he and his wife Ruth Slonitz could not remain in Nazi-dominated Czechoslovakia of the post-Munich era, so they emigrated to the United States in 1938. Deutsch enrolled at Harvard for further studies and joined government service after the U.S. entry into World War II. As a member of the International Secretariat of the San Francisco Conference of 1945, he participated in the creation of the United Nations. He began his teaching career at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT). Deutsch also worked on his doctoral dissertation, Nationalism and Social Communication, at Harvard and published scholarly articles. In 1952, he was appointed a full professor of history and political science at MIT. His teaching assignments spanned reputed institutions and universities in the United States and abroad. Deutsch was with the Center for Research on World Political Institutions at Princeton University; the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Palo Alto, California; the University of Chicago; and Yale University before becoming Stanfield Professor of International Peace at Harvard. Deutsch’s first major academic work was an empirical study of West Germany’s revival after 1945. He used quantitative methods to try to test hypotheses in the social sciences. His book Nationalism and Social Communication: An Inquiry Into the Foundations of Nationality, based on his doctoral dissertation, was truly interdisciplinary. His model of nationalism was valuable for research on nation building and international integration. Deutsch collaborated widely with colleagues from many disciplines. In Political Community and the North Atlantic Area, Deutsch explained how the interaction between the elites and masses in the form of communications was vital in development of nationalism. His emphasis was more on community formation than on union of separate units. Dictatorship Deustch is best known as a systems theorist popular in political science in the 1950s and 1960s. More mathematical than many other systems theorists, he applied cybernetics and the study of communications and controls to politics using simulation models and system dynamics in verifying different propositions pertaining to social, political, and economic problems. The application of mathematical analysis opened new ground in the study of politics. His best-known work is The Nerves of Government, which examined communication and control in political systems. Patit Paban Mishra See also Nationalism Further Readings Deutsch, K. W. (1963). The nerves of government: Models of political communication and control. London: Free Press of Glencoe. Deutsch, K. W. (1966). Nationalism and social communication: An inquiry into the foundations of nationality. Cambridge: MIT Press. Merritt, R. L., Russett, B. M., & Dahl, R. A. (2001). Karl Wolfgang Deutsch: July 21, 1912–November 1, 1992. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. DICTATORSHIP Dictatorship is an autocratic form of governance under which the ruling authority is responsible to no one for his or her deeds. The term is used synonymously (although not necessarily accurately) with the terms totalitarianism, tyranny, despotism, and absolutism. Dictatorial regimes have historically been responsible for some of the most malevolent, socially injurious actions ever perpetrated by humankind. This entry highlights some of the characteristics of dictatorships, how they have historically manifested themselves, and the implications for the evolution of human rights. The term dictatorship refers to an autocratic style of rule or governance. It is distinguished from the term totalitarianism in that the latter term includes reference to the degree of control (namely, over the totality of social existence), which typically 187 includes the means of production and labor. The etymology of the term dictatorship locates its origin in the early Roman constitution, which provided for a temporary office of exceptional power for use in emergencies. When considered in its original Roman context, Juan J. Linz notes that dictatorships cannot be identified until they have disbanded, because the classification of a dictatorship is contingent on its temporary status. A less restrictive definition is provided in the Oxford English Dictionary, which defines a dictator as “a ruler or governor whose word is law; an absolute ruler of a state.” Perhaps the quintessential example of a modern dictator in this context was Adolf Hitler, whose word was given the full force of codified law subsequent to the German Reichstag’s passage of the Enabling Act in 1933. Scholars have recognized that there are varying degrees of dictatorship and usually classify them according to the extent of control they maintain over the daily affairs of their citizenry. Jeanne Kirkpatrick identified one end of the continuum as representing “totalitarian dictatorships,” which are characterized as regimes that are focused on massive intervention in all areas of social and economic life. These are typically motivated by some underlying utopian goal and are exemplified by the dictatorial regimes of the former Soviet Union and Nazi Germany. At the opposite end of the spectrum of dictatorships are less repressive traditional autocracies. These regimes interfere minimally with conventional social relations, typically doing so only to the extent that it helps ruling elites capitalize on the fruits of their status, often by draining state financial reserves to increase their personal wealth. Consequently, they are sometimes referred to as “tin-pot” regimes. Traditional autocracies are also relatively politically unstable in comparison with more repressive dictatorial regimes, which is unfortunate considering that they have historically been less antagonistic toward nations founded on democratic ideals. Traditional autocracies flourished in the Middle East during the late 20th century, and are exemplified in the dictatorial regimes of Ferdinand Marcos and Manuel Noriega. Some scholars have noted that the economic motivations underlying political decision making in democratic regimes is qualitatively similar to the decision-making process that occurs under 188 Diplomacy dictatorship. These scholars note that dictators do not repress merely for the sake of repression, but to maintain and increase their political power. All governments provide services, including dictatorships, in the form of protection from potentially hostile regimes as well as funding public works projects (e.g., roadway construction). Ronald Wintrobe found that the type of dictatorial regime affected how it responded to improving economic conditions, whereby traditional autocracies reduced their level of repression whereas totalitarian regimes acted contrarily. One of the distinguishing features of a dictatorship is the degree to which power is monolithically located in the hands of few ruling elites. Even where there exists a proliferation of government institutions, within dictatorships they derive their power from central authorities. Another characteristic of dictatorships involves their use of complex ideologies that justify the historic legitimacy of the regime and are used to interpret and understand contemporary events. Within a dictatorship, political participation is usually possible only to the degree that one joins the party ideologically favored by the regime. Another hallmark of dictatorship is the emphasis leaders place on controlling dissenting and contrary political perspectives. The degree of control can range from supervision and control of media outlets to outright suppression, with potentially dire consequences for nonconforming individuals. Dictatorships maintain elaborate police forces whose duties typically include the monitoring and censorship of dissidents seen as potentially challenging to the legitimacy of the regime. The consequences for those who criticize dictatorial regimes from within can be dreadful and include torture, confinement in concentration camps, forced labor, and outright murder. In cases where dissidents have been prosecuted via judicial proceedings for their alleged misdeeds, dictatorial regimes have occasionally concealed their intent by facilitating elaborate “show trials.” These procedures involve the forgery of an actual judicial procedure to produce the foregone conclusion of guilt. Of recent international interest is the trend toward making dissidents (and their families) disappear. These cases only garner attention by virtue of their unusual lack of fanfare coupled with the stifled suffering and questioning of confused acquaintances. Dictators are historically responsible to no domestic or international entities for their actions and policies, ruling with the absolute authority of functional deities. When considered as a class, dictators have been responsible for instigating, promoting, and participating in many of the most socially injurious actions ever committed. Douglas J. Dallier See also Absolutism; Arendt, Hannah; Authority; Exploitation; Fascism; Ideology; Military in Government; Responsibility; Totalitarianism Further Readings Arendt, H. (1958). The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Meridian. Friedrich, C. J., & Brzezinski, Z. K. (1965). Totalitarian dictatorship and autocracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kirkpatrick, J. J. (1982). Dictatorship and double standards: Rationalism and realism in politics. New York: Simon & Schuster. Linz, J. (1975). Totalitarian and authoritarian regimes. In F. Greenstein & N. Polsby (Eds.), Handbook of political science. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Wintrobe, R. (1990). The tinpot and the totalitarian: An economic theory of dictatorship. American Political Science Review, 84(September), 849–872. DIPLOMACY Diplomacy is not an unequivocal concept and can be simply defined as the conduct of international relations by negotiation. Alternately, diplomacy is characterized as the communication system of the international society, the peaceful conduct of relations among political entities, or, in more existential terms, mediation between estranged individuals, groups, or entities. Whereas the very word diplomacy might be imprecise, one might distinguish two different perspectives on diplomacy in the scholarly literature, both of which relate to power—yet in contradictory ways. One perspective, closely associated with classic realism, is to regard diplomacy as an asset of states. Diplomacy then becomes a component, or reflection, of state power. Another perspective Diplomacy views diplomacy as an international institution, that is, a relatively stable collection of norms and rules that prescribe behavioral roles, constrain activity, and shape expectations. Diplomacy is then located at the level of international society rather than of individual states, and is seen to temper, rather than reflect, state power. Hans Morgenthau is emblematic of the first perspective. In his Politics Among Nations, he includes “the quality of diplomacy” among elements of national power. Considering all the other factors that determine national power as the raw material of power, Morgenthau argues that the quality of a nation’s diplomacy combines these different factors into an integrated whole, turning potentialities into actual power. To Morgenthau, the conduct of a nation’s foreign affairs by its diplomats is for national power in peace what military strategy and tactics by its military leaders are for national power in war. Diplomacy, in this view, is included among, and depends on, other, more material capabilities; hence, it reflects state power. However, the quality of diplomacy may modify the value of other elements of state power. Thus, skillful diplomacy can increase the power of a nation beyond what one would expect it to be in view of other, material factors. Conversely, poor diplomacy may prevent otherwise powerful states from making full use of their power potentials. As an example of an outclassed state in material terms wielding power chiefly by virtue of its brilliant diplomacy, Morgenthau cites France from 1890 to 1914. Furthermore, he argues that British power covaried with the quality of British diplomacy, and that the first decades of skillful U.S. diplomacy were followed by a long period of mediocrity, or even ineptitude. Raymond Aron, another classic realist, expresses a similar dual understanding of diplomacy as an element of state power. On the one hand, diplomacy implies the use of economic, psycho-political, and violent means and the choice of appropriate means among them; on the other hand, “pure” diplomacy relies on persuasion alone, without economic and political pressure or violence. Yet, Aron doubts that pure diplomacy exists. To be sure, states may make every effort to convince both adversaries and onlookers that they want to persuade or convince, not to constrain, and adversaries may have the illusion of freedom, even when 189 they are in fact yielding to force. Yet, persuasion that is not backed up by power has little chance of success, according to Aron. The other, institutionalist perspective on diplomacy is primarily associated with the so-called English School. Adherents of this school argue, in opposition to realists, that beyond an international system, however anarchic, there exists an international society, reflected in certain international institutions with concomitant norms, rules, and practices. Diplomacy is seen as one of these institutions. Martin Wight characterizes diplomacy as “the master-institution” of international relations, and other authors in the English School tradition count diplomacy among the central international institutions along with sovereignty, war, and international law. As one of the major institutions of the society of states, diplomacy is seen to have a moderating influence on state power, “taming the sovereigns,” in Kalevi Holsti’s words. Diplomacy is one crucial component in the set of institutional arrangements that for the most part allows states to coexist peacefully and to interact in rule-bound environments that enhance the opportunities for mutual communication, trade, and flows of people and ideas. By providing links of communication and representation between states and regulating their day-to-day intercourse, diplomacy sets limits on the unrestricted use of state power. If diplomacy is viewed as a “thin” international institution, involving merely rules of coexistence, allowing political units “to live and let live,” an institutionalist perspective can be combined with the realist conceptualization of diplomacy as a reflection of state power. However, if diplomacy is viewed as a “thick” institution, involving a shared commitment to peace among diplomats, guided by raison d’état and by raison de système, it serves as a restriction on state power. At issue is the relationship between diplomacy and the use of force. Whereas diplomacy has been characterized as the art of convincing without using force, some students of contemporary international relations have coined the phrase coercive diplomacy to denote the use of threats or limited force to persuade opponents not to change the status quo in their favor or to call off or undo an encroachment. In this view, the use of military power can be an integral part of 190 Discipline diplomacy. In one sense, therefore, diplomacy and war can be seen as complementary rather than contrary institutions. Historically, symbolic power, or precedence, has played a prominent role in diplomacy. Early European diplomacy was full of endless struggles for precedence and crises caused by intended or unintended slights between diplomats. In the 19th century, diplomatic rules that neutralized the issue of precedence were initiated and gradually institutionalized. Thus, precedence among envoys is now established according to the date they have presented their credentials, disregarding the power of the state they represent, and alphabetical order is used by international organizations and conferences to avoid precedence issues in seating arrangements, treaty signatures, and the like. Christer Jönsson See also Anarchy in International Relations; Gunboat Diplomacy Further Readings George, A. L. (1991). Forceful persuasion: Coercive diplomacy as an alternative to war. Washington, DC: U.S. Institute of Peace Press. Holsti, K. (2004). Taming the sovereigns: Institutional change in international politics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Jönsson, C., & Hall, M. (2005). Essence of diplomacy. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Raymond, A. (1966). Peace and war: A theory of international relations. New York: Praeger. DISCIPLINE Discipline is a cognate of power related primarily to self-control, or power over oneself. Whoever has power over his or her self has discipline. By extension, discipline relates to power over others in the sense of training or having instilled training in others such that one is able to successfully command them. An army that obeys has discipline. Although they are distinct, obedience is sometimes confused with discipline. The sort of discipline exhibited by armies involves a command–obey structure containing two distinct parties and a hierarchical arrangement of some sort. In its wider senses, for example when scholarship or the sciences are referred to as disciplines, discipline implies obedience to rules and expectations, but need not imply two parties nor any sort of hierarchy. Self-control has usually been understood as the ability to command and obey oneself. Another understanding takes self-control as the ability to make oneself fully submit to an authority, such as a leader, community, or scripture. The latter has been common among military and religious orders, whereas the former has been a prime area of concern for philosophers. For many philosophers, such as Aristotle and Niccolò Machiavelli, self-control is a prerequisite for attaining and maintaining power over others. For Aristotle, it is required for gaining mental and physical skills in general, but is especially crucial for acquiring a virtuous, well-rounded character. The virtues are conceived as a set of habits, and Aristotle believed it was possible to train oneself to have virtuous habits. For example, if one talks too much or too little, then to achieve the virtuous mean between them requires restraint from speaking in the first case and motivation to speak in the second. Repeated application of the proper principle will yield the habit of speaking a moderate, virtuous amount. For other thinkers, such as Friedrich Nietzsche, independence of mind requires selfdiscipline, because “he who cannot obey himself will obey someone else.” For Machiavelli, the first task of a would-be sovereign is to raise and discipline a militia. The militia will tend to reflect the character of its sovereign even more than will the populace at large, and thus an obedient militia requires a leader who publicly exhibits exquisite selfcontrol, even if he or she privately lacks it. Similarly, leaders of monastic orders must exhibit a high degree of self-control in the sense of total submission to monastic principles, even if they privately lack it. Bryan Finken See also Ability; Aristotle; Capability; Control; Hierarchy; Machiavelli, Niccolò; Nietzsche, Friedrich; Power To and Power Over; Religious Power; Submissive; Subordination Discourse Further Readings Aristotle. (1984). Ethics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Machiavelli, N. (2005). The prince. (P. Bondanella, Trans.). New York: Oxford University Press. DISCOURSE The notion and analysis of discourse has gained increasing prominence within the social sciences. The linguistic turn that took place in the 1960s and 1970s reflected and spurred a growing scientific interest in the role of language beyond its function as a means of expression or representation. The structural linguistics of Ferdinand de Saussure showed how our use of language in daily interactions (parôle) is formed by underlying language structures (langue). The theory of speech acts advanced by John Austin claimed that the utterance of particular statements, under certain circumstances, can be seen as a way of acting and doing things. Following these lines of argument, it was increasingly recognized that language and social action are intertwined in what Ludwig Wittgenstein termed language games. Actions and language are interrelated in a multiplicity of ways, and our actions are meaningful and shaped by language-mediated conceptions of ourselves and the world we live in. In the 1980s, the linguistic turn was further deepened by poststructuralist theories emphasizing the constitutive role of incompletely structured systems of signs, psychoanalytic theories claiming that the unconscious is structured like a language, and post-Marxist theories interested in the ways power and domination are exercised and sustained through ideological discourse. The underlying assumption of the new theories of discourse is that meaning and identity are not determined by an underlying essence such as God, reason, human nature, or the laws of capital accumulation. Rather, social meanings and political identities are constructed within discourses defined as more or less sedimented systems of rules, relations, and articulations that are shaped and reshaped in and through power struggles. Hence, it becomes important to analyze how particular discourses structure the 191 terrain of social and political action, how these discourses are created, and how they can be transformed. How, for instance, can it be that the NATO campaign in Kosovo was referred to as a “humanitarian intervention” rather than as “military aggression”? How can it be that “welfare” has increasingly been seen as a “problem” and an “expenditure” rather than as a “policy goal”? How can it be that social clients and psychiatric patients tend to be conceived as “self-responsible citizens in need of empowerment” rather than as “objects of paternalistic governance and therapeutic treatment”? Discourse analysis aims to answer these sorts of questions. The analysis of discourse reveals a “fourth face of power” added to the three faces of power identified by Steven Lukes. Hence, power is not merely exercised by strong and resourceful actors who are capable of prevailing in an open conflict, suppressing conflicts by controlling the political agenda, or manipulating the other actors’ perceptions of their interests so as to avoid conflicts altogether. There is also a structural power that cannot be led back to a conscious, willful, and self-interested actor. Rather than being masterminded by strategic actors, structural power defines how the actors perceive themselves, each other, and the entire terrain in which they are operating. Structural power defines the conceptual framework, the rules of the game, and the identity of the actors, but that does not mean that the actors are reduced to passive bearers of the discursive structure. The structural, or discursive, notion of power does not eliminate autonomous agency. In contrast, the notion of power aims to mobilize the free action of social and political actors within a discursive framework that shapes their action in certain ways and thereby ensures conformity. The Latinate root of discourse refers to the practice of running here and there (dis “in different directions” and currere “to run”). That is precisely what we do in conversation, dissertation, and textual practices, which today constitute the common meaning of discourse. We cover a certain ground, topic, or issue by moving back and forth and combining old and new contents and expressions. We cover the world with text. In linguistics, discourse is defined as a textual fragment larger than the sentence. But as a result of Louis Hjelmslev’s and Roland Barthes’ formalization of structural linguistic, which purged it of 192 Discourse all reference to phonetic or semantic substance, everything from military parades and TV commercials to political demonstrations and public administration reforms can be analyzed in terms of the construction of particular discursive forms. The expansion of the notion of discourse to include all kinds of social practices led to a growing appreciation of the formative role of power and politics. For whereas specific language systems tend to be quite stable over time because the individual speakers have no interest in changing the meaning of words, the broader discursive systems of language-mediated practice will be subject to ruptures and transformations caused by political conflicts and struggles. Theories of Discourse Discourse theory developed as a cross-disciplinary attempt to combine and integrate central insights from linguistics and psychology with central insights from social and political science. Hence, there were linguists and psychologists who aimed to analyze the social causes and impact of a particular language usage and there were social and political scientists who sought to analyze how language was used to create ideological misrepresentations of social reality. The first group of linguistic discourse analysts includes different kinds of sociolinguistics, content analysis, conversation analysis, and discourse psychology. Sociolinguistics analyzes the relation between our socioeconomic status and our vocabulary and linguistic code. Content analysis analyzes our usage of particular words, word classes, and word combinations in order to identify particular patterns. Conversation analysis focuses on the organization of linguistic interaction in formal or informal settings. Finally, discourse psychology analyzes the strategies of the speakers and how they aim to achieve particular objectives by producing a shift in the framing of the conversation and in the style in which it is deployed. Although they clearly offer fruitful tools for analyzing spoken and written language, the linguistic theories of discourse generally fail to relate the linguistic analysis to questions about politics, ideology, and power. The second group of critical linguists and Marxist ideology theorists depart from linguistic discourse analysis by claiming that language cannot be analyzed independently of its social and political function. The analytical focus is on how discourse, through its combination of different concepts, phrases, and images, produces a particular representation of social reality. The aim is to show how language is used to produce ideological misrepresentations that help sustain the power of the ruling elite. However, despite the explicit attempt to ground the critique of ideology in a linguistic analysis of concrete discourses (newspaper articles, political speeches, etc.), the attempt of the critical linguists and ideology theorists to develop a theory of discourse failed because it remained trapped within a Marxist theory of ideology that presupposed a privileged access to the objective reality that is hidden by ideological misrepresentations. Critical Discourse Analysis Critical discourse analysis (CDA), as developed most consistently by Norman Fairclough, is far more successful than its predecessors in balancing linguistic analysis with the analysis of power and ideology. CDA expands the notion of discourse to include all linguistically mediated practices. Social practice is discursive insofar as it contributes to a semiotic production or interpretation of text. Discursive practices are ideological to the extent that they contain linguistic expressions that we take for granted and that, therefore, contribute to naturalizing social relations. Social and political actors use ideological discourse to sustain their own power or to challenge the hegemonic power of other actors. Hence, ideological discourse plays a key role in maintaining and transforming societal relations of power. However, whereas CDA clearly demonstrates the power effects of discourse, it remains unclear how we should understand the relation between discursive practices and the nondiscursive context. Actually, there is a tendency to reduce discourse to a linguistic mediation of causal powers embedded in socioeconomic structures. This significantly reduces the explanatory power of discourse analysis. Foucault The distinction between the discursive and the nondiscursive comes from the early works of the French philosopher Michel Foucault. However, Discourse Foucault advances a theory of discourse that is quite different from the one developed by CDA. Whereas CDA defines discourse as an empirical collection of social practices with a semiotic content, Foucault defines discourse as the conditions of possibility for producing particular statements. As such, Foucault does not focus on the form and content of particular utterances, but rather on the rules of formation guiding and regulating the production of statements. His archaeological analysis aims to reveal the discursive rules that regulate what we can talk about; from which position we can talk about it; which concepts we can use when talking; and which strategies, in terms of themes and theories, it is possible to advance in a particular discursive context. Foucault later modified this quasi-structuralist approach, when, as a part of his genealogical analysis, he insisted on viewing the sedimented forms of discourse as both a medium and outcome of a myriad of power struggles that take place at all levels of society. To account for how discourses are produced in and through power, Foucault developed a new notion of discursive power that transgresses the classical sovereignjuridical notion of power epitomized by Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan. Power is not exercised by a centralized authority that represses the subjects by means of laws, juridical sanctions, prohibitions, and taboos. Rather, power is exercised through a decentered network of mobile forces that aim to produce particular meanings, identities, and forms of knowledge. Laclau and Mouffe Foucault’s works are one of the main sources of inspiration for Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe in their development of a post-Marxist and poststructuralist theory of discourse. Laclau and Mouffe agree with Foucault’s insistence on the internal relation between discourse and power, and they adopt Foucault’s quasi-transcendental approach to the analysis of discourse. Discourse is defined as a relational totality of signifying sequences that provides the conditions of emergence for any meaningful object. Hence, like Kantian transcendentalism, discourse analysis focuses on the conditions of possibility for our perceptions, utterances, and social actions rather than on the factual immediacy or hidden meaning of social 193 phenomena. However, there are two important differences between classical transcendentalism and poststructuralist discourse theory. The first difference is that discourse theory does not conceive the conditions of possibility as ahistorical and universal, but emphasizes their historical variability and the impossibility of completely separating the conditions of possibility from what they make possible. The second difference is that discourse theory does not locate the conditions of possibility in a subjective mind, but rather sees them as a part of an incomplete discursive structure that is constantly destabilized by empirical events and political struggles. Laclau and Mouffe take issue with, and finally abandon, Foucault’s distinction between the discursive and the nondiscursive. The distinction is theoretically unsustainable because it can be shown that all the examples of apparently nondiscursive phenomena—such as institutions, architecture, techniques, production organization, and so on— are differential orders and therefore discursive. The distinction between the discursive and the nondiscursive only occurs in Foucault’s earlier work. But it is a very unfortunate distinction because it has permitted discourse theorists with a Marxist origin to reduce discourse to a regional instance of ideological articulation, which is somehow determined by extra-discursive structures. This possibility is eliminated by Laclau and Mouffe, who argue that discourse, ultimately, is coextensive with the social. All social relations are discursive and all discursive relations are power relations. The assertion of the discursive character of the social does not—as some might believe—dispense with the realist claim concerning the independent existence of a world external to our thoughts, consciousness, and language. However, the only way we can have access to this existing matter is by articulating it as a meaningful object with a particular discourse. Matter can be constructed in different ways within different discursive systems and the discursive construction of its being will not put its existence into question. For example, the head scarf of a young Turkish girl might be constructed as a symbol of religious faith, a fashion product, or a sign of rebellion against her secularized parents. No matter how the particular textile is constructed, it is still the same physical object. 194 Discourse Derrida, Lacan, and Žižek Laclau and Mouffe combine and synthesize insights from Foucault’s power analytics with insights from Jacques Derrida and Jacques Lacan. Derrida’s deconstruction of the notion of centered and totalizing structures leads us straight to the notion of discourse. The classical notion of structures depicts a complex totality in which meaning and identity are determined by a privileged center. As Derrida shows, however, the idea of a determining center is contradictorily coherent because it assumes that the center structures the entire structure while escaping any kind of structuration. By giving up the idea of a determining center, which is given in its full presence beyond the reach of the play of meaning, the process of signification extends almost infinitely. In this situation, everything becomes discourse in the sense of being constituted within relational ensembles of signifying sequences that in the absence of an ultimate center are structured by a multiplicity of mutually substituting centers that fail to invoke a totalizing closure. Meaning and identity are partially fixed within discourses that tend to construct a binary textual hierarchy between a privileged inside and an inferior and threatening outside. The binary hierarchies are results of decisions taken in an undecidable terrain in which the constant oscillation between determinate options cannot be arrested by any pregiven rule or rationality, but requires a constitutive, contingent, and political intervention that tends to realize one particular option at the expense of other options. There might be good reasons for choosing this option, but it is impossible to provide an ultimate ground for the decision, which will always be marked by a certain undecidability. The undecidable character of the social meaning and identity is revealed by deconstruction that shows that the inferior outside of a privileged essence is constitutive of the inside. For example, it can be demonstrated that the celebrated reign of the free market requires heavy state intervention to create and sustain a more or less free market. Whereas Derrida’s works can help us understand the contingent construction of discourse, Slavoj Žižek’s version of Lacanian psychoanalytic theory can help us understand the discursive construction of subjectivity. The subject is internal to the discursive structures, but it should not be reduced to a decentered assemblage of relatively fixed subject positions whereby the subject is hailed as a “woman,” “immigrant,” “consumer” and “student.” Žižek urges us to account for the subject before its subjectivation. The subject aims to find a way of representing itself within the symbolic structure of discourse. However, the symbolic structure is constantly disrupted by the real, which is defined as the traumatic kernel of social life that resists symbolization. The disruption of the symbolic order prevents the reduction of the subject to yet another structural position within a particular discourse. The subject emerges as a split subject in the cracks and fissures of the incomplete structure. As such, the subject has neither a fully achieved structural identity nor a complete lack of identity, but rather has a failed structural identity. In this situation, the split subject can either lapse into paralyzing self-denial or attempt to reinvent himself or herself by establishing an illusionary full identity in and through acts of identification. Hence, instead of giving in to a self-destructive alcoholism, an unemployed party functionary from the former Soviet Union may find comfort, and the promise of a new order and a fully achieved identity, by means of identifying with the Orthodox Church, Russian Nationalism, or some other populist cause. Viewed through this analytical lens, identity is not the cause of the subject’s political identifications, but rather the result of the split subject’s identification with an available and credible political imaginary. Social and political imaginaries are structured around tendentially empty signifiers such as progress, modernization, freedom, the people, and so on, which because of their conceptual vagueness and ambiguity are capable of representing different political identities that have become unified by their common experience of being negated by disruptive events or enemy forces. The Role of Hegemony, Social Antagonism, and Dislocation Discourses are relational systems of meaning and identity. According to Laclau and Mouffe, social identities can be linked either through relations of difference or through relations of equivalence. The differential construction of identity stresses the difference between a particular identity and other identities, whereas as the equivalential construction of identity emphasizes the “sameness” of different Discourse identities that can be constructed through either metonymy or metaphor. Sometimes the differential logic prevails as in the modern welfare state that constructs different social, political, and economic groups as legitimate differences within an organic whole. This contrasts with other situations such as wars, revolutions, and big political upheavals where the social and political space tends to become divided into two opposed camps and there is no place for a middle ground. Discourses tend to become unified by nodal points that are defined as tendentially empty signifiers that are not attached to a particular signified and, therefore, can function to construct a knot of meaning that partially fixes the meaning of different floating signifiers that are proliferating in the wake of disruption and crisis. For example, floating signifiers such as regulation, competitiveness, and state might be partially fixed by being referred to the master signifier of globalization that tends to reformulate regulation in terms of liberalization and market regulation, competitiveness in terms of structural competitiveness, and the state in terms of a facilitating state that aims to govern selforganizing actors and networks. Discourse is a result of articulation that is defined as a practice that establishes an internal relation among dissimilar elements such that their identities are mutually modified. When, for example, liberalism became articulated with democracy, the result was that the liberal state was democratized and democracy was restricted to the public sphere, thus exempting the capitalist economy and the patriarchal family, which were both located in the private sphere, from the democratic demands for equality. Articulations that involve the production of political frontiers between friends and enemies are defined as hegemonic articulations. Hegemony is an articulatory practice that aims to construct a political as well as moral intellectual leadership and thus engages in the struggle for our hearts and minds. According to Antonio Gramsci, a hegemonic force must transgress its own narrowly defined interest and construct a collective will with a national and popular character. Vladimir Lenin saw hegemony as merely the working class’s political leadership of a tactical alliance of workers, soldiers, and peasants. The social classes should strike together, but march separately. By contrast, Gramsci claimed that the social classes 195 must develop a common political project that blurs and modifies the original class interests. The hegemonic force must articulate a variety of interests and demands in a collective will that provides a particular reading of the sociopolitical problems and offers a way of solving them in accordance with cherished norms and values. Gramsci’s attempt to transgress the class reductionist scheme of Marxism is hampered by his insistence that only the fundamental classes—that is, the proletariat and the bourgeoisie—are capable of exercising hegemony. This economistic attempt to anchor the contingent logic of hegemonic articulation in the economic structures is abandoned by Laclau and Mouffe, who insist that the economy is an institutionalized discursive terrain that is crisscrossed by political struggles and power strategies. Foucault has convincingly demonstrated that the limits and unity of a hegemonic discourse cannot be constituted with reference to its style, vocabulary, or objects that are often shared with other discourses. Neither can it be constituted in relation to an external element that is different from the moments within the discourse because in that case the outside is reduced to being simply one more difference within the discourse. Therefore, the construction of the limits and unity of a hegemonic discourse must involve the construction of a constitutive outside that has no common measure with the discourse in question, but poses a threat to its differential order. The construction of a radical and threatening otherness is a result of the exclusion of discursive elements that are articulated in a chain of equivalence that collapses their differential character. The chain of equivalence emphasizes the “sameness” of the excluded elements. But as the number of elements expands, it becomes clear that the only thing they have in common is that they constitute a threat to the discursive order from which they are excluded. The unification and delimitation of a hegemonic discourse through the construction of a radical and threatening outside is captured by Laclau and Mouffe’s notion of social antagonism. Social antagonism is neither a “real opposition” where one physical object clashes with another object; nor is it a “logical opposition” in which A is contradicted by non-A. Rather, in both cases, A remains fully A, whereas in social antagonism A is negated by antiA. In other words, social antagonism unifies a 196 Dispositif hegemonic discourse by constructing an external enemy that prevents the closure of the discursive system. A hegemonic discourse that is unified by a social antagonism separating the discursive system from its constitutive and threatening outside can be very stable over time because it might be able to integrate new events by turning them into legitimate discursive differences. But precisely because discourses only manage to produce a partial fixation of meaning and identity, they are bound to come up against events that they fail to inscribe in their symbolic order. The failure to integrate, domesticate, and inscribe new and emerging events will lead to a complete or partial breakdown of the discursive system and the proliferation of floating signifiers. Thus, when faced with the unrepresentable kernel of social life, the finite and contingent discourses are dislocated. A good example of dislocation is the stagflation crisis that hit most of the Western economies in the beginning of the 1970s. The so-called Keynesian doctrines of economic crisis management were dislocated by the joint occurrence of rising unemployment and mounting inflation. Dislocation reveals the undecidability of the social and opens a political terrain for hegemonic struggles about how to heal the rift in the dislocated structure. As such, dislocation is the condition of possibility for articulation, hegemony, and political transformation. Discourse is formed by hegemonic articulations, unified by social antagonisms, and transformed by political interventions facilitated by structural dislocation. The attempt to suture a dislocated discourse by advancing a new hegemonic project will always involve some kind of ideological totalization. Ideology does not hide or misrepresent an objective social reality because social reality is always already constructed in and through discourse. Rather, what ideology systematically hides and misrecognizes is the precarious and contingent character of social meaning and identity that is rooted in the ultimate undecidability of the social. Ideology is a totalizing gesture within hegemonic discourses that aims to present the discursively constructed meanings and identities as natural, objective, and given and denies the presence of a constitutive outside. As such, ideology aims to efface the traces of power from the social fabric. Ideology constructs myths that function as simplifying reading principles that aim to make a complex, chaotic, and dislocated terrain intelligible. Ideological myths are sometimes transformed into social imaginaries that provide a totalizing horizon that permits a limitless inscription of social and political demands into the promise of a new order. In this sense, the Enlightenment, the communist dream of a classless society, and the welfare state project can all be seen as examples of social imaginaries, whereas neoliberalism, the Third Way project, and right-wing populism can be seen as myths aspiring to become social imaginaries. The power of ideological totalization derives from the fact that we do not necessarily abandon the myths and social imaginaries that we ascribe to when their totalizing and reductive ploys are revealed. We are often prepared to “act as if” the totalizing ideological fantasy provides an adequate account of the social world—not because it is rational to do so, but because it gives us a certain enjoyment to mask the failure of ideological totalization. We are freed from facing the undecidable and antagonistic character of the social, and we are permitted to displace our self-blockage to an imaginary enemy who is held responsible for the corruption of the social. As such, the enjoyment attached to ideological fantasy explains the strong grip of ideology and, therefore, why it is so difficult to escape the structural power of discourse. Jacob Torfing See also Foucault, Michel; Gramsci, Antonio; Hegemonic Power; Hegemony; Ideology; Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal; Lukes, Steven; Three Faces of Power Further Readings Fairclough, N. (1995). Critical discourse analysis. London: Longman. Laclau, E. (1993). Discourse. In R. E. Goodin & P. Petitt (Eds.), Contemporary political philosophy (pp. 431–437). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Torfing, J. (1999). New theories of discourse. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. DISPOSITIF Apparatus, dispositif, and machine are three terms that figure significantly in French theorizations of Distributive Justice different forms of power. In English, apparatus (derived from Latin) translates as both appareil (apparatus, machine, device, camera) and dispositif (arrangement, disposition, device, or apparatus). The notion of state apparatus (or appareil d’état) is especially associated with Louis Althusser, a French structural Marxist, and his followers. Dispositif was first used in the study of the cinema but for present purposes is more often associated with Michel Foucault’s analyses of power/knowledge relations. Machine is a broader term with many connotations, ranging from the machinery of state power to the desiring machine. The term has a key, albeit often loosely metaphorical, role in the work of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, such as their 1972 work Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism et Schizophrenia. In Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses, Althusser supplements Karl Marx’s theory by identifying the state’s key ideological as well as repressive functions in reproducing class domination. He distinguished a relatively unified repressive state apparatus (RSA) from a plurality of relatively autonomous ideological state apparatuses (ISAs). Although the former comprises the core of the state (executive, legislature, judiciary, and police– military apparatus), the ISAs include diverse institutions such as the family, education, organized religion, and the media. RSAs and ISAs operate in different ways to secure class power and social cohesion. Although the RSA relies more on coercion, it has an important ideological moment, and, although ISAs rely more on ideology, coercion remains in the background. Subsequent work has explored the changing articulation of the RSA and ISAs in different kinds of political systems, whether “normal” bourgeois democratic regimes or exceptional regimes such as military dictatorships, fascism, developmental states, or new forms of authoritarian rule (see, for example, Nicos Poulantzas’s 1972 work, Fascism and Dictatorship). Foucault introduced dispositif in an interview after Surveiller et punir (translated as Discipline and Punish) appeared in 1975; it also figured in The History of Sexuality, Volume 1 (1976) and, more prominently, in his studies of governmentality between 1976 and 1979. His most elaborate account presented dispositif as a general network or web of relations among a “thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble” of linguistic and nonlinguistic 197 relations, discourses and institutions, architectural forms, scientific statements, philosophical and moral propositions, and so forth. More important for Foucault than a given dispositif’s individual elements were (a) how their articulation in games of power, knowledge, and truth served strategic functions in addressing an urgent need; and (b) how the dispositif produced appropriate subjects for specific types of power/knowledge relations. In their very different ways, the arguments of these leading French scholars have influenced studies of power across many disciplines and regarding the most varied topics. The main theoretical and methodological interest in apparatus, dispositif, and machine concerns how relatively heterogeneous elements are combined to generate specific strategic effects in power relations across different sites and scales. Bob Jessop See also Althusser, Louis; Foucault, Michel; Marx, Karl; Postmodernist View of Power in International Relations Further Readings Althusser, L. (1971). Lenin and philosophy and other essays. London: Verso. Foucault, M. (1980). The confession of the flesh. In Power/knowledge (C. Gordon, Ed. & Trans., pp. 194–228). New York: Pantheon. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE Justice is often taken to hold over two domains: the distributive and the corrective. The latter is concerned with questions of punishment and rectifications of injustices. The former concerns the just distribution of the benefits and (nonpunitive) burdens of social life. These include civil and political rights as well as income, wealth, health care, and so on. Debates about distributive justice are critical to contemporary politics. In this entry, we consider arguments that justice requires promoting welfare; an equal distribution of holdings; a distribution that benefits the worst off; and a distribution that merely respects the rights of property holders. Finally, we ask whether justice 198 Distributive Justice should have the central place accorded it in contemporary political thinking. Justice is a matter of each person receiving what is due to him or her. In the liberal tradition, this ties it closely to the formal idea of equality that requires that things that are relevantly alike should be treated alike. In the absence of relevant differences between people, justice requires that each be treated as an equal. Of course, without an account of “relevant differences” and of what it is to be “treated as an equal,” this does not tell us very much. Indeed, one way to characterize many of the debates in distributive justice is as being about the characteristics or properties that might count in distinguishing persons and over the meaning of the demand to treat persons as equals. These debates have tended to focus on the distribution of income, wealth, and the goods of economic activity generally (and that will be the focus here). In the matter of civil and political rights, there is a broad consensus that has held since the end of World War II that there are no relevant differences between sane, adult, citizens and that each is entitled to an equal share of such rights in recognition of his or her status as a citizen (although even here there are debates about the scope of justice—whether it applies only to citizens, or to everyone, or to everyone in a territory including migrants and children, etc.; this entry will not consider these questions). Utilitarian Theories of Justice Perhaps the most obvious way to justify some or other distribution of goods—or to justify principles that ought to govern the institutions that together determine that distribution—is by reference to whether what results advances the overall or average welfare of those affected by it. This is the case made by utilitarians who hold that the right principles of distributive justice are those that will bring about greatest future utility (i.e., the greatest future good for persons, however that is defined). This means that the right content of the principles of justice is an empirical matter. Although most utilitarians agree that having equal civil and political rights will maximize utility, there is no similar agreement on the economic arrangements (socialist, capitalist, mixed, etc.) that will achieve that goal. Although utilitarian theories are attractively simple and appeal to an intuitively plausible criterion for thinking about just institutions (surely one consideration in thinking about the institutions we have ought to be their consequences for human welfare?), they are widely criticized for failing to respect the rights of persons. Consider, for example, a distribution in which some have an abundance of goods and others are kept in abject misery and yet which is utility maximizing (the utility gained by the rich being greater than the disutility suffered by the poor). According to utilitarianism, this is acceptable, and it is just. Utilitarians commonly reply to this objection that in “the real world” scenarios such as this one are very unlikely to occur. As noted, this is also the account they give of the egalitarian distribution of civil and political rights (in the real world, distributing these rights equally is utility maximizing). As an empirical matter, the utilitarian claim can be disputed, but even if it is granted, it seems to deliver the right answers for the wrong reasons. We think that adult sane citizens have equal rights as a reflection of their equal standing, not because giving them those rights equally has good consequences. Egalitarian Theories of Justice The principle that governs the distribution of civil and political rights, then, is one of strict egalitarianism. The goods in question are allocated equally to (almost) all members of society on the basis that that everyone is owed equal respect and that an equal distribution of these goods best reflects this ideal. This raises the question of why we do not simply extend the same principle of strict egalitarianism to other (economic) goods? The idea of a strict egalitarian distribution of all benefits and burdens of social cooperation can be criticized on both theoretical and technical grounds. Those who press theoretical objections contrast the case of civil and political rights with economic entitlements. When it comes to the former, all adult sane citizens are relevantly alike and an equal distribution of these rights reflects their equal status. However, when it comes to economic goods, some critics of egalitarianism claim that citizens are not all relevantly alike. For example, some are talented and hardworking and thus more deserving. Other critics argue that an inegalitarian distribution Distributive Justice could make everyone better off, and so egalitarianism is inefficient. Finally, others argue that maintaining an equal set of holdings would involve continuous interference in the freedom that citizens have to transfer their goods to one another in gifts or exchanges. The most pressing technical problem with (although not limited to) strict egalitarianism is that it needs to specify what it is that ought to be distributed equally to treat citizens as equals. One answer is to distribute resources equally. However, different people will gain very different levels of benefit from similar bundles of resources and the outcome in terms of welfare of an egalitarian distribution of resources may be very inegalitarian (e.g., a disabled person may need considerably more resources than would an able-bodied person to derive similar levels of satisfaction from life). Justice as Fairness The most famous contemporary attempt to respond to these problems—and the theory of distributive justice that has become the starting point for all recent discussions of the topic—is found in John Rawls’s idea of justice as fairness. Rawls accepts the criticism advanced against strict egalitarianism that everyone can be materially better off if incomes are not maintained at a strictly equal level (a criticism that reflects the experience of industrialized countries during the last few centuries: the wealth of an economy is not fixed and the most common way of producing more wealth is a system that rewards the more productive with greater incomes). In addition, he sees the need to provide an “index” of goods to be distributed. He argues that persons in an original position—a social contract—would agree to a distribution of primary social goods (including civil and political rights and income and wealth) governed by two principles of justice that must be satisfied in turn. The first principle requires strict equality in civil and political rights. The second principle specifies, first, that social and economic inequalities must be attached to positions that are open to all under fair equality of opportunity and, second (in what is called the difference principle), that any social and economic inequalities must be to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged. This deviation from strict equality in holdings is justifiable as long as 199 the inequality results in the least well off being better off than they would be under strict equality. Advocates of desert-based principles argue that the difference principle ignores claims that people deserve economic benefits given their contribution to social products and the effort they expend in their work. For the desert theorist, distributive systems are just insofar as they distribute incomes according to the different levels earned or deserved by the individuals for their productive efforts or contributions in that society. It may be objected that desert-based theories require extremely difficult measures to isolate contribution and effort, particularly in a complex economy. Moreover, they make economic benefits dependent on factors over which people have little or no control—for example, someone may be more or less productive depending on inherited talents or because his or her particular skills are in great demand given other people’s tastes. Responsibility-Sensitive Egalitarian Principles So-called responsibility-sensitive egalitarian principles inhabit a middle ground between these two positions. Theorists regard the difference principle as flawed because it is insufficiently “ambitionsensitive” (because it does not ensure people live with the consequences of their free choices) but they also emphasize the necessity of “endowmentinsensitivity” (that people’s holdings should not be determined by [dis]advantageous natural abilities or brute bad luck). Thus, rather than a distribution governed by the difference principle, responsibility-sensitive egalitarians argue for a principle that people should be entitled to the outcomes (good and bad) of their choices, but should be compensated for the operations of luck. Responsibility-sensitive egalitarianism has generated a great deal of discussion. Those who favor it think that it incorporates the idea of deserts into traditional egalitarianism. Critics, though, argue that how responsibility-sensitive egalitarianism could actually be implemented in a real economy is unclear because a distinction between natural and developed talents would be difficult, if not impossible, to identify. Others think that it has deflected traditional egalitarianism away from its core concern with the plight of 200 Distributive Justice the disadvantaged and the effects of relative inequalities in societies. Libertarian Theories For all their differences, what all the theories considered so far have in common is that they conceive of a just distribution as being one that fits some pattern (a pattern in which utility is maximized, the worst off are as well off as possible, or people have the results of their choices and not the results of luck). Libertarians characteristically object to any patterned distributive ideal, regardless of whether material goods or welfare are at stake. The basis of the objection is as follows. Surely, they argue, the point of giving people holdings (income, wealth, etc.) is to allow those people to use their holdings as they see fit in living their lives. Thus, given some initial just set of holdings, people will freely trade, bargain, bet, transfer, and so on, with one another. The result of all this freedom will be to upset the pattern. Yet, if the initial holdings were just, and people freely interacted with one another (no one stole from, or coerced, another), then how can the result be unjust? Thus, the only way that the pattern can be restored is by an illegitimate use of state power in violation of people’s freedoms. Thus, rather than developing some pattern theory of distributive justice, libertarians favor rules that establish and protect the rights of individuals (particularly rights of property in their own person and in things justly acquired). Whatever then results from the use of those rights is just, and interference by the state (e.g., in the form of redistributive taxation) is unjust. Critics of the libertarian position have typically focused on three difficulties the theory faces. First, it is not clear how one gives an account of, let alone establishes, a set of just initial holdings. To whom, for example, does the land of the United States belong: to the descendents (however that is to be established) of those who first found it; of those who first colonized and farmed—made use of—it; or of those who purchased it from Native American tribes? Second, the argument depends on the idea that injustice cannot arise from the accumulation of many individual, isolated acts, each of which is just. But there is no reason to think that. Finally, the theory depends on citizens being granted property rights, and being granted such rights absolutely. However, we can surely believe that we have a conditional right to, say, our monthly salaries. The condition being precisely that those salaries can be subject to just taxation. The foregoing discussion has proceeded on the basis that justice is not merely one virtue among others, but that it is the most important virtue of social institutions. Some or other distribution might be more efficient, more benevolent, more likely to promote artistic endeavor (or whatever), but these things do not matter in the face of the charge that they are unjust. The Theories Critiqued This view has been challenged. In a less radical form, some feminists argue that liberal theories of distributive justice are blind to the oppression that occurs in the private sphere. Enduring inequalities for women arise especially because women often have primary responsibility for child rearing and, as a result, retain substantial disadvantages when competing in the market. As a consequence, feminists argue, all theories that rely on market mechanisms will yield a distribution of wealth in which women will systematically have less income and wealth than men. This is a less radical challenge in that it offers a critique of the traditional liberal boundaries of political authority, but in the name of securing a just distributive outcome. The more radical version of the critique requires that justice itself is displaced as the core virtue of distributive schemes. For some feminists and communitarians, justice “colonizes” spheres in which it has no place—destroying valuable social relationships that are maintained by friendship, love, care, or fraternity. Theorists of justice might agree, at least in the sense that they think that certain circumstances make justice necessary. These circumstances include moderate scarcity and the conflicting demands of persons for their “fair share.” The response of those who would favor justice, then, is that the absence of care and community is precisely what makes justice so important. Matt Matravers and Alex Bavister-Gould See also Democracy; Fair Division; Freedom; Liberalism Domhoff, G. William Further Readings Barry, B. (1995). A treatise on social Justice: Vol. 2. Justice as impartiality. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Goodin, R. (1995). Utilitarianism as a public philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Kymlicka, W. (2002). Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. DOMAIN The domain of power or influence refers to the persons whose policies are affected. When power is exercised, it must be with respect to some person or group. The person or group affected is the domain of power. In potential power relationships, the domain refers to those persons potentially affected. The term domain was introduced by Harold Lasswell and Abraham Kaplan in Power and Society to specify one of the basic dimensions of power. The other two dimensions were weight and scope. Weight refers to the amount of power or the degree to which the policies of others are affected. Scope refers to the kinds of policies affected. Robert Dahl has also emphasized the importance of specifying scope and domain in specifying a power relationship. The observation that a person has a lot of power may not be meaningless, but it is not very meaningful. It begs the questions of “With respect to whom?” and “With respect to which issues?” Thus, specification of domain and scope is important for clear communication. Specifying domain and scope also has important implications for the measurement of power. If the power of an actor varies with respect to different scopes and domains, it is difficult to determine an actor’s total power. A sea captain may have a great deal of power with respect to the members of his or her crew and passengers but very little power with respect to other people. A powerful legislator 201 may have much power with respect to how his or her fellow legislators vote but very little power with respect to whom they marry, how many children they have, what they eat, or where they take their vacations. Although one might say that someone who has power with respect to a large number of people has more power than does someone who has power over a small number of people, one might not want to do so. It could be argued that power over a large number of weak people constitutes less power than power over a small number of very powerful people. Variations in the scope and domain of power do not make it impossible to measure the total power of and actor or to compare the power of actors, but they do make it difficult to do so. David A. Baldwin See also Capability; Community Power Debate; Dahl, Robert A.; Domination; Hegemony; Influence; Lasswell, Harold; Power Indices; Scope; Social Power Further Readings Dahl, R. A., & Stinebrickner, B. (2003). Modern political analysis (6th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Lasswell, H. D., & Kaplan, A. (1950). Power and society: A framework for political inquiry. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. DOMHOFF, G. WILLIAM (1936– ) G. William Domhoff is a research professor in psychology and sociology at the University of California, Santa Cruz. He has published many books and articles dealing with the power structure in the United States. A leading power elitist and neo-Marxist analyst of power, he has been highly influential in urban studies and sociological studies of power in the United States. His first best-selling book, Who Rules America? (published in 1967), is a detailed description and analysis of the links between political elites in business, politics, and the military in the United States. Five further editions under the title Who Rules America Now? were published between 1983 and 202 Dominant Parties 2009, updating the list of elites and their links. The argument of the books is that class and corporate finance dominate U.S. politics, though Domhoff also offers some hope that activists can operate within a democracy to break the class structure and offer a better future. Domhoff argues that the structure of U.S. society is dominated by class and capitalism. The neoMarxist line is that the structure of capitalist society provides easier access for businesspeople into the political system, but he is not a determinist in any sense. Rather, he sees the power structure operating through personal and social networks that enable the elite to dominate. He does see these elites as competing, largely through the two-party system, but at the end of the day that struggle is simply for which circles will dominate U.S. politics, and not for any distributional struggle that will benefit the U.S. people as a whole. Domhoff argues that although the democratic system allows ordinary people to have a route into the political process, access is much easier for the wealthy. The relative costs of taking part in politics are lower and they have links through personal networks. He believes that the facts of class domination are overshadowed in most academic writing because analysts concentrate far too much on institutional processes and do not examine outcomes to the extent they should. That the outcomes benefit the rich so much demonstrates their domination. In 1978, Domhoff published Who Really Rules?, a reexamination of the materials that Robert Dahl and his associates collected in writing their classic Who Governs? Here Domhoff argues that, rather than supporting a pluralist view of power in New Haven, Connecticut, Dahl and his associates had actually collected material demonstrating elite dominance. Domhoff has also been closely associated with the growth machine or growth coalition argument that urban politics is dominated by development and that development is skewed toward exchangevalue rather than use-value and, hence, benefits capitalists rather than local people. Keith Dowding See also Dahl, Robert A.; Elite Theories; Growth Coalitions; Marxist Accounts of Power; Pluralism Further Readings Domhoff, G. W. (1990). The power elite and the state: How policy is made in America. New York: Aldine de Gruyter. Domhoff, G. W. (2010). Who rules America? Boston: McGraw-Hill. DOMINANT PARTIES Parties are considered dominant if they achieve electoral dominance both vertically and horizontally. Vertical electoral dominance is achieved when a party surpasses a threshold of vote or seat shares. In the literature, the demarcation of this threshold varies from a majority of at least 40% to 70% of raw votes or lower-house seats. Horizontal electoral dominance requires such a majority to be sustained longitudinally—usually over a generation. For example, Italy’s Christian Democratic Party, an archetypal dominant party, controlled the parliamentary executive for 36 years (1945–1981). Dominant parties often amount to an infraction on the “alternation rule” that requires meaningful democracies to have regular and intermittent exchanges of power between major political parties. As such, dominant parties emerge frequently in so-called partial democracies where electoral competition is ostensibly open but less than fair. A number of obvious explanations account for the rise and persistence of dominant parties in illiberal democracies: electoral fraud, corruption, oligopoly, control by the dominant party of public finances and its usurpation of the national mythology, or a submissive attitude to authority among citizens. In advanced democracies, however, the emergence of dominant parties is perplexing. By definition, a healthy democracy should contain a vigorous culture of opposition politics. Moreover, the dominant party phenomenon hardly squares with studies in organizational behavior that illustrate how these kinds of bodies should be particularly arthritic in adapting to change over time. Hence, a robust understanding of the emergence, persistence, and breakdown of dominant party systems depends on advances in the theory of political competition. Attempts to explain dominant-party systems have focused on either the demand side of the problem by studying electoral behavior, the Domination supply side of the problem by examining party behavior, or by investigating the role of structure. Some approaches from electoral behavior argue that dominant parties are sustained either by a lack of social cleavages that would stimulate greater political competition or by the absence of voter dealignment from the dominant party. These approaches have found limited empirical corroboration. In cross-polity analysis, the number of political parties does not seem to correlate with social cleavages when political competition is measured against ethno-linguistic fractionalization. Meanwhile, dealignment explains little when one observes how negative retrospective voting often fails to translate into positive prospective voting for the opposition. Structural approaches have argued that the number of major competitors in a party system is shaped by institutional factors such as district magnitude or the choice of electoral formula. However, the explanatory power of this argument is weak because the collection of electoral systems within the population of dominant party systems is heterogeneous. Supply-side models have attempted to explain the number of competitors in a party system by calculating when it is rational for parties to be formed. Although such models have demonstrated high internal validity, they tend to assume a neutral political market, where parties enter with the same relative advantage and voter preferences are accurately distributed across a left–right spectrum. Other approaches have attempted to advance theories of party behavior via a more realistic account of the asymmetries in resources between opposition and incumbent parties. Single-party dominance may also be attributed to the shortcomings of opposition performance. Some suggest that dominant-party systems place centrifugal ideological pressure on opposition parties, framing them as antiestablishment, niche parties that subsequently fail to attract the support of the median voter. Adam Packer 203 Pempel, T. J. (Ed.). (1990). Uncommon democracies: The one-party dominant regimes. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. DOMINATION When we talk about power, often what we mean more specifically is domination. Domination refers to a situation where an agent exercises relatively stable, ongoing control over the actions of other agents (“agents” taken broadly to mean anything from individual persons, to social groups, to organizations and institutions). Domination is not episodic. Relations of domination are, by definition, firmly established, and often naturalized and taken for granted. Even specified to this degree, the concept of domination is used to cover a wide range of social relations. To unpack it further, we need to look at several key aspects of this idea. First, domination can be taken as a neutral description of certain kinds of relationships, but it also tends to have strongly negative evaluative connotations. For many, domination is by definition morally wrong. Second, paradigmatic understandings of domination often portray it as a process of which the dominated are unconscious, or only partially conscious. But domination can also be quite explicit and recognized by all involved. Third, the idea of domination shades into more general social processes of socialization that regulate human behavior, without being clearly authored by any dominant agent. This raises difficulties for defining the boundaries of domination. Fourth, the modern state, as potentially the most powerful form of social organization, is routinely involved in domination. Finally, although we primarily use the concept of domination to describe large-scale structural social relationships (e.g., between social classes), it also gets used regarding patterns of interpersonal interactions, indicating the scope of a concept ranging from macro- to microlevels of analysis. See also Core Parties; Democracy; Political Parties Further Readings Greene, K. F. (2007). Why dominant parties lose: Mexico’s democratization in comparative perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press. Descriptive Versus Normative Senses Of Domination It sounds strange to suggest that domination might be a normatively neutral concept, neither good nor bad. We tend to regard domination as implying 204 Domination harm and unjust treatment. But it can be argued that, to be useful for social analysis, a purely descriptive, normatively neutral concept is precisely what is needed. If relationships of domination are common features of our social landscape, then we need to be able to describe, analyze, and comparatively study these, dispassionately, before any normative evaluation of the relationships in question. Such a view seems to have informed one of the most influential figures on the social analysis of domination, the German sociologist Max Weber (1864–1920). Weber used the German word Herrschaft to identify relationships in which one actor can routinely expect his or her commands, whether explicit or implicit, to be obeyed, and even internalized as principles of action, by those they are directed at. Herrschaft has manifold connotations (domination, dominion, rule, authority, leadership) that are not easily translated into a single English word. Anglophone scholarship tends to vacillate between the terms domination and authority when translating from Weber, perhaps betraying ambivalence toward Weber’s normatively neutral use of Herrschaft. The key point is that for Weber, the influence of a charismatic teacher on his or her pupils, conventions of deference between tenants and landlords in agrarian societies, the ability of an established democratic government to rule, or the cultivation of widespread nationalist fervor by a dictator were all equally instances of domination (Herrschaft), phenomena of the same type, regardless of how we might morally judge them. In keeping with this principle, Weber described most forms of domination as “legitimate,” meaning not that they should be approved of, but that those subject to domination frequently found that situation justifiable on some grounds, and that this was basic to the operation of domination. Thus, Weber spoke of legitimate domination, a phrase that has an oxymoronic ring for most English speakers. This linking of domination and legitimacy leads many to prefer the translation “authority” for Herrschaft, because we think of authority as inherently involving legitimacy. Consciousness of Domination by the Dominated Many kinds of social relationships unambiguously exemplify domination. Slavery rests on slave owners having a legal right to command the actions of their slaves, and the knowledge that extreme force may be brought to bear on slaves who resist commands or the claim of ownership itself. Populations conquered in war are subjected to the rule of the victors, through military occupation and martial law. Prisoners live under the rigid regimes of their keepers. In all these cases, force and its threat overtly underwrite the claims to domination, tending to make the nature of the power relationship explicit for both sides. But even in these kinds of relationships, the dominated will sometimes accommodate themselves to their situation, regarding rights to dominate as legitimate, and personal conditions of subordination as natural. However, such unambiguous forms of domination, perhaps because they are so apparent, have not featured prominently in recent social scientific explorations of domination. Instead, the greatest attention is paid to those forms of domination that seem to operate beyond the awareness, or at least the full awareness, of the dominated. Domination is often thought to quintessentially involve the ideological manipulation and mystification of the dominated, not mere material subjugation. Thus, Pierre Bourdieu (1930–2002) elaborated the term habitus especially to describe the way class domination becomes encoded in different class-based sensibilities and criteria of “taste,” which are learned and embodied at a preconscious level, thus reinforcing the general class structure of a society. Another highly influential figure, Michel Foucault (1926–1984), argued that human subjectivity itself is a historical creation, shaped by wider societal patterns of power. For him, the modern period was characterized by the rise of institutions and practices (e.g., criminology, medicine, psychiatry) that make enforceable claims to superior knowledge, thereby compelling subjects to participate in selfunderstandings suitable to their domination by these institutions and practices. And Steven Lukes (b. 1941), in a celebrated critique of political analysis, argued that social power is not just a matter of how manifest conflicts of interest get decided, but also of how and why conflicts of interest remain latent, and unarticulated, and how the very desires, preferences, and motives of the less powerful get formed in the first instance to suit the interests of the dominant. In all these approaches, there is an emphasis on how domination intervenes Domination in the very formation of the self-understandings of the dominated. Acknowledging the insights of these approaches, we need to bear in mind that familiar modes of domination often fall in between the extremes of explicitness and implicitness outlined previously. For instance, in colonial contexts, one often finds complex and socially stratified attitudes toward the colonizers among the members of the colonized society, as some in the upper strata see opportunities in accommodating themselves to the values and mores of the colonizing society, whereas those further down, or embedded in social institutions marginalized by colonization, more often experience only the condition of subjugation. In assessing such intermediate cases, we must ask whether relations of domination are encoded in laws and backed by state-sanctioned force, versus more diffusely embedded in social institutions and attitudes. We also must appreciate that multiple modes of domination attached to ethnicity, race, class, gender (among others) can operate as a more complex interacting system of domination, reinforcing or eroding each other, according to specific circumstances. More generally what these observations suggest is that the awareness of domination by the dominated varies according to the degree of explicitness of the mode of domination, and within any societal relationship of domination, understandings of that relationship will vary between members of the dominated group. Domination Versus Socialization These observations raise another problem. To the degree we can define a relationship of domination between one individual or group and another, we can identify, at least theoretically, an axis of competing claims on the nature of that relationship and its legitimacy. But when we consider the individual’s relationship with the wider society and its demands on the individual, talk of domination becomes more problematic because societies are processes, not agents in any significant sense. The coordination of individual with group behavior though social conventions, norms, and values is in our nature. We are evolutionarily designed to have our behavior shaped and constrained by the larger social groups we are part of, through formal and informal processes of social learning beginning at 205 birth. In this sense, through socialization, societies exhibit a great deal of stable, ongoing control over their members, but no one is really doing the controlling. However, this is not to say that this wider process of socialization does not interact with processes of domination between social groups. Although there must be some forms of generalized social control, the actual forms they take are likely to be inflected by societal patterns of domination. Thus although it is natural to feel shame in the face of strong disapproval from peers, because one engages in behavior widely deemed inappropriate to one’s gender, or because one’s speech patterns betray working-class origins, this indicates a historically specific pattern of social relations, one that encodes aspects of domination. This congruence between necessary processes of socialization, and more contingent processes of domination, facilitates the naturalization of domination for both the dominant and the dominated. Correspondingly, in regard to the critical social analysis of domination, the congruence can also encourage analytic slippage, from more targeted critiques of specific relations of domination, to less focused and more totalizing critiques of society in general. Domination and States Modern states however, perhaps by definition, exercise stable, ongoing control over populations, issuing myriad commands that are followed on a daily basis. Although the state is not an agent per se, it is the instrument of the groups that control it, and exhibits institutional logics that steer the commands and actions of those that occupy it. Allowing for this quasi-agentic status, let us say that states normally engage in domination over their citizens. However, that domination may be biased against the interests of some sectors of the population, and in favor of others, and has particular latitude regarding aliens without legal status within state’s territories. A state that does not dominate, in Weber’s broad nonevaluative sense, is hardly worth the name; the question is, how is domination rendered legitimate for those subject to it? Antonio Gramsci’s (1891–1937) concept of hegemony, a position of dominance in a given sociopolitical setting, is relevant here. Gramsci analyzed early 20th-century Italian politics in terms of the hegemony of the bourgeoisie, achieved 206 Domination by creating alliances (a “historic bloc”) with subordinate groups (such as peasants and workers in key industries) and core institutions such as the Catholic Church. Thus, state domination was a manifestation of the successful historical alliance around shared interests by certain groups operating within it. In addition to dominating their citizens, states can dominate each other geopolitically, thus specialists in international relations sometime use hegemony to mean an alliance, or transnational historic bloc, between a dominant state (or set of states) and other transnational actors such as the International Monetary Fund (IMF), the UN Security Council, and multinational corporations. The general image is the same, but on a global scale. Both senses of hegemony imply the possibility of counter-hegemonies, that is, alliances of subordinated groups within specific state contexts, or of sets of subordinated countries and transnational actors, around shared interests attempting to dislodge the power of an existing historic bloc. For Gramsci, as a Marxist, this approach to historical political analysis assumed that class struggle within capitalism was the core process of contemporary human history. However, the general idea of analyzing strategic alliances does not logically entail privileging the economic sphere and is compatible with approaches that have more heterogeneous, less economistic understandings of the institutionalization of power. From Macro to Micro Dimensions Small-scale, interpersonal relations can also be understood in terms of domination. Again, this runs from relatively coercive forms, such as a patriarch controlling household resources and thus its members, to willing subordination, motivated by love, admiration, moral commitment, or some other legitimating rationale. And again, we are more likely to recognize interpersonal domination when it appears pathological. The classic example is when a charismatic individual becomes the center of a cult of believers, as did the Reverend Jim Jones who eventually led a group of 909 followers into group suicide when their utopian community in rural Guyana was falsely perceived to be under mortal threat in 1978. Personal accounts suggest Jones elicited from his followers a complex combination of inspiration, devotion, emotional dependence, and psychic insecurity—all contributing to the tragic end. This example is extreme—charismatic-centered communities do not necessarily go this way. But the general sociological type of the small, tightly knit community of uncritically devoted followers focused on the leadership and message of a single individual is well established. Uncomfortable as it is to consider, such extremes of human behavior have correlates in more routine interpersonal dynamics. Small social groups are always susceptible to the leadership, explicit or implicit, of individuals with commanding personalities, and even everyday friendships often exhibit modest dominant–subordinate dynamics. Indeed, such imbalances may have positive effects, both practical and psychic, for those involved. Finally, the micro points back to the macro, to the “gearing up” of dynamics of interpersonal domination to the macrosocietal level, by means of mass communication and symbolic representation. Charismatic leaders have clearly dominated mass societies (e.g., Hitler), but how this works is not obvious, it being very difficult to analytically disentangle psychic devotion to the person of the leader from the various modes of ideological suasion and material coercion at the disposal of the modern state. Conversely, the legitimacy of bureaucratic organizations in complex societies often hinges on personalistic perceptions of a leading figure, be it a head of a state, church, or corporation. Where the power of an organization is a matter of explicit public scrutiny, “faceless bureaucracy” often just is not tenable. Jonathan Hearn See also Authority; Bourdieu, Pierre; Gramsci, Antonio; Habitus; Hegemony; Leadership; Legitimation; Lukes, Steven; Structural Power; Weber, Max Further Readings Bourdieu, P. (1989). Social space and symbolic power. Sociological Theory, 7(1), 14–25. Foucault, M. (1980). Two lectures. In Power/knowledge (C. Gordon, Ed., pp. 78–109). New York: Pantheon. Gramsci, A. (1971). Selections from the prison notebooks of Antonio Gramsci. (Q. Hoare & G. N. Smith, Eds. & Trans.). New York: International Publishers. Dowding, Keith Hearn, J. (2008). What’s wrong with domination? Journal of Power, 1(1), 37–49. Scott, J. C. (1990). Domination and the arts of resistance: Hidden transcripts. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Weber, M. (1978). Domination and legitimacy. In Economy and society (G. Roth & C. Wittich, Eds., pp. 941–948). Berkeley: University of California Press. DOWDING, KEITH (1960– ) Keith Dowding has made two key contributions to understanding political power: demonstrating the importance of the collective action problem for our understanding of power and demonstrating the interplay of agency and structure with his concept of “systematic luck.” Collective action problems show that a group of actors might seem powerless even if there is no other group acting against them. Dowding claims that both pluralists and structural approaches fail to grasp this simple idea. Systematic luck is almost the converse, how one group can get what it wants even though the group does not act. Building from Brian Barry’s idea of luck as “getting what you want without trying,” Dowding claims luck is not randomly distributed, but often tied to a person’s location in the social structure or “system” the person inhabits. First developed in Rational Choice and Political Power, then in the more accessible Power, Dowding explains that although the systematically lucky might have access to resources that make them powerful, they often want what they get (as opposed to get what they want) because their interests noncontingently coincide with policy makers. The concept of systematic luck is often misunderstood by those who think Dowding is arguing that, for example, capitalists are lucky rather than powerful. He argues they are both, but luck can explain why the powerful often do not seem to act yet attain the outcomes they want. 207 Dowding has applied these notions to traditional debates in urban theory, arguing that growth coalitions and regime theory can be illuminated by the idea of systematic luck. Indeed, this idea is very close to Clarence Stone’s systemic power that underpins his original regime concept. The difference is that Dowding predicates power to agents (individuals, parties, groups, organizations) and not to structure itself, though his accounts of both what the collective action problem and systematic luck mean for analysis of power in society are highly structural. Dowding is also widely known for his theoretical work about, and promotion of, rational choice theory, testing Charles Tiebout’s hypothesis regarding efficient service-provision, exploring why government ministers resign, and latterly turning to the measurement of rights and freedoms. Awarded a doctorate from Oxford in 1987 for his dissertation Collective Action, Group Organization and Pluralist Democracy, Dowding joined the London School of Economics and Political Science in 1993 after teaching at Oxford and Brunel Universities. An editor of the highly regarded Journal of Theoretical Politics since 1995, he is now research professor at the Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University. Kennedy Stewart See also Agency; Barry, Brian; Collective Action Problem; Growth Coalitions; Luck; Lukes, Steven; Morriss, Peter; Structuration; Systematic Luck; Systemic Power Further Readings Dowding, K. (1991). Rational choice and political power. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar. Dowding, K. (1996). Power. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Dowding, K. (2003). Resources, power and systematic luck: A response to Barry. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 2(3), 305–322. E to explain why men have been more likely to attain social dominance. Their theory suggests that the declining importance of male size and strength within high-status occupations combined with lower birth rates and shared child rearing underlie the erosion of men’s social dominance in postindustrial societies. Eagly has also initiated discussions of the political dimensions of research on sex differences, urging scientists to resist both simplistic “just-so” stories of evolutionary sex differences and liberal “political correctness” in favor of openness to the data. Eagly and her colleagues were the first to notice, in contradiction to prevailing views of sexism as antipathy toward women, that women are actually stereotyped more favorably than men. At the same time, she noted that this favorability occurs because stereotypical female traits (e.g., nurturance) suit women for traditional, lowerstatus feminine roles. These findings challenged the notion that prejudice is an undifferentiated antipathy and sparked important advances in understanding the nature of sexism. Eagly has also been a strong advocate and practitioner of meta-analysis (which allows for statistically sophisticated averaging of effects across studies). For example, Eagly and colleagues’ meta-analysis of studies on reactions to women leaders revealed that women are disliked when they adopt a masculine leadership style. These findings inspired Eagly and Karau’s role congruity theory, which suggests that prejudice is not a simple antipathy toward a group, but a relatively lower evaluation of group members when evaluated for EAGLY, ALICE (1938– ) Why do men possess more power than women in so many cultures? Does this reflect evolved differences in aptitudes or socially imposed strictures that favor men and discourage women from obtaining positions of power? Few have made as significant theoretical and empirical contributions to understanding these questions as has Alice Hendrickson Eagly. Eagly’s early interests in attitudes led her (in the 1970s) to a critical examination of findings that women are more easily influenced than men. Her review suggested that social status rather than inherent sex differences (the previously accepted explanation) accounted for these effects. These insights led Eagly to further explorations of sex stereotypes, culminating in social role theory, which explains how a gendered division of labor (and the gender hierarchy it reflects) creates sex differences in behavior and corresponding sex stereotypes (e.g., women are more likely to enact the nurturing behavior the homemaker role demands). By relating social structure (roles) to prescriptions for behavior, Eagly’s theory accounted for the origins of sex differences. In response to evolutionary psychologists, Eagly and Wendy Wood expanded the social role approach. Their biosocial theory incorporates the interaction of biological sex differences, such as men’s greater size and strength and women’s reproductive role, with social factors (e.g., the development of agriculture) 209 210 e-Governance roles that do not match the group’s perceived traits. Peter Glick See also Sexism, Role of Power in Further Readings Eagly, A. H. (1995). The science and politics of comparing women and men. American Psychologist, 50, 145–158. Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (1999). The origins of sex differences in human behavior: Evolved dispositions versus social roles. American Psychologist, 54, 408–423. E-GOVERNANCE E-governance is the use of the Internet and related information technologies by governmental organizations internally and to interact with citizens, firms, nongovernmental organizations, and other governments. Defined so, e-governance offers the potential to reshape power relationships between governments and citizens, particularly in those countries with widespread use of the Internet. For citizens, the Internet opens new ways to seek and find information from government but also from a proliferation of other information sources. The Internet gives citizens access to expertise—for example, on health and education—that can rebalance information asymmetries in their interactions with public sector professionals. The Internet also reduces the costs of political mobilization and organization, strengthening civil society in ways that may increase the influence of interest groups on public policy issues in liberal democratic states. Less benignly, the usefulness of the Internet for a wide range of criminal and fraudulent activities puts pressure on states to develop further their surveillance techniques. In authoritarian states, the Internet may offer new ways in which citizens and groups can challenge state authority, for example by disseminating information about the regime across global networks or using social media to coordinate protests and demonstrations. Conversely, e-governance may also increase the power of governmental organizations in relation to citizens. Governments in most developed nations spend around 1% of gross domestic product (GDP) on their own information systems and electronic presence. The capacity of such technologies to collect, store, and analyze personal information about citizens increases the state’s ability to influence societal behavior and control citizens, with new potential for state intrusion into individual privacy even in democratic states. Authoritarian states can use Internetrelated technologies to strengthen their authority over citizens through surveillance of online activity. The challenges to authoritarian regimes posed by citizen use of the Internet has led to widespread censorship and filtering of the Internet across China and most Arab states and prohibition of its use in North Korea, for example. Some states have also used the Internet to challenge the authority of other states, attacking the electronic capability of another government and waging “cyberwar.” The extent to which power relations are rebalanced through use of the Internet will rely partly on the relative capacity of governments and citizens to innovate with technology. The Internet is perhaps the first information technology that has been used more extensively by citizens and civil society than by governments, and for this reason, there is a greater chance of citizen empowerment than from earlier technological developments, such as mainframe computer systems, the personal computer, or databases. Convergence with other popular technologies, such as mobile telephones and mainstream media outlets, accentuates this pattern, as do so-called Web 2.0 technologies, which allow users to generate their own content and to participate in large-scale collaborative networks or forums such as blogs, video-sharing sites (such as YouTube), Wikipedia, social networking sites, and so on. Governmental organizations, in contrast, have been slower to adopt these innovations, sometimes struggling to manage large information technology investments and unwieldy databases and being reluctant to embrace the informality of social networking technologies and the part-authenticated nature of the information that Web 2.0 applications provide. For this reason, e-governance may, ultimately, empower citizens relative to government. Helen Margetts Elections See also Globalization; Governmentality; Internet and Power Further Readings Dunleavy, P., Margetts, H., Bastow, S., & Tinkler, J. (2006). Digital-era governance: IT corporations, the state and e-government. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. ELECTIONS Elections are the process by which people are voted in and out of positions of power. In representative democracies, elections determine who is able to exercise power and who is not and in this way grant politicians and parties power to enact their policies. Elections give power to ordinary citizens who may have few other ways to voice their preferences in the political world. For many, elections are the only means by which they participate in politics. Elections commonly receive widespread coverage in the media and concentrate the public’s attention on political matters. They are meant as a peaceful way in which the people can have their voices heard and usually involve a coordinated and peaceful transition of power. In this way, elections bring order and stability to the political world. The outcome of elections depends on the nature of the political system, which determines how political power is configured. Elections can vary from “first-past-the-post” (FPTP) elections where a party is often able to govern with a majority in the legislature to proportional representation (PR) elections where parties form government coalitions that share power and work together. For example, in FPTP parliamentary systems such as Australia, a party can have a majority in the lower and upper houses, giving the governing party effective control over what legislation is passed. Conversely, PR systems (which operate, for example, in many European countries) often involve coalitions and a great deal of negotiation between parties, thus spreading power across the parties. There are also parliamentary and presidential elections, which have very different outcomes and consequences for political power. There are other variations in how elections are conducted in various countries. In some countries, 211 elections are held on fixed dates, whereas in other countries they can be held (often within certain time periods) at the discretion of the party in power. The way in which electoral districts are laid out can dramatically affect the outcome of election. Gerrymandering is a process by which a ruling group can bias electoral districts in its own favor. Electoral proportionality is also important. In some countries, parties can win an election without securing the majority of the vote. Electoral systems can therefore produce disproportional outcomes. For example, in the 1992 British general election, the Liberal Democrats won 17.9% of the vote but only 3.1% of seats in the House of Commons. Elections are now a common feature of contemporary society. The number of electoral democracies greatly expanded throughout the 20th century. According to Freedom House in 2009, there are 121 electoral democracies in the world. It remains to be seen whether the number of electoral democracies will contract or expand over time. Freedom House has expressed concerns that a “democratic recession” is setting in. The 19th century saw the development and extension of the party system around which elections continue to be based today. Whereas before elections involved parties representing capital or labor, in recent elections a much larger array of parties represents a much larger array of interests. The spectrum of parties has broadened considerably in the last few decades. Parties such as green or disarmament parties have come to represent the new issues and interests of the public. Absent effective opposition parties, however, elections are often not held in “free and fair” conditions. Elections often involve opposition parties making the argument that they are a better alternative than the governing party. However, in places where there are no effective opposition parties, electoral legitimacy is questioned. In this sense, elections are not always synonymous with democracy. In many countries, voters are presented with very little choice and elections occur under suspicious conditions. Holding elections is a necessary but not sufficient condition for citizens to live in freedom and have a say over their country’s future. Foremost among these other conditions are civil and political rights and a free media. Absent these conditions, elections can lack any substantive meaning. In frustration with this, some citizens 212 Elite Theories may adopt other means of having their voices heard, such as protests or sit-ins. In authoritarian countries, however, these efforts are often stymied. Elections are often used in authoritarian states to give the perception of legitimacy to those who want to maintain power. Modern elections in advanced democracies occur in a very different environment from that in the past. Television and the Internet have greatly altered the nature of elections by exposing politicians to greater scrutiny and sometimes reducing politics to entertainment. Opinion polls have also changed elections by changing the strategy of parties and politicians by giving them access to information about voter’s preferences and opinions in between elections. Parties also conduct internal polling to find out more about the popularity of leaders and policy. Whereas before the electorate voiced its views through elections predominantly, now opinion polls can provide a snapshot of the public mood at any given time. There is also much greater volatility in vote choice with social class playing a smaller influence than it did before with partisan loyalty and identification decreasing and “swing voters” often determining the outcome of elections. In some cases, radical parties have appealed to these new “floating” voters by making populist appeals, further creating instability in the political world. Aaron Martin See also Democracy; Legislative Power; Political Parties; Referendums; Voting Further Readings Colomer, J. M. (Ed.). (2004). Handbook of electoral system choice. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Gallagher, M., & Mitchell, P. (Eds.). (2005). The politics of electoral systems. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. ELITE THEORIES Elite theories of power hold that power is primarily concentrated in hands of a few, or the elite. The first and perhaps the most famous proponent of an elite theory was noted American sociologist C. Wright Mills in The Power Elite (1956). As Alan Wolfe notes in his afterword of the republication of The Power Elite in 2000, Mills took aim at two prevailing views of U.S. society at the time, namely, pluralism and the end of ideology thesis. Pluralism is the view that power is not concentrated in the hands of the few but rather spread out among different groups. The “end of ideology” thesis holds that the debate about any ideological differences was over and that any problems that remain could be solved with technical expertise. Mills argued instead that power in U.S. society is not spread out evenly, but is instead concentrated in the hands of few that are in command of the major hierarchies and organizations of modern society. . . . They occupy the strategic command posts of the social structure, in which are now centered the effective means of the power and the wealth and celebrity which they enjoy. (Mills, 1956, p. 3) In contrast with the end of ideology thesis, Mills argues that the debate over ideas is not truly exhausted, but instead it is merely being silenced. Mills felt that democratic politics ideally should be an arena where different viewpoints and opinions should be debated freely and openly. However, Mills felt that the concentration of power allowed the debate to be skewed to favor the viewpoints of the power elite. This, according to Mills, has led to the degradation of public discourse and the erosion of democracy, which in turn has led to power being shifted away from elected representatives. This is why Mills says at the beginning of The Power Elite that the powers of ordinary citizens often seem to be driven by forces that they cannot see. Floyd Hunter in Community Power Structure makes a similar case. His study focused on control at the local level in the United States. Although he is not as confrontational as Mills is, Hunter’s conclusions are nonetheless scathing. He found a small group in control of most of the social structures in “Regional City” with most citizens simply acquiescing to the decisions made by those in power. The social and political structures, Hunter claims, “are controlled by men who use their influence in devious ways . . . to keep down public discussion Empire on all issues except those that have the stamp of approval of the power group” (Hunter, 1953, p. 249). The one thing common to proponents of elite theories of power is that they do not think that the concentration of the power in the hands of elites is a good thing for society. First, elite concentration of power ensures that certain viewpoints do not make it into the public discourse. Second, and as a result of the first point, most citizens will have no information or knowledge about how power is being used to affect their lives. Although the accusations made by elite theorists are certainly scathing and impassioned, they have been criticized for not sustaining their theoretical criticisms with empirical verification. Early elite theorists used reputational analysis to empirically base their claims. Reputational analysis proceeds by asking people who they think are powerful, and then triangulating responses by questioning those names as powerful. Modern elite theory, as represented by William Domhoff, uses many techniques to analyze the elites, including examining the schools they attended, the clubs they belong to, and so on. Modern network analysis generates similar ways of examining links between elites. The growth coalition literature expands elite theory into a more structural direction by suggesting that it is the structures of power that lead developers at the local level and capital at the national and multinational level to have greater power. Another direction, also more structural than elite theory has taken, is through the work of Clarence Stone who, like Hunter, bases his empirical work on Atlanta. Regime theory and its associated idea of systemic power suggests that elites tend to dominate through sharing specific ideas. Elite versions of these analyses concentrate on the personnel involved and their family backgrounds as part of the structures of power in society. Joseph Angolano See also Domhoff, G. William; Growth Coalitions; Hunter, Floyd; Mills, C. Wright; Regime Theory in Urban Politics; Reputational Analysis 213 Mills, C. W. (1956). The power elite. New York: Oxford University Press. Wolfe, A. (2000). Afterword. In C. W. Mills, The power elite. New York: Oxford University Press. EMPIRE An empire is a regime of domination, created when a powerful state (the “core”) imposes its rule on a number of weaker territories and peoples (the “periphery”), controlling or strongly influencing the internal and external affairs of those countries. The imperial power exercises ultimate sovereignty over core and periphery, but the two parts are run on divergent principles. Empires were not formed because the core state wished to assume responsibility for administering outside territories; there were usually more salient reasons for acquiring an empire, such as economic or strategic imperatives. Running empires required a delicate power balance: on the one hand, empires were vehicles for strong states to increase or consolidate their power resources, through acquiring land, raw materials, military forces, and cheap labor; on the other hand, coercive control of outside territories could exhaust a state’s resources and bring an end to its empire. Empire building involved high costs for the core state, so acquired territories were expected to yield an adequate return on investment. To maximize returns, empires were generally run “on the cheap” unless more expensive strategies became necessary. Empires crumbled when the core state became weak and a stronger state took over, or when the costs of maintaining an empire became so prohibitive that dismantling was the only rational option. Most analysts believe that empires are now a thing of the past and have been replaced by hegemonic relationships. But recent authors have argued that empires still exist, controlled by powerful coalitions rather than individual states. Historical Background Further Readings Hunter, F. (1953). Community power structure: A study of decision makers. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Empires have existed since ancient times, at least since Sargon of Akkad formed the first Mesopotamian empire in 2300 BCE. Early empires were continental, with core territories located in the 214 Empire Middle East, Asia, North Africa, South America, and Europe. Some ancient empires, notably Rome, controlled far-flung territories, but their mode of expansion was overland rather than by sea. From the 15th century on, advances in seaborne technologies meant that maritime empires could form. Land empires continued to exist—the Ottoman, Russian, Chinese, and Austro-Hungarian empires survived into the 20th century—but overseas imperialism became the dominant form of territorial expansion, and the center of geopolitical power shifted to Western Europe. During the 15th and 16th centuries, Portugal and Spain were the main imperial powers, extending their rule to the New World, Africa, South Asia, and the Caribbean. By the end of the 16th century, other imperial rivals— namely, France, England, and Holland—began to emerge, acquiring territories in the Americas, Southeast Asia, and Africa. Thereafter, the global power balance became multipolar, with different countries assuming the lead position and wars between imperial rivals resulting in territorial transfers between empires. In the late 19th century, three new European powers—Belgium, Italy, and Germany—joined the race for empires, as did two countries from outside the region, the United States and Japan, which expanded overland as well as overseas. European territorial annexations in Africa, Asia, and the Pacific between 1880 and 1900 resulted in 80% of the world’s land being run by empires. Systems of Coercion and Control Empires combine coercive force with political control. The dual character of empires is contained in the word itself. Empire derives from the Latin imperium, which in ancient Rome meant “sovereignty,” or the legal authority to make and enforce laws and to wage war. During the reign of Augustus, the term gained a territorial dimension and the Imperium Romanum referred to Rome and its newly acquired dependencies as a single entity. The imperator or “emperor” was the new unit’s head of state and military commander-inchief. These words and their dual meanings were appropriated by later empires: in 1876, Queen Victoria declared herself “Empress of India,” whereas the highest official in most British colonies was the governor-general. Coercive force was necessary both for acquiring and running empires. Military theorists have estimated that the ratio of power required for a superior state to regularly exercise control over an external territory and defend its position is about three to one. Hence, core states needed to be significantly more powerful than are the territories they conquered if their empires were to survive. Of course, not all peripheries were acquired by force, although most were. Michael Doyle has flagged three instances when groups in weaker polities invited core powers to extend their rule into the weaker polities: Cameroonian kings Bell and Acqua to British Prime Minister Gladstone, factions within Corcyra to the Athenian empire, and elites within Greece and Britain to the Roman Empire. The military played a key role in taming rebellions and defending territorial borders against attack by rival powers. Peripheral populations could often be controlled through subtle threats of military action, so brute force was not always required. But in some cases—for example, the Spanish invasion in the Americas and the westward expansion of the United States—indigenous groups were exterminated. In maritime empires, a strong navy was necessary for quickly transporting military forces across the globe and providing security for the smooth flow of trade. Subject populations were often recruited as troops to form the lower echelons of the imperial military forces, for deployment locally as well as across the empire. Core state officials had ultimate authority over all parts of the empire, core and periphery. The same set of people determined policy for both parts, but each was governed according to divergent principles. Core state institutions operated in the interests of their citizens, or at least a large enough proportion to command legitimacy. Meanwhile, rule in the peripheries took place without the explicit consent of local populations and served the interests of the core state. Peripheral policies had two main purposes: to maintain the territories within the empire and to generate income and other benefits for the core. The bulk of peripheral revenues not remitted to the core was spent on military and police activities, in effect forcing peripheral populations to fund their own subjection. Because empires are large entities incorporating diverse populations, political control of the periphery was not possible without the Empire cooperation of local elites. These “collaborators” were given power, status, and a small portion of peripheral revenues in exchange for keeping the peace, securing imperial trade, collecting taxes, and, where possible, supplying the empire with troops and cheap labor. These collaborators helped keep administration costs low and reduce chances of popular rebellion. Specific systems of peripheral rule varied depending on the time period, the availability of local elites capable of commanding legitimacy, and the structure of the international system. Most ancient empires before Rome lacked the political capacities and infrastructures to directly govern the territories they conquered. Hence, they ruled their peripheries informally: territories were legally independent, and local clients governed their jurisdictions unhindered as long as they kept trade routes open and passed on a large proportion of the taxes they collected to the core. The core maintained sovereign control of certain key areas, however, including finance, military, diplomacy, trade, and political succession. An alternative method of informal rule employed by England, Holland, and France during the 17th and 18th centuries, and by England during the 19th century, was quasi-government through chartered companies: private trading firms were authorized to acquire territories and administer them on behalf of the core, and were provided with monopoly powers and naval support in exchange for a share of the profits. The Roman Empire was the first to rule formally by annexing territories and assigning a governor to them to directly implement imperial policies. The governor represented the core state and carried out functions on its behalf, such as levying tax, administering justice, and controlling police forces. However, the core state retained sovereign powers for trade, defense, and external affairs and could overturn any decision made by the governor. Local elites formed the lower echelons of government, supervised by the governor. All empires after Rome used some combination of formal and informal rule. However, informal rule was preferred because it generated revenues for the core at low cost and without the responsibilities of formal, direct rule. Conversely, multipolarity in the international system after the 16th century rendered formal rule necessary for deterring imperial rivals from forming alliances with peripheral elites. 215 But some modern empires discovered a route around the problem: peripheries could be ruled formally, with core-appointed “residents” overseeing independently functioning local elites who administered large provinces rather than small localities. This was the “indirect rule” system employed in many British colonies since the late 19th century. Benefits of Empire The main benefits generated by an empire were economic. In some cases, territorial extension preserved economic advantages already gained: Sargon conquered neighboring areas in Mesopotamia to protect existing trade routes and surpluses. In other cases, expansionism occurred to promote economic growth in core states: the Roman empire spread to obtain slaves to overcome labor shortages in domestic agriculture, whereas late Victorian empires were constructed to secure cheap raw materials and new markets to feed industrialism at home. Coercion and control mechanisms were used to obtain maximum economic gains. In many European empires, peripheral populations were forced off fertile lands to make way for settlers from the core who wanted to exploit agricultural and commercial opportunities there. The state assisted settlers by providing them with imported slave or indentured labor or by forcing indigenous populations to work on their plantations or mines. Settlers were also given monopoly production rights, precluding peripheral populations from developing industries of their own. Empires were run as economic enclaves: peripheries were permitted to produce only the few commodities that the core required, and raw materials were transported from periphery to core, manufactured, and then forcibly sold back to peripheral groups at a profit. From the 15th to the 18th centuries, imperial powers applied mercantilist principles to monopolize the benefits of trade from peripheries. Peripheries were thus tied to the core in economic dependence, creating a gap between European growth economies and peripheral economies, which persisted even after free trade replaced mercantilism. Technological innovations, particularly in weaponry, transportation, and communications, enhanced the core’s abilities to coerce and control the periphery. In early empires, innovations such as 216 Empire the chariot and iron weapons allowed more technologically advanced powers to dominate less advanced groups. In modern times, military technologies such as the repeating rifle, the Maxim machine gun, and armored steamships allowed European empires to impose their rule on tribal societies. Effective control of peripheral populations was not possible before animal-powered vehicles, paved roads, and sailing ships enabled the flow of movement and communication across large surfaces. Empires require infrastructures connecting core and periphery, as well as routes into and through the periphery. Railways, roads, and ports enabled the rapid transport of officials and military forces, as well as commercial goods, across and between territories. Innovations in communications, such as the telegraph, enabled the core state to more directly influence policies in distant peripheries and helped lower the costs of imperial control. But coercion and control could not be too oppressive or overbearing; otherwise, there was the risk of rebellion. Revolts were costly and diverted military and police forces from other duties—for example, defending territorial borders against invasion by rival powers. Additionally, resistance could sometimes be successful, resulting in loss of prestige or even an empire. The Roman Empire collapsed partly because it placed too many tax, military, and other demands on its subject populations. Overtaxation without political representation was the prime reason American revolutionaries fought for, and won, independence from the British Empire. Slave uprisings against the French in Haiti were also ultimately successful. Successful revolts and independence movements had observation and demonstration effects, increasing the likelihood that other peripheries would follow suit. Resistance could be subverted, and the costs of coercion and control reduced, by assimilating peripheral populations into the culture of the core territory. In some early empires, cultural diffusion was achieved through intermarriage between rulers and ruled. Some later empires, such as the Roman and the French, believed that assimilation could dissolve cultural differences and strengthen peripheral bonds of loyalty to the empire. Hence, they extended citizenship rights to peripheral groups that adopted their customs and values. Most modern European empires relied on missionaries from the core to transmit their culture to peripheral populations. The relationship between religious and imperial state institutions was symbiotic: missions benefited from military protection and state financial support, and imperial control was facilitated by church teachings that state authorities should be obeyed. In the Spanish and Portuguese empires, powerful papal bulls authorized imperial expansion. Cultural diffusion was a two-way process in all empires, affecting rulers and ruled and producing a hybrid culture. The ideas, customs, and habits of many empires lasted well beyond their regimes. Ideas and lessons from the Roman Empire were applied by succeeding empires. Decolonization and After All empires crumble eventually, under the strain of ruling other territories or because stronger challengers emerge and wrest the empires from their rulers. The two processes are interlinked: whereas peripheries initially enhance a core state’s power, at some point they become more expensive than the benefits they provide, and the core becomes weakened trying to maintain control of them. Most core states devised strategies to stem losses—for example, gradually granting self-government to peripheries. This happened in the Roman Empire under Augustus and in the 20th-century British Empire. In modern empires, the spread of Western ideas and education alerted peripheral populations to inherent inequalities in imperial policies and the different rules applied to core and periphery. Post–17thcentury Europe had rejected monarchical rule in favor of popular representation, yet continued to autocratically govern its overseas peripheries. Political consciousness gave rise to demands for equal treatment and political representation, then to nationalist struggles for self-determination and independence. Ideas also traveled between empires: hence, the U.S. war of independence inspired French revolutionary ideas, which in turn stimulated Latin American independence movements. Wars among powerful polities also weakened core states and produced imperial challengers, who took control of defeated countries’ empires or demanded that they dismantle them. Early empires, such as the Persian and Mughal, lost their empires for the former reason, and 20th-century European empires were pressured to decolonize by the new world powers, the United States and Soviet Union. Entrepreneurs With near-complete decolonization of European maritime empires by the 1980s and the collapse of the Soviet empire in 1991, most analysts agreed that the era of formal empires had come to an end. However, many claimed that the United States still operates an informal empire, using its international dominance, overseas military bases, control of international political and financial institutions, and all-encompassing cultural and technological influence to force other countries to act according to its wishes. Some have termed U.S.–led interventions in Afghanistan and Iraq formal imperialism. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri contend that globalization processes, which began during the imperial era, have created a new empire: the core is no longer a single state but a transnational network of powers comprising states and economic actors that dominates and exploits a periphery that is not territorially bounded but progressively incorporates the entire globe. Gita Subrahmanyam See also Domination; Globalization; Imperial Power; Imperialism Further Readings Abernethy, D. B. (2000). The dynamics of global dominance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Doyle, M. W. (1986). Empires. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hardt, M., & Negri, A. (2000). Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Howe, S. (2002). Empire: A very short introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. ENTREPRENEURS Entrepreneurs are the economic actors who, in competitive markets, make decisions about which goods to produce and at what price to market them. Entrepreneurial activity is understood here to include both innovation, the introduction of new goods and new methods of production, and market making, attempts to find new customers for existing products or to sell to new customers at a more profitable price. Traditionally, and in 217 both popular discourse and economic theory, entrepreneurs have been pictured as the buccaneering, larger-than-life owners of individual businesses. Indeed many would still argue that it is a defining feature of entrepreneurs that they risk their own resources in the pursuit of profit. At the same time, however, it has become conventional to distinguish between entrepreneurs and the entrepreneurial function and to argue that the latter can be performed by appointed managers. Do entrepreneurs possess power? Economists such as Israel Kirzner who belong to the Austrian School argue that they do not. Entrepreneurs are the “Prime Mover[s] of [economic] Progress” and routinely make decisions that can affect the lives of millions of people. In doing so, however, they are simply responding to and so are the servants of consumer preferences. Entrepreneurs, in themselves, have no power to change those preferences and if they chose to ignore them would soon be driven out of business. What if, through an astute reading of the market, an entrepreneur is able to acquire a degree of monopoly power? Would he or she then be able to exercise this power by exploiting consumers? Kirzner would argue that entrepreneurs could not. Because it is always open to other entrepreneurs to enter a market if they feel that there are profits to be made, apparent monopolies when measured in current market share are, in practice, always contestable and this means that entrepreneurs cannot exploit consumers. Much the same argument might be made in relation to the powers exercised by entrepreneurs over their workforces. Entrepreneurs might, subject to minimal government standards, be able to set workers’ wages and working conditions, and this might be said to give them a degree of power. They must, however, exercise this power in the context of a competitive market. If entrepreneurs were to abuse their power, this would simply encourage their workers to seek alternative employment. Very different accounts of the role of the entrepreneur are offered by Joseph Schumpeter (1883– 1950) and John Kenneth Galbraith (1908–2006). Schumpeter argued that entrepreneurs acquire “spectacular prizes” to the extent that they are able to anticipate what consumers might want and what they can be persuaded to want. He also argued that successful entrepreneurs do often acquire, in the short term at least, a degree of 218 Environmental Treaties monopoly power over consumers, although he cautioned that the existence of monopoly should be regarded as a sign of economic vitality rather than of inefficiency. In The New Industrial State, Galbraith argued that the entrepreneur no longer exists as an individual person, and that, within the modern economy, the entrepreneurial function is instead exercised by a large group of anonymous specialists who work within giant corporations where ownership is divorced from economic decision making. Galbraith views the rise of the giant corporation with ambivalence. On the one hand, he recognizes that corporations have accelerated the rate of innovation. On the other hand, he argues that corporations are able to anticipate and manipulate consumer preferences to “create the wants they seek to satisfy.” In this respect and at least in the tone he adopts, Galbraith appears to go farther than Schumpeter. Schumpeter indicates that consumers’ preferences are malleable but leaves the impression that entrepreneurs must nevertheless at least engage with them. Galbraith seems to suggest that “product planners . . . advertising and sales executives [and] public relations men” can create preferences out of thin air. He also maintains that corporations have routinely hijacked the democratic political process and extracted policy concessions from government. In each of these respects, Galbraith would argue that entrepreneurs working within corporations possess a measure of power. In recent decades, the concept of entrepreneurs and of entrepreneurship has been borrowed by political scientists. There are three common applications here. First, those writing about the process of party competition have often likened votemaximizing party leaders to profit-maximizing business entrepreneurs. Second, policy analysts such as John Kingdon have identified a crucial role for entrepreneurs within the policy process in discovering and repackaging innovative policy proposals, identifying previously unnoticed policy problems, and coupling these two streams by brokering coalitions of support for a new policy initiative. Finally, a more applied literature within social policy has sought to account for the success of particular community-based voluntary organizations in terms of the activities of “social” entrepreneurs who can acquire funding, energize workers, and overcome bureaucratic obstacles. The impression left in each of these cases is that entrepreneurs must be alert to and exploit previously unrecognized opportunities by gaining the support of either voters or political leaders but that entrepreneurs do not themselves possess any political power. Against this, it might be argued that political entrepreneurs do possess considerable power insofar as they are able to set policy agendas and shape political leaders’ preferences. In these respects, the power exercised by political entrepreneurs might be likened to that attributed to economic entrepreneurs by Schumpeter and, less benignly, Galbraith. Andrew Hindmoor See also Policy Entrepreneurs Further Readings Galbraith, J. K. (1967). The new industrial state. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin. Kingdon, J. (1994). Agendas, alternatives and public policies. Boston: Little, Brown. Kirzner, I. (1980). The prime mover of progress: The entrepreneur in capitalism and socialism. London: Institute of Economic Affairs. ENVIRONMENTAL TREATIES Environmental treaties are binding international agreements designed to address issues of natural resource management, pollution, and other ecological concerns that are not contained within political boundaries of states. Treaties symbolize states’ intent to engage in cooperative action to address an existing problem or take precautionary action to prevent ecological deterioration. Both state and nonstate actors may attempt to use environmental treaties to promote their own interests and influence the actions of others. In this way, environmental treaties can become mechanisms by which actors may wield varying degrees of power over others. History of Environmental Treaties The first multilateral environmental treaty was recorded in 1868. Since then, more that 450 Environmental Treaties multilateral and 900 regional agreements have entered into force. Most of these have been adopted since 1972, when the UN Conference on the Human Environment was held in Stockholm, Sweden. This landmark meeting was the first mega-conference convened to discuss international environmental issues in a systematic and comprehensive way. To date, three subsequent mega-conferences have been held and a plethora of environmental agreements have been concluded internationally, regionally, and globally. Although cooperative environmental agreements are often hailed as positive steps toward managing resources, protecting fragile ecosystems, or preventing harm to human health, the UN Environment Programme has noted that parties often find it difficult to meet the numerous obligations conferred on them by these agreements. Key Actors Both state and nonstate actors are involved in the development and implementation of environmental treaties. State actors may include both bureaucrats, or government-designated policy experts, and scientific advisers appointed by states to assist policy makers in their analysis of technically complex issues. Nonstate actors may include representatives of corporations, industry associations, and civil society advocacy groups. These actors participate in treaty development and implementation by lobbying decision makers, contributing ideas to policy discussions, and providing evidence that may influence policy choices. The Role of Science in Environmental Policy Making Science plays an important role in the formulation of environmental treaties. The complexity of environmental problems and lack of certainty about hazards posed by various technologies and activities have led policy makers to rely increasingly on scientists for advice about appropriate policy responses. As advances in technology (e.g., chemical production and use) have changed the way humans interact with the environment, new issues relating to environmental and human health degradation have arisen. The risks associated with these technologies are often poorly understood, and 219 evaluation of these hazards often requires individuals with scientific expertise to predict possible outcomes under conditions of great uncertainty. Policy makers have called on scientists to interpret complex technical information, assess the risks posed by various activities, and help devise appropriate policy responses to problems. Thus, scientists have become key actors in the formulation of many international environmental agreements. Governments, corporations, and advocacy groups all employ scientists to analyze problems and represent their interests during the stages of policy making in which scientific evaluation of environmental problems is carried out. Thus, although science is often regarded as separate from politics, in reality economic and social interests are often promoted during the earliest, supposedly politically neutral, stages of policy making. The technical complexity of many contemporary environmental problems can create opportunities for stakeholders to promote their political agendas by emphasizing knowledge gaps or scientific uncertainty. Parties on all sides of an issue can use scientific evidence (or the lack thereof) to argue in favor of their own policy preferences. Exaggeration of scientific uncertainty or strategic framing of issues are two examples of the way in which power can play an important role in the formulation and implementation of environmental treaties. Enforcement Enforcing the rules established by international environmental treaties is very difficult. Most treaties rely on what can be summed up as peer pressure to encourage parties to abide by the terms of the agreements. Theoretically, environmental treaties are voluntary contracts that states sign and ratify only if they support the treaties’ objectives and are willing to implement any subsequent measures. In practice, nations may have difficulty abiding by the tenets of a treaty, or their interests change in ways that create incentives for noncooperation. Formal punishment (e.g., sanctions) for failure to abide by such agreements is virtually nonexistent. Although disincentives for noncooperation may appeal to members of civil society, policy makers often prefer to encourage a spirit of cooperation, in hopes that such support will lead to future opportunities for the advancement of an 220 Espionage international environmental agenda. Punitive measures such as sanctions may discourage countries from engaging in policy-making discussions from the start. To encourage cooperation, some treaties (particularly those involving nations from both developed and developing nations) include financial or technical support mechanisms to help countries abide by the treaty’s requirements. Some observers have argued that offering more incentives for nations to sign and implement treaties would improve both the scope and effectiveness of environmental treaties. Such incentives could take the form of financial assistance, technological development, special trade agreements, and so forth. Jessica Templeton See also Agenda Setters; Coordination; Elite Theories; Framing; Global Governance; Knowledge and Power Further Readings Andresen, S., Skodvin, T., Underdal, A., & Wettestad, J. (2000). Science and politics in international environmental regimes: Between integrity and involvement. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. Center for International Earth Science Information Network (CIESIN). (1996–2001). Environmental Treaties and Resource Indicators (ENTRI). Palisades, NY: CIESIN. Retrieved from http://sedac.ciesin. columbia.edu/entri/ Conca, K., & Dabelko, G. D. (Eds.). (2004). Green planet blues: Environmental politics from Stockholm to Johannesburg. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Susskind, L., Moomaw, W., & Gallagher, K. (Eds.). (2002). Transboundary environmental negotiation: New approaches to global cooperation. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. ESPIONAGE Literally the conduct of spying (from the French espion meaning “spy”), espionage is usually referred to as “covert collection” by the intelligence community, as opposed to the gathering and processing of information from publicly available open sources. Covert collection is broadly grouped into five collection methods, known in U.S. parlance as “collection disciplines”: (1) human intelligence, (2) signals intelligence, (3) imagery intelligence, (4) measurements intelligence, and (5) signatures intelligence. Human intelligence (HUMINT) is the receipt of information from human sources or agents (career employees of intelligence services are always designated intelligence officers). This can include highly sensitive reporting from informants active within a target group or government known as penetration agents; defectors who are former members of the target groups who have changed sides and fled their home community; information provided by escaping servicemen or gleaned from the interrogation of prisoners of war; and less sensitive materials by debriefing refugees and business travelers. Human intelligence requires very careful evaluation or validation to establish what the information does or does not indicate, and whether the information can be trusted or not. Agents can be mistaken or captured and “played back” on their controllers to feed deceptive information, a practice known as doubling an agent. Agents may also be sincerely mistaken or exaggerate claims to curry favor with the intelligence officer to whom they report. In their favor, human sources can provide unique insight into the intentions, personalities, and methods of a target organization or government. Signals intelligence (SIGINT) comprises the interception and interpretation of (mainly) electromagnetic signals. SIGINT is divided into the interception and interpretation of communications (COMINT) and the monitoring of noncommunicative signals such as radar or telemetry transmissions or electromagnetic leakage from the operation of various electronic systems grouped together as electronic intelligence (ELINT). Signals can be intercepted from ground-level facilities such as mobile units of the army or air force on land or ships at sea and at fixed scale monitoring stations (known colloquially as “antenna farms”). Signals can also be monitored either by staffed or unstaffed aircraft operating in the atmosphere (known as air breathing platforms) or from Earth orbit by reconnaissance satellites (termed non-air-breathing platforms). Most communications, even over targeted channels, are of little or no intelligence value. Consequently, a distinction is drawn between the overall body of intercepted traffic or take and that which is actually of intelligence use, which is Essentially Contested Concept termed product. Product is typically as little as 10% or less of the take. Intercepted communications are generally divided between encrypted, which are in code, and clear traffic, which is not, whether in the form of voice or text. Encrypted materials must be decoded before they can be processed or exploited. However, even if a particular cipher is not successfully broken, a great deal can be learned about the target just from the pattern of communications being generated. Direction finding uses multiple receivers to triangulate the location of a transceiver, whereas traffic analysis examines which transceivers or “nodes” in a communications network send and receive the most traffic and to and from which other nodes. Imagery intelligence (IMINT) is the use of various imaging technologies to generate pictures that can then be interpreted to extract intelligence information. Photographic intelligence (PHOTINT) generally refers to images taken in the same light spectrum that the human eye uses to see. Much imagery intelligence employs nonvisible wavelengths, such as parts of the invisible spectrum that the eye cannot detect. Infrared (IR) imagery, for example, detects heat radiated or reflected by an object. IR also makes it possible to form judgments about the composition as well as shape and size of objects because different materials generate heat in different frequencies. Radar imagery can “look” through poor weather conditions, although it is best for imaging solid objects such as buildings and vehicles. Nonvisible wavelength imagery is termed either hyperspectral imagery or multispectral scanning. IMINT may be collected at ground level by elements of the uniformed services engaged in reconnaissance or surveillance and from above using air-breathing or space-based platforms much like SIGINT. Indeed, many satellites carry both imagery and SIGINT sensor suites. Satellites have the particular advantage for imagery purposes that they can legally overfly foreign countries in space, but aircraft are not allowed to enter a foreign country’s sovereign airspace without permission. Imagery intelligence is chiefly limited to that which can be observed. It is also vulnerable to denial and deception through concealment and what is called spoofing through the use of false or notional equipment and facilities such as phony 221 tanks made of wood or empty buildings prepared to appear in active use. Although innovations in imagery are constantly made to penetrate them, denial and deception techniques also continuously develop and usually cost an order of magnitude or more or less than the imagery platform and its sensors. Moreover, high-resolution systems such as the U.S. KEYHOLE satellites or the Russian Zenit and Yantar systems are exceptionally expensive to build (in the late 1980s, the KEYHOLE 12/Improved Crystal satellites reportedly cost approximately one billion dollars each), and it is costly in fuel to alter their orbit to cover any new target. Consequently, they only operate in comparatively small numbers. Measurements and signatures intelligence (MASINT) is a very wide category that subsumes gathering and interpreting chemical or radioisotope signatures from sources such as air, soil, or water samples that may indicate particular weapons development, manufacture, and testing; information from active or passive sonar surveillance systems; and detecting and measuring seismic signals to detect and measure underground nuclear tests. Philip H. J. Davies See also Central Intelligence Agency; Intelligence Further Readings Burrows, W. (1988). Deep black: The startling truth behind America’s top-secret spy satellites. New York: Berkley. Herman, M. (1996). Intelligence power in peace and war. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Lowenthal, M. (2006). Intelligence: From secrets to policy. Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly Press. Shulsy, A. N., & Schmitt, G. J. (2002). Silent warfare: Understanding the world of intelligence (3rd ed.). Washington, DC: Brassey’s. ESSENTIALLY CONTESTED CONCEPT Power is often described as an essentially contested concept. That term was first introduced into political theory in 1958 by William Gallie, who applies it to various subject-terms including 222 Essentially Contested Concept power. In some hands, the use of the idea of an essentially contested concept is taken to entail that the meaning of words such as power or interests has not been universally agreed. The terms have been discussed for many years, so the lack of consensus suggests that there will never be any agreement. However, there are many scientific terms about which there has been much debate and whose meaning in standard definitions has altered over the years. In physics, the concept of atoms has changed over time, and the central concept of gene in evolutionary theory has several meanings that are much debated. However, physicists and evolutionary biologists do not normally consider their concepts to be “essentially contested.” Rather, essentially contested concepts are not merely those over which there happens to be no agreement over a long time, but those that because of their central role in normative theory can never achieve a universally agreed definition. The claim that power has an ineradicably normative nature leads many to suggest that there can never be agreement over its meaning. If we take the term essential seriously in the idea of an essentially contested concept, then we are suggesting that some terms are necessarily of their nature contestable (and perhaps we should replace “contested” with “contestable” in such discussion). This would mean that even if people do reach agreement, they can never do so decisively; there will always be the possibility that someone can come up with a reason for challenging the definition. As William Connolly maintains, universal criteria for relevant reasons to accept a definition do not suffice to completely settle any debate. In The Terms of Political Discourse, Connolly sets out three criteria for essential contestability. First, that there is no settled agreement; second, that future attempts will fail; and third, that there are good reasons why such attempts will fail. The third makes contestation into essential contestability. That there can be no decisive agreement might derive from two processes. The first is that there is no empirical evidence that could prove one account of, say, the power structure, over another. The claim here is that empirical evidence will always fail to allow the possibility of agreement. We might illustrate this claim with the old community power debate. In that debate, pluralists maintain one vision of the power structure; elitists maintain another view. Both recognize that within democracies politicians have to consider the views of the masses; otherwise, the politicians will be thrown out of office. Both recognize that democracy is better than dictatorship. However, pluralists maintain that power is generally dispersed among competing elites who represent the interests of different groups, that the same group does not dominate in all issue areas, and that there is some competition between groups within issue areas. Elitists maintain that the same sets of people dominate in all issue-areas and govern in their own interests. One might think that empirical evidence could decide between these competing views. We could see if the elites form one reference group or several. We could examine the circulation of elites. However, the two sides might disagree about what counts as circulation of elites and so whether there is one reference group or many. For example, both might agree that it is not the same individuals in positions of power, but elitists claim that they all come from the same social class and that whatever else they do, they protect the interests of that class. So both might recognize that different people exist in different issue areas but differ in their interpretation of whether those elites form one reference group or several. And they may differ about whether the elites govern almost exclusively in their own interest (and only support the interests of others to the extent the interests of the elite and the mass coincide). Here, the disagreement is over the meaning of elite in terms of reference group and in terms of interest. Even then, we might go farther. Pluralists might suggest that the elites do, by and large, govern in the interests of the masses because, once policies are put to the masses, most (and not always the same majority) support those policies. The elitists then maintain that surveys and polls are not decisive because we have to examine why people support those policies. People might not have full information; they might be mistaken about their own interests because of propaganda from the elites in positions of power. In this simplification of this community power debate, therefore, we can see that judgment or the empirical evidence is complicated by disagreement about the application of several terms such as elite, interests, and power. One possible solution is to see the terms in the rival accounts as terms within that theory, so the Exchange Theory terms elite, interests, and so on, can be marked relative to a theoretical claim. Hence, we have “elitep” and “elitee” for elites as understood by pluralists and elitists, with similar definitions for all other terms in the rival accounts. In that way, we do not have essential contestability over the concepts, though we might still have rival interpretations of the nature of the power structure. But what is the nature of that disagreement? One side cannot maintain the other is wrong in their claims if, given their definition of the terms, the power structure is correctly described, even though it is correctly described in the terms of the other theory. Without some common set of agreements about terms and their entailments, all we have are different theories. They are not even rival different theories. This leads to relativism, understood as the thesis that there is no truth of the matter in such cases, only underdetermined descriptions. One way the two views might be made to appear rivals is in terms of our normative attitudes toward them. The elitists generally believe that the structure of power in society is wrong, and power should be more dispersed. The pluralists are more sanguine because they believe that power is already dispersed. However, unless they agree over what dispersed means—and they are not likely to because the term power is assumed to be essentially contested—all we are left with are rival normative views, rather than rival empirical accounts. This constitutes the second reason why essentially contested concepts are thought to be so: that people have different normative commitments and they cannot reach agreement over those commitments. They might appear to agree that, for example, equality is good, or that power should be dispersed, but simply disagree over the empirical provenance of those terms. Keith Dowding See also Community Power Debate; Elite Theories; Interests; Pluralism Further Readings Connolly, W. E. (1983). The terms of political discourse. Oxford, UK: Martin Robertson. Gallie, W. (1962). Essentially contested concepts. In M. Black (Ed.), The importance of language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. 223 EXCHANGE THEORY Exchange theory was developed by social psychologists and sociologists to model human relationships as forms of reciprocal trade. People give things to each other to get things back. When I give a gift to a friend, I do so for exchange reasons, not necessarily to receive a gift but perhaps, say, out of gratitude and to further friendship through conversation. Exchange theorists model these exchanges much as economists model trade or bargaining. People who trade can create value by exchanging in a mutually beneficial way, but they might have divergent interests with regard to the precise nature of the trade in the sense that they place different valuations on the commodity being traded. The difference in valuation is the potential surplus created through trade, and this gives both the incentives to exchange. However, each might have an incentive to pretend to value the exchange less than they really do to gain extra from the trade. For example, one lover might pretend he is less enamored of his partner than he really is, to extract more care and attention from her. He might lead her to believe that if she does not give complete devotion he might leave the relationship, whereas he would show her complete devotion if he thought she was about to leave him. In economic terms, the two lovers have a common interest in the production of the “love surplus” but diametrically opposed interests with regard to its distribution. In standard (pre-game-theoretic) economic discussions of trade, power takes almost no role. All we have are two partners who can trade for mutual advantage. However, most people would see a potential power relationship in the previous discussion. Imagine for a moment two potential lovers. The first (a man, say) is desperate for the affection of the other, but the second (a woman) is relatively indifferent to the affection of the first. The asymmetry with regard to distribution of affection means that the second lover can demand great attention from the first while giving relatively little in return. Observing such a relationship, we might say she has a great hold over him: she has the power to force him to behave in ways that he would prefer not to. She will not let him go to the sporting events he would like to attend, mix with his old friends, and so on. There is an exchange going on, one that 224 Exclusion (by assumption) he prefers to not having this exchange at all, but one that disadvantages him relative to her. In other words, she gains more than he does because she values the exchange less. Exchange theory deals with these types of asymmetrical power relationships by examining the nature of trades with regard to the equity. In exchange theory, if both parties have similar attitudes toward equitable exchange—that is, both (a) hold the same beliefs about relative profit and (b) hold the same beliefs about equitable exchange—then inequitable social exchange will not continue in the long term because one party might feel annoyed and the other guilty. More interesting for social exchange theory is where the parties do not have similar attitudes. This is seen in the example given earlier, where the beliefs of the parties about the relative profit vary drastically. However, third parties (the friends of the two lovers, for example) might have similar attitudes toward relative profit and, hence, see one partner as exploiting the other. In social exchange theory, therefore, the degree of power of partners in social exchanges is measured relative to the valuations of the profits of the exchanging parties. Love is a good example precisely because “love is blind” and being in love might make one oblivious to what one would ordinarily see as exploitation. In retrospect, one might realize that a partner had great power over one and regret the inequitable exchange that one accepted at the time. In exchange theory, the degree to which one party can have power over another depends on the degree of dependence that one has on the other. In the “love market,” for example, if there is a shortage of supply of potential female lovers, say, then men would be more dependent on the lover with whom they have managed to enter into social exchange. The price of a loving relationship increases with the shortage of love-exchanging partners. Dependency thus gives power. Sometimes there might be mutual dependency, which should lead to equitable exchange. If there were only two people on a desert island, say, then they would have mutual dependence that might lead to equitable trade over time. However, one important aspect of exchange theory relative to standard economic bargaining models is that people might gain benefit from exchange itself. Thus, the two people on the desert island would not have equitable exchange if one of them valued the exchange relationship itself more than did the other—say she is unable to forage for food as efficiently as he does, or he would be content living alone whereas she needs company. Exchange theory in terms of social relationships has been extended to power dependency theory in political network analysis. Here, organizations are thought to exchange resources (money, influence, information, etc.) for mutual gain. The more powerful organizations are those that are less dependent on the exchange than their partners. Thus, a government regulatory department that had several sources of information about the effects of regulation on its clientele would be less dependent on individual sources than would a department that had only one source of information. Thus, if the regulatory agency depended entirely on the industry or professional body that it was regulating, then the entire power over regulations would lie with those being regulated. Similarly, dependency theory has been applied to exchange relationships between nations and international organizations. Keith Dowding See also Bargaining; Chicken Games; Dependency Theory in International Relations; Exploitation; Networks, Power in; Networks and Communities Further Readings Blau, P. (1964). Exchange and power in social life. New York: John Wiley. Coleman, J. (1991). Foundations of social theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cook, K. S., & Emerson, R. M. (1978). Power, equity and commitment in exchange networks. American Sociological Review, 43, 721–739. Homans, G. C. (1961). Social relations: Its elementary forms. New York: Harcourt Brace. EXCLUSION The concept of exclusion has risen to prominence in policy debate and academic research since the 1980s. The discovery of a “new” poverty at that time, characterized by growing long-term unemployment, an increased strain on welfare systems, and a proliferation of demands for social justice, Exclusion created an unstable political context and a concomitant struggle to define a program of action. This has seen the new poverty accounted for in three distinct ways. One focuses on the emergence of an underclass, denoting a body of people who have fallen beneath the conventional class structure. This does not simply add a new layer of stratification to modern industrial societies, for the dominant account of the underclass is of a body of people who are unable or unwilling to support themselves other then through crime, welfare, and sporadic employment in the informal economy. A second account focuses on the problem of social cohesion, which is framed by the challenges posed by globalization, and in particular the impact of market liberalization on national economies and the organization of public services. Here, the main concern is how to implement reforms without creating inequalities that might lead to social fragmentation and a loss of political legitimacy. Finally, the third account reemphasizes relations of domination, exploitation, and discrimination long associated with coercive state power, capitalist relations, patriarchy, and racism. These are very different ways of interpreting poverty and inequality today, and all are gathered into the concept of exclusion, which raises the question of whether and how such a contested concept might be used for the purpose of social and political analysis. One way of handling this diversity is to retain it, so that the different (and at times competing) accounts are examined as discourses. A discourse can be defined as a relational field of meanings that is constituted by and constitutive of a particular social context, and within which knowledge and practice intersect and interact with other discourses. In this way, exclusion can be seen to articulate a number of strategies and programs that together constitute a field of political struggle. Power and the Excluded Each of the three discourses sketched can be presented as a statement about the excluded that is both diagnostic and evaluative: 1. The excluded have opted out. 2. The excluded have been left out. 3. The excluded have been kept out. 225 The third statement, which is generally expressed by the political Left, has the most to say in connecting exclusion specifically to power. This is because the Left has tended to derive an understanding of power from a Marxist conception of ideology, of state, and of social relations. However, when examined as a discourse, each statement can be seen to adopt a distinct position on power relations. 1. The core argument is that the excluded belong to an underclass that has become disconnected from, and may even actively oppose, social norms and the rule of law. Whether because of lack of ability or willingness to exercise responsibility and self-discipline, the underclass poses a threat to social order. Assuming a moral decline, of which the underclass is merely the most visible manifestation, the discourse articulates a negativesum view of power relations, identifying the egalitarian aspirations of state welfare and affirmative action programs as primary causes. The central thesis is that far from eradicating poverty and inequality in the structure of opportunities, mechanisms of redistribution actually socialize the poor and the less capable into habits of dependency, which in turn erodes social power while fostering conditions that are conducive to criminality. 2. The core argument is that the excluded are the unfortunate and unintended victims of modernization, which is to say that they have been disadvantaged or marginalized by changes that have occurred in the context of late modernity. As a sociological thesis of unintended effects, this is a discourse of renewal and reform that finds its clearest formulation in the post-left–right third way politics. The central thesis is that we are on the cusp of a new age, with a new economy that can benefit everyone if, and only if, each and all recognize that they have responsibilities as well as rights. The discourse articulates a positive-sum view of power relations that links individual empowerment to social empowerment, devolving responsibility to the individual, transforming the citizen into a consumer of public and private services, and encouraging self-help and mutual assistance in the form of familial and community relations. 3. The core argument is that the excluded are a new servant class subjected to a global economy that operates in the interests of the dominant 226 Exclusion consumer classes, nations, and global regions. The discourse articulates a zero-sum view of power relations, and it identifies the “new” poor as migrant communities, ethnic minorities, solo mothers, and other marginalized groups who depend on sweatshop labor and low-paid service sector work. Furthermore, against the idea that the underclass is a collection of criminal and feckless individuals, it is argued that the impoverished conditions once associated with the third world are now found in the ghettos of first world countries, with the new poor blamed for their poverty, or at the very least made responsible for it, through neoliberal reforms that are making welfare entitlements tentative and conditional on participation in training programs and make-work schemes. Although each of these discourses provides a specific account of power and exclusion, they all converge on the more general problem of order. Power, Order, and Exclusion At the most general level of analysis, the concept of exclusion evokes a conception of order that is based on a relation between an inside (inclusion, the included) and an outside (exclusion, the excluded). Between one and the other is a relation of difference and division, which raises the question of how such frontiers are constituted and instituted. The study of nationalism and ethnicity has produced an impressive literature on how populations, cultures, states, and territories are ordered into discreet entities through the construction of divisions and differences, the boundaries of which have given rise to the bloodiest conflicts in history. A more wide-ranging approach to this problematic can be found in the poststructuralist literature. Poststructuralist theory proposes that any ordered field or system—whether a discourse, a social order, or the international system of nation-states—is constituted through exclusion. The basic premise (drawing on Jacques Derrida’s notion of différance) is that each element within a system of elements defers meaning to itself by differing from the others. Chess is a good way of illustrating this point. If we want to explain chess to someone who knows nothing about the game, then it becomes clear that explaining what the rook can do is pretty meaningless unless we define the rook in relation to the knight, the bishop, and all the other pieces. The chessboard supports a definite universe of identities, dispositions, and relations that are constituted through difference. When we move to the study of social order, then there are three important added dimensions: first, when taken as a whole, the system of elements can be conceptualized as a field of power relations; second, this field has been constituted through struggle and strategy; and third, order, which is the outcome of struggle, is constituted through the deferral or exclusion of some meanings and the inclusion of others. In this way, it can be argued that any ordered field or system is constituted by what it excludes, which is also to say that there is no order without exclusion. At this level of abstraction, the outside of order is essentially beyond language and representation: it is simply a horizon of deferred meanings that renders order unstable. The questions that follow are “how” questions: how is order actually created, how does it endure, how is it transformed? Studies inspired by the work of Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe have shown that order is accomplished through hegemony, which stabilizes the field by constructing a specific representation of the inside– outside relation. From a Western perspective, the most pertinent example today is the war on terror. In contrast to terrorist and terrorism, both of which can be given tangible form, terror is a bottomless discursive vessel that can be can be endlessly filled with meaning. As a purely negative symbol, terror is used to constitute a united inside that must be defended. Representations of this inside, such as “the coalition of the willing” or “the free world,” are symbolically charged and yet, like terror, remain essentially vague. In the same way, the political Right has waged a reasonably successful campaign against affirmative action and welfare in the United States by shaping the discourse of the underclass as an immanent threat. In Europe, however, the discourse of cohesion has become hegemonic, and although this may suggest a more egalitarian social democratic ethos, policy is focused on employability rather than on redistribution as the solution to exclusion. An alternative, though related, approach to the study of power, order, and exclusion is inspired by the genealogical method of critique developed by Michel Foucault. An example would be an analysis Exclusion of liberal government and exclusion. In postEnlightenment Europe, J. S. Mill could reasonably assert that there was a natural incompatibility between subjection to the will of others and selfgovernment. However, he also argued that the doctrine of liberty had definite limits: it did not apply to children and it did not apply to childlike or “primitive” cultures. His point was that neither was (yet) capable of self-government, so that in both cases the correct and legitimate mode of government was a benevolent form of despotism. In other words, children and childlike cultures must acquire the arts of self-government, which assumes a willingness and ability to learn. The argument, which is derived from universal claims about human reason and the equal moral worth of all individuals, reflected a widely held evolutionary theory of social change. And it was precisely this claim to the universal that constituted the exception to Mill’s axiom of self-government. Not all people were capable of practicing freedom and so, in the name of reason, civilization, and progress, the bodies and minds of children and childlike adults—or the capacity for action that is human life—was to be acted on. But acted on how, and by whom? The answer, at least in principle, was education. If those to be subjected to education and training were capable of self-government, then in time they would benefit from the freedoms that a liberal order bestows on its subjects. Freedom was made contingent on the willingness to learn and the ability to comply with specific norms of conduct, with the ideal subject of liberal order both a self-supporting laborer and a responsible citizen. The autonomy so dear to liberals turns out to be a mode of self-discipline, which can also be imposed by external authorities. This is an example of how knowledge is transformed into a regime of truth, not through the design of individuals such as Mill, but as discourses are assembled from struggles and strategies. The consistency of Mill’s position is found in the way that he assumes all people everywhere to be capable of self-government. What makes the adult of the civilized society different from children and primitives is not a question of essence; it is simply that the minds of children and the mentality of childlike peoples are less developed. And yet Mill’s argument belongs to a system of knowledge that is constructed against an outside that is made into an 227 inferior reflection of itself. Classical liberal government was built on illiberal foundations, and yet this was concealed by projecting a socially constructed hierarchy onto a temporal axis so that it became part of the natural order of things. This type of analysis shows that the subject of liberal order was not given by nature only to be discovered during the age of Enlightenment. Instead, the subject was made within a tapestry of disciplinary powers that began with the child and the primitive and expanded through the growth of medicine, psychiatry, education, social work, charity, and child rescue. Furthermore, although liberalism is often associated with the impartial rule of law, in practice a liberal order deploys law and norm in dividing the population and excluding certain people from the status of the autonomous and rational individual. During the 19th century, paupers were subjected to the harsh conditions of the state-administered workhouse, unmarried mothers to private Magdalen asylums, juvenile delinquents to reformatories, and the children of the “perishing classes” to industrial schools. Likewise, the insane, the mentally defective, inebriates, and others perceived to be childlike or primitive in their habits were also excluded in the name of security, order, and progress. Whether coded as care, cure, or control, the effect of these social technologies was to construct a universe of subjects who collectively populated the margin of order and defined its internal limits. And as this margin was carried into the 20th century, so it became the focus of professional social work and the welfare state, as well as of more sinister strategies. Alert for defective minds, deficient bodies, malformed character, and dangerous dispositions that might corrupt the individual and degrade the population, the authorities policing the margin confronted some of the fundamental questions of the day: should the delinquent, the defective, and the depraved be left to their own devices in the hope that they would eventually die out? Could they be cured? Was it better to place them in custody so that the risk of procreation was controlled? Or the most insidious of all: should they be exterminated, either through selective sterilization, or collectively, by applying the techniques of bureaucratic organization and industrial production to the task of purification? In the wake of the Holocaust, there was some effort involved in opposing 228 Executive Power the egalitarian strategy of the welfare state to the brutal techniques of eugenics, but this tends to overlook the fact that both are examples of what Foucault called biopower, or sociopolitical technologies that act on life and living populations. More recently, and coinciding with the changes and challenges sketched earlier—the discovery of a new poverty, an increased strain on welfare systems, and a proliferation of demands for social justice—the exclusions that operated through incarceration have been challenged. Although this has had a limited impact on the prison, there has nonetheless been a general trend away from custody and detention to care and treatment within the community. A question for analysts today is whether social inclusion is a form of empowerment, a new mode of control, or both simultaneously. Order Without Exclusion? In contrast to the distinctly modern projects of emancipation and equality, the prevalence of debate on inclusion and exclusion suggests a shift away from the pursuit of a final emancipation or end-state of achieved equality. This is coincident with a range of debates on postmodernity, late modernity, and a second or reflexive modernity. A mode of social organization might be emerging that is predicated on the insight that exclusion is the condition of possibility for order, and that order can never be more than provisional because the standing conditions that structure and stabilize social relations are contingent on political struggle. Kevin Ryan See also Discourse; Domination; Foucault, Michel; Hegemony; Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal Further Readings Bauman, Z. (1998). Work, consumerism and the new poor. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press. Garland, D. (2001). The culture of control. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Levitas, R. (1998). The inclusive society? Social exclusion and New Labour. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave. Ryan, K. (2007). Social exclusion and the politics of order. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. EXECUTIVE POWER The separation of powers theory, as developed by the 18th-century French political philosopher Charles-Louis de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu, distinguishes between executive, legislative, and judiciary power as three branches of government that are not to infringe on each other’s constitutionally vested competences. The executive consists of a government, its ministerial bureaucracy, and subordinate governmental agencies. The separation of powers doctrine more or less accurately describes power relationships in presidential systems, but in parliamentary systems, executive and legislative powers are fused because the executive’s capacity to govern depends on the parliamentary majority’s willingness to support it. In place of an institutional separation of powers, parliamentary systems are therefore characterized by a functional division of powers between the government majority and the opposition. All this is only empirically relevant in democratic political systems because in autocratic regimes formal allocation of powers has no systematic consequences for how real power is executed by dictators, ruling parties, or military juntas. The executive power is the authority to enforce laws and to ensure that they are implemented as intended. Organizational structures to carry out these functions vary considerably. Intragovernmental relationships in presidential systems vary between a clearly dominant president with subordinate departmental chiefs in the United States and a more evenly balanced power structure in some of the Latin American countries. In parliamentary systems, the role of the prime minister varies relative to ministers, depending on cabinet manuals or informal traditions and on whether the government is formed by just one party or is a coalition government. Whereas the British prime minister is clearly first among equals, the constitutional position of the German federal chancellor with his or her competence on guidelines is politically limited because the chancellor has to respect the autonomy of his or her coalition partner(s). In other parliamentary democracies, Italy being a good example, the prime minister has virtually no prerogative competences at all. In addition, presidents in presidential systems combine the roles of head of Exercise Fallacy state and head of government, whereas in parliamentary systems with their dual executive, there exist elected presidents or monarchs as heads of state alongside the prime minister. In some instances, these presidents hold real political power that has given rise to a—however heavily debated—new type of democratic governance: semi-presidentialism. The relationship between the government, no matter how power is internally allocated, and the bureaucracy has traditionally been seen as hierarchically structured. On this account, ministers are seen as principals who rely on ministerial civil servants and agencies as agents with all the agency loss problems that delegation of power relationships implies. Parallel to delegation theory, which studies the opportunities to prevent or minimize agency loss and to maintain political control of bureaucratic implementation, core executive studies have recently begun to criticize the traditional hierarchical accounts of the interorganizational structure of the executive by pointing out that network governance may be a more appropriate concept. André Kaiser See also Legislative Power; Prime Ministerial and Presidential; Separation of Powers Further Readings Dunleavy, P., & Rhodes, R. A. W. (2007). Core executive studies in Britain. Public Administration, 68(1), 3–28. Mainwaring, S., & Shugart, M S. (1997). Presidentialism and democracy in Latin America. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Weller, P. (1985). First among equals: Prime ministers in Westminster systems. London: George Allen & Unwin. EXERCISE FALLACY Exercise fallacy was coined by Peter Morriss, from a point made by Anthony Kenny. Both authors start from the recognition that power refers to a capacity or disposition, rather than to an event or occurrence. Philosophers who have investigated how we should understand the meanings of such dispositional terms have started with 229 simple natural powers, such as “soluble.” To say that sugar is soluble in water is to say (something like) that if sugar is put into water, it will dissolve. This does not describe any event that has occurred; it is a claim about what would happen if such an event did occur. What is meant by saying, “This sugar lump is soluble in water,” is very different from what is meant by saying, “This sugar lump has dissolved in water.” Or, in Kenny’s example, whisky only begins to exercise the power to intoxicate after it is imbibed, but it possesses this power even when it is sitting harmlessly in the bottle. The power endures. Ignoring this distinction—to think that a power can only exist when it is being exercised—is to commit the exercise fallacy. Both philosophers and social scientists have been tempted by the exercise fallacy. The motivation for doing so of many philosophers (and some social scientists) has been a wish to rid our language of unscientific metaphysical ideas, such as an immortal soul or a spirit of the age driving history. This led to the view that we can only meaningfully talk about what we can observe. Postwar social scientists were much influenced by this empiricist trend in philosophy. They similarly wanted to rid social science of much of what they considered to be metaphysical nonsense. Thus, the behaviorist school wanted to limit social science (particularly psychology) to talk about behavior, and thus remove the “unscientific” focus on mental events, which were necessarily unobservable, and therefore perhaps not there at all. Behavioralism in political science demanded a similarly pared-down vocabulary. And that led to the exercise fallacy in political science. Thus, Robert Dahl (among others) claimed that to say that someone had power was to say no more than that that person was causing something to happen. But this is false: just as the whisky’s power exists when the whisky is not being drunk, so does the president’s power exist when he or she is not doing anything with it. More recently another influential, and very different, school in social science has taken to committing the exercise fallacy: disciples of Michel Foucault. This is partly because of an elementary blunder in translation, in which two, quite different, French words—pouvoir, which denotes the action, and puissance, which designates something lasting and permanent—are both rendered by the English word power. This has resulted in its 230 Exit and Voice as Forms of Power becoming an orthodoxy, among Foucauldians writing in English, that power exists only when it is exercised. Thus, the exercise fallacy has returned in this banal and uninteresting form. Peter Morriss See also Ability; Ableness; Dahl, Robert A.; Foucault, Michel; Morriss, Peter; Vehicle Fallacy Further Readings Kenny, A. (1975). Will, freedom and power. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Morriss, P. (2002). Power: A philosophical analysis (2nd ed.). Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. EXIT AND VOICE AS FORMS OF POWER If you want others to do as you wish, you can ask them, or threaten them in some way. In certain circumstances, a threat to walk away can make asking someone more likely to succeed. Albert Hirschman made this point well in his famous book Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (1970). The basic idea is quite simple: people or organizations have two main responses to the decline in the quality of a product. They may voice, such as complain, or exit by buying another company’s product. This insight extends to a variety of situations where people became dissatisfied, such as consumers of public services, members of political parties, or as employees, and in each situation people use the voice and exit options open to them. Hirschman did not just describe these actions; he argued that they might be rival options, or complementary ones. People might trade off voice and exit; if exit is easy and cheap, then people tend to voice less when they have an exit option. The threat of losing customers helps keep organizations such as business firms on their toes; losing customers affects their profit line. In that sense, the market power of consumers is their exit strategy, and the individual power of a consumer is the threat of exit. A trade union gains power of voice in negotiating with management with the threat of pulling workers out of their jobs. But entities other than firms in a competitive market might be more sanguine about the possibility of people exiting. An authoritarian regime might be happy to allow citizens to leave rather than give them a voice. In that sense, the salience of exit and voice may give more power to those who are already not responsive and who do not like competition. Individuals who leave are not exercising power because their exit shows they have failed to get a response from their target. Only the threat of exit is a power resource, and it only works if the target cares about the exit of the person. There are many situations where individuals can trade off exit–voice to their advantage and wield power. For one, they can use their potential for exit to make their voices heard. Discontented employees know about this weapon very well: even hinting they might leave their job can be an easy way to get better terms and conditions and to avoid the costs of leaving. Sometimes the possibility of exit means that the individual can voice more strongly, in what is called “noisy exit.” Critics of authoritarian regimes, such as of the former German Democratic Republic, can protest more effectively if they know they can leave. Alternatively, consumers or citizens are reluctant to exit because they have loyalty, so they voice with added passion. Loyalists might voice even more strongly when others are leaving because they can point to the destructive effects of exit. And those on their way out can give a signal to the rest left behind. So even though voice weakens in the face of exit, the threat of exit can strengthen voice in some circumstances. The key insight is that the ingenuity people display in communicating their options to the powerful allows them to increase their influence. Peter John See also Bargaining; Free Market; Loyalty; Threats; Trade Further Readings Dowding, K., John, P., Mergoupis, T., & Van Vugt, M. (2000). Exit, voice, and loyalty: Analytic and empirical developments. European Journal of Political Research, 37(4), 469–495. Hirschman, A. O. (1970). Exit, voice, and loyalty: Responses to decline in firms, organizations and states. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Expectancy Confirmation, Power and EXPECTANCY CONFIRMATION, POWER AND When people interact with others, they often use preconceived beliefs and expectations as guides to action. Their actions, in turn, may prompt interaction partners to behave in ways that confirm initial beliefs. This phenomenon, in which belief creates reality, is known by several names—the self-fulfilling prophecy, expectancy confirmation, and behavioral confirmation (terminology that emphasizes how the target’s actual behavior confirms the perceiver’s initial beliefs). The behavioral confirmation scenario has been demonstrated in a series of empirical investigations in which a person (the perceiver), having adopted erroneous beliefs about another person (the target), acts in ways that cause the behavior of the target to confirm the perceiver’s expectations. Considerable evidence suggests behavioral confirmation effects are robust and generalize over a wide range of expectations and interaction contexts. Moreover, research has demonstrated that power plays a possible causal role in this interplay of belief and behavior in several compelling ways: those with expectations tend to hold positions of power, the motivations of powerful perceivers differ from those of powerless targets, behavioral conformation is particularly likely within interactions between powerful perceivers and powerless targets, and expectations themselves create a sense of relative power thereby turning perceivers into powerful perceivers. One way that power may be implicated in behavioral confirmation is that those with expectations are often those in positions of power. One can readily think of a variety of situations with powerful perceivers and less powerful targets. For example, teachers, interviewers, employers, and therapists all have positions of power and are apt to have expectations about others with less power. Moreover, these positions of power often make expectations relevant; for example, teachers may rely on expectations about student performance to guide their teaching efforts, employers may rely on expectations in supervising employees, and therapists may draw on expectations in designing therapeutic strategies. Thus, it may be particularly likely that people in positions of power are guided by 231 their expectations in dealing with those of lesser power. Moreover, research by Mark Snyder and Julie Haugen indicates that the motivations of perceivers often differ from those of targets and these differences set the stage for behavioral confirmation. Typically, the motivation of perceivers is to “get to know” the target and this motivation leads perceivers to use expectations as a guide for their interactions, as those in positions of high power rely more on stereotyped expectations in their dealings with persons of lesser power. For example, a perceiver interviewing someone expected to be tardy is likely to ask about the times the target had been late in the last month; any affirmative response confirms the initial expectation of tardiness. Further, because of the power associated with the position of interviewer, the interviewer may have ample opportunity to direct the interaction based on his or her expectations, choosing the interview topics that are addressed and making it difficult for the target to avoid discussion areas that might not confirm the perceiver’s expectations. By contrast, the motivation of the target is often “to get along” with the perceiver. This motivation leads targets to acquiesce to whatever inquiries a perceiver directs at the target and not attempt to redirect the conversation. Even if targets are aware of negative expectations held about them, they put themselves at risk attempting to disconfirm the expectations that perceivers hold about them. In general, people are not pleased when their expectations are disconfirmed. Thus, targets may actively confirm expectations in an effort to please and “get along” with the powerful perceiver. Furthermore, the net effect of the interrelations between power, motivation, and the roles of perceiver and target is that behavioral confirmation is particularly likely in interactions that involve a powerful perceiver and a powerless target. In his research, John Copeland demonstrated that power can be created in the laboratory and can be as simple as making a decision about whether someone else should continue in an experiment. Thus, in the classic perceiver/target experimental paradigm, when the power to decide whether the other participant will have the opportunity to earn a reward in a subsequent phase of the experiment is assigned to the perceiver, behavioral confirmation occurs; however, when this kind of explicit social power is 232 Exploitation given to the target, the perceiver’s expectation has no effect on the behavior of the target. In addition, motivation follows power, such that the person with the power is motivated to get to know the other person; when that person is the perceiver, he or she acts on expectations and treats the target in ways that elicit behavioral confirmation. Finally, power confers the opportunity and ability to have one’s expectations confirmed; the expectations themselves confer a sense of power on those who hold them. In experimental settings, Austin Baldwin, Marc Kiviniemi, and Mark Snyder found that the simple act of providing an expectation about an anticipated interaction partner is sufficient to elicit feelings of power over that person. This sense of power comes from feeling that one knows something about someone else and that this knowledge will be of use in social interaction. This effect seems particularly pronounced when the knowledge associated with holding an expectation confers a sense of relative advantage (i.e., that one knows something about the other person that the other person does not know about oneself). The intricate interplay of expectations, power, and behavioral confirmation is not only of theoretical significance, but has “real world” implications too. Every day, people encounter others who have stereotypes, have implicit and explicit biases, or simply have access to information about them. These a priori expectations are often erroneous and, perhaps more often than not, are in the hands of those who have some sort of power. Whether it is the teacher with overt expectations about what minority children are capable of, or the prospective employer who is scrutinizing the résumé of a job applicant eagerly seeking employment, a powerful perceiver’s expectations are likely to affect the target’s behavior and consequently his or her opportunity for success. Mark Snyder and Jennifer Filson See also Knowledge and Power; Relational Power; Social Power Further Readings Snyder, M., & Stukas, A. (1999). Interpersonal processes: The interplay of cognitive, motivational, and behavioral activities in social interaction. Annual Review of Psychology, 50, 273–303. Snyder, M., Tanke, E., & Berscheid, E. (1977). Social perception and interpersonal behavior: On the selffulfilling nature of social stereotypes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 656–666. EXPLOITATION To exploit something in the most general sense of the term simply means to make use of it. Especially with regard to natural resources, exploitation tends to refer to consumption only. What makes the concept a basic one of social critique and theoretically controversial is that apart from this value-neutral meaning, exploitation can also be used pejoratively. In social theory, the concept of exploitation is usually used to characterize social relations in which an actor or category of actors uses others for their own ends because of a fundamentally asymmetric power relationship between them. Accordingly, most authors define exploitation as taking advantage of another person unfairly, that is, as using someone who, because of his or her disadvantaged and inferior position, has to comply with the exploiter’s will. However, the classic and most influential theorist of exploitation, namely Karl Marx, did not share this standard account of the concept. Marx: Surplus Labor and Surplus Value Marx’s account differed in two ways. First, Marx explicitly rejected the moral framing characteristic of the standard notion of exploitation. Second, he restricted the concept to the field of labor relations. Most disputes about the concept of exploitation center around these two issues. The first concerns the status of the concept of exploitation: what is the function of the notion of exploitation in social theory? The second issue concerns the range of social phenomena to which the concept of exploitation is applicable: which social relations can be exploitative? Marx identified exploitation as the appropriation of another’s surplus labor. Surplus labor is the amount of labor exceeding what is necessary for the reproduction of the worker’s labor power, that Exploitation is, for producing the worker’s living conditions sufficient for the worker’s capability to keep on working. Appropriation of surplus labor is by no means specific to capitalist societies. It is rooted in forced labor and just changes in form in relation to the different ways forced labor has historically been organized in societies. In slaveholder and feudal societies, exploitation as the appropriation of surplus labor occurred in the form of a direct appropriation of surplus labor or in the form of a requisition of the surplus product, respectively. Leaving aside that the institution of slavery disguises the fact that not all of the slave’s labor is exploited insofar as the exploiter is interested in the reproduction of the slave’s labor power, to Marx there is nothing mysterious about these historically prevalent forms of exploitation. What is enigmatic is rather how exploitation can occur within capitalist societies given that these societies, in principle, have abolished forced labor and rest on free labor, instead. The Marxian theory of exploitation is intended to solve this riddle. Marx’s analysis of capitalist exploitation centers around his notion of the “doubly free worker”: Under capitalist conditions, the worker is free in the first sense of being the owner of his labor power, legally uncoerced to work for another apart from contractual labor relations the worker enters into at his or her discretion; the worker is free also in the second sense of being free from any means of production, hence, undermining the worker’s freedom in the first sense, necessitated to sell his or her labor power to make a living. Nonetheless, neither is the surplus labor nor the surplus product of the worker directly appropriated by another under capitalist conditions. The free worker is not exploited in the same way as the slave and the serf. How can the worker be exploited at all? How is it possible that capitalists appropriate free workers’ surplus labor? The mystery resides in the fact that under capitalist conditions goods appear as commodities insofar as they are primarily produced for the market, and all goods can, in principle, be converted into each other (by monetary means) through economic transactions. Therefore, all these transactions have to take the form of an exchange of equivalents. The commodity of labor power is no exception to this rule. Marx argues that the capitalist economy functions in such a way that the workers are paid according to the value of their labor 233 power. There is no robbery involved in capitalist labor relations. To explain how capitalist labor relations can embody an exchange of equivalents as well as the capitalists’ appropriation of the workers’ surplus labor, Marx focuses on the specific form surplus labor takes under capitalist conditions, namely surplus value. Capitalist exploitation, then, consists in the appropriation of surplus value. Key to Marx’s notion of surplus value is his analysis of the singular character of the commodity of labor power that is rooted in the labor theory of value he developed on the basis and in critique of classical political economy (most notably Adam Smith and David Ricardo). According to this conception, labor is the sole source of value. Value, Marx states, depends on, but must not be confused with usage value, that is, a good’s particular utility for an actor. In case such goods result from human activity, they have to be understood as products of concrete labor, that is, qualitatively defined labor. Concrete labor—such as, for example, the productive activities of a carpenter and of a weaver—as well as the different usage values of the products are incommensurable, however. Value, in contrast, that allows for the exchangeability of commodities in a market economy (and is realized in economic transactions as exchange value), arises from abstract labor, labor stripped of all qualitative characteristics and determined in purely quantitative terms. Accordingly, the value of a commodity is defined by the (average) amount of labor power necessary for its production. The singular character of the commodity of labor power, then, resides in that its usage value consists in producing value. Labor relations embody an exchange of equivalents insofar as workers are paid whatever is necessary for the reproduction of their labor power; surplus value is produced by consumption of this labor power in excess of the amount necessary for its reproduction, that is, by the worker’s additional working time beyond what would be necessary for his or her reproduction. Being rooted in an exchange of equivalents, no injustice is involved in capitalist exploitation, according to Marx. Yet, the concept of exploitation receives attention just for the reason that it is not normatively neutral. It is intended to identify a wrongness hidden behind the façade of free contractual relations. One reason why Marx did not frame exploitation in normative terms is that he 234 Exploitation believed subjects’ normative assumptions to depend on the socioeconomic conditions prevailing in their society. If, however, one grants more autonomy to the realm of moral argument than the materialist Marxian scheme of society allows for, that is, the scheme of a foundational economic base and an ephemeral superstructure (of politics, law, morality, art, etc.), then the normative ambiguities of the notion of exploitation are open to debate. What kind of wrongness is involved in exploitation? Other Analyses of Exploitation An obvious answer, it would seem, is that because the liberal notion of freedom disguises the social coercion that forces the “free” worker to sell his or her labor power, capitalist labor relations resemble an exchange of equivalents only on the surface; without such coercion workers would own the whole product of their labor. They are actually entitled to this whole product, and the wrongness of exploitation consists precisely in the fact that they receive less than they are entitled to. The normative core of such an understanding of exploitation is a strong notion of self-ownership according to which agents have the basic right freely to dispose of and capitalize on their natural talents. This interpretation of the concept of exploitation has led some authors to claim a close affinity between Marxism and libertarianism; it is fundamental to left-libertarianism and at the heart of an extensive debate on the normative content of exploitation that has taken place within analytical Marxism. The classic contribution to this debate is John Roemer’s influential analysis of exploitation. Roemer uncouples the concept of exploitation from the highly problematic labor theory of value that (in its Marxian as well as Ricardian, etc., variants) had been superseded already in the late 19th century by the neoclassic subjective theory of value based on the concept of marginal utility. Instead of relying on an objective theory of value, Roemer grounds his approach on a theory of property relations. This leads him to define as exploitative all those situations in which actors are worse off than they would be under conditions of an equal distribution of (external) resources. Exploitation, then, arises from distributive inequality, especially the unequal distribution of the means of production. Thus, Roemer’s analysis downsizes the normative weight of exploitation that is made dependent on a theory of just distribution. Indeed, Roemer even advises Marxists to redirect their focus from exploitation to inequalities in the distribution of assets and points to the fact that exploitation only counts for one kind of injustice among others. Confronting the problem how, on the one hand, actors can be conceived of as responsible agents (thereby allowing for legitimate inequalities) while, on the other hand, acknowledging that inequalities have to be remedied by redistributive measures insofar as they arise from conditions that are beyond an individual’s control, he further argues for certain restrictions on self-ownership, the supposed normative core of the Marxian concept of exploitation. The normative implications of the concept of exploitation are qualified by this reconceptualization, but of greater importance are the consequences for its explanatory function. According to Roemer, exploitation might be overcome by redistributive measures; in this regard, there is no difference to the neoclassic notion of exploitation as payment of workers beneath the marginal product of their labor. Marx, in contrast, believed that the private ownership of the means of production must inevitably lead to exploitation for systemic reasons. Hence, redistribution (and, for that matter, any intervention confined to the distributive sphere) must necessarily fall short; only a reorganization of the economic system, that is, the productive sphere, would be suited to eliminate the fundamental wrongness of capitalist societies. In this view, the proposition that exploitation is the fundamental wrongness of capitalist societies does not imply that there are no other kinds of injustice, possibly even of greater harm to those suffering them; it simply means that exploitation is that wrongness that sustains conditions under which suffering is inevitable. Whether convincing in this respect, it is central to Marx’s account of exploitation that it does incorporate an explanation of its systemic causation; such an explanation is in danger of getting lost in Roemer’s reformulation. The latter also applies to another set of conceptual analyses. Besides the extensive debate on exploitation, justice, and self-ownership in analytical Marxism and the discussion about the relevance of coercion and structural factors to exploitation, Exploitation questions about the concept’s normative content have also been raised concerning the issues of consent and harm. Joel Feinberg has argued for a very broad understanding of exploitation and has defined it in terms of gaining from a relationship with another person; such a relationship may rest on consent and does not necessarily involve any harm in the sense of a violation of rights. Subsequently, Alan Wertheimer has claimed that exploitation can involve a moral wrong even if the exploited is not harmed because a social relationship may be mutually advantageous, but less rewarding to one party than it should be. In determining what actors are entitled to, Wertheimer discusses the neoclassic marginal utility principle and develops the concept of a hypothetical fair market price. However, his focus on noneconomic exploitative relationships might be better served by framing the concept of exploitation itself in noneconomic terms. Such an approach has been presented by Robert Goodin, who defines exploitation as taking advantage of another person’s vulnerabilities in an unusual situation and, therefore, in an inappropriate manner. Yet, it has been remarked that Goodin’s commitment to a consequentialist moral theory undermines his assumption that exploitation can be mutually advantageous. Ruth Sample develops an alternative Kantian conception of exploitation as degradation that might be suited to capture mutually advantageous exploitative relations and cases of exploitation the Marxian analysis did not focus on. Debates about exploitation are not limited to the question whether the concept should be interpreted in moral terms and, if so, what its normative content consists of; discussion also gravitates around the problem of identifying the scope of the concept of exploitation. Marx restricted it to labor relations and focused his analysis on capitalist relations of wage labor that he tended to identify with industrial labor relations. Niklas Luhmann has argued that the concept of exploitation is linked to stratified societies and is not applicable to today’s functionally differentiated world society for which the distinction between inclusion and exclusion might turn out to be central; others have argued that current structural transformations render exploitation anything but obsolete. To highlight changes in exploitative labor relations 235 caused by economic globalization, namely the increased power of employers to capitalize on workplace insecurity by threatening to shift production to another country, Pierre Bourdieu has coined the term flexploitation. The shift from industrial to service labor represents another structural change of the economy that has been at the center of a different discussion dating farther back. Disagreement concerns the question whether the labor theory of value, still defended by some, and the concept of surplus value can be applied to white-collar work. In view of recent changes within the field of service labor, the growing importance of immaterial production, and the structural transformation in the direction of knowledge-based societies, Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri have proposed uncoupling the notion of value from quantitative criteria and defining exploitation as the private appropriation of collectively produced value. With this move, Hardt and Negri also aim to do justice to criticisms according to which the concept, whether based on a version of the labor theory of value or not, remains too narrow and blinds us to important cases of exploitation when modeled on capitalist labor relations. Most important, such shortcomings of classic accounts of exploitation have been demonstrated by feminist authors. They have pointed to affective and emotional exploitation in the context of unpaid labor and reproductive activities in the supposedly private sphere of the household and the family. Moreover, the specific vulnerabilities of children and women have been discussed with regard to sexual exploitation. Last but not least, recent developments in biotechnology have put pressure on the distinction between exploitation within social relations and exploitation of natural resources. As this overview indicates, technological trends and structural changes constantly spark new debates. Nor is there a consensus on the scope or on the normative content and the theoretical function of exploitation. It will remain a contested concept. David Strecker See also Capital, Marxist; Critical Theory; False Consciousness; Gender, Role of Power in; Ideology; Justice; Marx, Karl; Marxist Accounts of Power; Social Power; Structural Power; Substructure and Superstructure; Systematic Luck; Systemic Power 236 Extended Deterrence Further Readings Arneson, R. (1981). What’s wrong with exploitation? Ethics, 91, 202–227. Cohen, G. A. (1990). Marxism and contemporary politi