THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF CHILDREN’S RIGHTS international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 brill.com/chil Maturing Children’s Rights Theory From Children, With Children, Of Children Matías Cordero Arce Independent Researcher [email protected] Abstract Children’s rights research is an under-theorised field of studies. The Convention on the Rights of the Child (crc) has gained the status of source and (“theoretical”) framework of research, policy and practice, thus making most research efforts a matter of discussing implementation. This paper wishes to advance a critical, that is, politically committed theoretical agenda for children’s rights research that is not bounded by the institutional framework (i.e. crc) but intends to freely think it. Programmatically, it delves on the following issues, that call for further research, of the like that might start filling in this theoretical void: the position of children’s rights research within the wider interdisciplinary field of childhood studies, children’s citizenship (instead of “participation”), the normative legitimacy of children’s rights/laws, children’s law as a branch of antidiscrimination law, and the necessary independence of children’s laws from children’s sciences. Keywords children’s rights theory – critical legal theory – children’s citizenship – antidiscrimination law – children’s empowerment * A first version of this paper was presented at the meeting of the Mediterranean Network of Children’s Rights, held at the University of Barcelona in September 2013. A more elaborated version was then presented at the Symposium of the Research Network on the Sociology of Childhood, of the European Sociological Association, held at the University of Modena, in May 2014. The author wishes to thank the participants of those meeting and symposium for the discussions and valuable comments on the ideas presented then. Also, he wishes to thank the following scholars for their comments on the draft: Maggy Barrère, Manuel Calvo, David Oswell, Teresa Picontó and Nigel Thomas. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi 10.1163/15718182-02302006 284 1 CORDERO Arce Introduction: Children’s Legal Studies as an Under-Theorised Field of Studies Children’s rights have recently been described as an under-theorised field of studies (Reynaert et al., 2009; Dixon and Nussbaum, 2012 and Quennerstedt, 2013). Indeed, the majority of the research spectrum reveals an implicit consensus on the fact that children have rights and, most importantly for our purpose here, even a theory of their rights, namely the crc, source and framework of children’s rights. Of course, the crc is not properly a theoretical framework, but the relevant issue for the diagnosis of under-theorisation is that it is treated as such (see Quennerstedt, 2013). Thus, for example, a recent congress held in Madrid entitled “Children’s Rights Research: from Theory to Practice”, but which could have been perfectly relabelled as “Children’s Rights Research: from the crc to Practice”, because the papers presented consisted basically of a discussion of the implementation of the crc, and there were various calls by influential children’s rights’ scholars to make research stem from the crc’s principles. Certainly, there is also a lot of research on, say, children’s participation rights, but this is research undertaken within the narrow framework of Article 12, crc (a critique of Article 12 in Cordero Arce, 2012), that is, research that must be understood as a species of the genus that we could term “implementation research” (and under implementation I include standard-setting and monitoring; see Reynaert et al., 2009: 526). As put by Reynaert et al. (2009, 2012) and Quennerstedt (2013), it is fair to say that children’s rights research has been ensnared by consensus, that is, by the consensus that children’s rights are none other than those enshrined in the crc, that these rights are unproblematic (meaning that they only need to be implemented, not further through, even less critiqued), and that the crc should instruct research, policy and practice.1 Of course, this does not mean that there is no proper theory inside children’s rights research. On a small, but relevant corner of the research spectrum, we can find, if not the only, surely the major theoretical issue being currently discussed, namely, the reach of (adult) paternalism over children – usually sweetened with well-sounding adjectives – (see Cordero Arce, in press), discussion that stems from, and inevitably leads to, the question whether children really have rights (see Purdy, 1994; Brennan and Noggle, 1997; Brighouse, 2002; Griffin, 2002; Ferguson, 2013; Ross, 2013 and Tobin, 2013). This discussion, that has been going on for decades now, revolves around that other one of the will theory versus the interest theory (see Freeman, 1992; Eekelaar, 1992 and 1 The diagnosis of insufficient theorisation has also reached childhood studies; see Adrian James, 2010: 486. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 285 Brennan, 2002). First brought to the fore of children’s rights research by Neil MacCormick (1976), this debate confronts the view that rights are based on the capacity of its holders with the view that they are based on their interests. As concluded by MacCormick, given that children would lack capacity, but definitely have rights, rights, including children’s, must be based on their holders’ interests. Now, as is clear from a brief survey of the debate (see, for example, Ross, 2013), this was, since its beginning, a debate played on grounds alien to children, who only served as objects of a debate in which they, as children, were not the main concern. The concern was the ultimate justification of rights: in a person’s will, or in a person’s interests. This explains the problems of transplanting the debate to children’s rights theory and its resulting futility concerning children, inasmuch as it turns out to be a debate between the assertion that “children have no rights” (because they have no will, so cannot assert rights), and the assertion that “children have no rights” (because their supposed rights – which protect their interests – are, by definition, administered by adults which means, for example, that children can end up having the oxymoronic “right” to an outcome they do not want; see Ferguson, 2013: 193 and Cordero Arce, in press). Apart from this futility regarding children, tarrying in this discussion seems like an obscene entanglement because, which is the position of the questioner that allows for questioning such a thing as whether children have or do not have rights? And what does it say of this question that the questioners belong to a social group whose members do not question their own capacity as rightholders, but the capacity of another group? (i.e. adults vis-à-vis children). Of course, the position is a hierarchical one, based on an adultist assumption, that is, on the belief that adults’ knowledge, discourse and reason are better than children’s, for the mere fact of being the knowledge, discourse and reason of adults. And the question itself, independently of how it is answered, further strengthens that hierarchy and adultism (see sections 2.4 and 2.5, below).2 Probably the only relevance of this debate, for the sake of the rights of children, emerges as an undesired outcome of itself, once it is understood that the whole debate stems from the negative answer to the question about children’s agency; that is, once it is understood that it is a debate that, by definition, leaves children out of it. In other words, the relevance of this debate is to show its hidden and inevitable political dimension. 2 ‘One of the major characteristics of adultism is the ignorant attribution of ignorance to children’, (Kennedy, 2006: 162). I will delve into adultism in the following sections, but see also: Zelizer, 1994; Boyden, 1997; Mayall, 2000; Lee, 2001; Castañeda, 2002; Archard, 2004; Cannella and Viruru, 2004; Jenks, 2005; Wyness, 2005; Rodríguez, 2007; Burman, 2008 and Taylor, 2011. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 286 CORDERO Arce This state of affairs presents us with a (false) dilemma. On the one hand, we have a discriminatory theoretical debate on children having or not having rights (see section 2.4, below). This debate has not moved forward in decades (see Ferguson, 2013; Tobin, 2013 and Ross, 2013), which of course explains why it is impossible to theorise from it: if children’s rights theorists still do not agree on the fact that children have any rights (much less on why they have them, if they do), it is impossible for them to move forward and start building a proper theory of those (still) dubious rights. That is why some scholars directly prefer to avoid regulating children’s legal situation from a rights’ perspective, at least inasmuch ‘that perspective is grounded in any of the available theories of ­children’s rights’ (Ferguson, 2013: 182; see also O’Neill, 1992; Simon, 2000 and Griffin, 2008). So, we are told, as it is impossible to advance children’s rights, let us put them on hold for a while. On the other hand, the majority of researchers sidestep this issue and consider that there is theory and justification enough in the crc, that needs only be implemented, that is, preached (Quennerstedt, 2013: 239). Thus, for example, the words of Geraldine Van Bueren when commenting with approval that there were no philosophical debates on the nature of the moral rights of children during the discussions of the different State delegates that contributed to the drafting of the crc: the ailings of the world’s children could not afford such a luxury (Van Bueren, 1995: 6). So, it seems that we either cannot move, or have to move blindly in an uncritical flight forward. This paper tries to engage with, and widen, the space in the middle of these two perspectives. It steps ahead of the debate on children having or not having rights, because children themselves have shown that they can not only agentically administer their rights but even define and conquer them (Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press), and away from the conception of the crc as the pretended source and framework of theory. Lest our only purpose as researchers is to advocate for the (narrow, disciplinary, top-down) rights of the crc (see section 2.2, below, and Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press), it is a disservice to children’s rights research, and thus to children’s rights and children themselves, to take the crc for granted (the “sacred-text approach”, in Karl Hanson’s [2013] critical words).3 Instead of thinking inside the i­ nstitutional 3 With this I am not implying that research on implementation should be abandoned; it is necessary and actually, calls itself for further theorisation. A recent attempt to theorise implementation can be found in Bonvin and Stoecklin, 2014, who call for the encounter of children’s rights with the capability approach: the capability approach is a way to operationalize formal freedoms (entitlements), and hence children’s rights. Therefore, the capability approach is used to inspire us on dimensions to look at when it comes to implementing formal rights as the ones contained in the international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 287 framework, thus remaining bounded by the crc, in this paper we just think the institutional framework, freely think the crc. And given its hegemonic standing, we stay close to it, because it serves as a mirror in which to acknowledge the reproduction of the hegemonic construction of childhood4 and, most importantly, as a huge and fertile possibility to rework and/or reconstruct childhood(s) (see Prout and James, 1997: 8). Thus, this paper assumes a critical, committed standpoint. This approach does not mean to make legal categories trace and trap the way things are, [nor] to make rules that fit reality. It is critical of reality. Its task is not to formulate abstract standards that will produce determinate outcomes in particular cases. Its project is more substantive, more jurisprudential than formulaic … It proposes to expose that which [children] have had little choice but to be confined to, in order to change it. MacKinnon, 1991: 87, my brackets In other words, human rights are understood here as ‘claims and aspirations that allow the status quo to be contested in favor of the oppressed’ (Dembour, 2010: 3), i.e. children (see section 2.4, below). This critical, emancipatory commitment (Cordero Arce, 2012), does not amount to “politicizing” research, since research has always been politicized. On the contrary, by making it explicit, I attempt ‘to understand and act ethically in light of such politicization’ (Steinberg and Kincheloe, 2004: 4). So, schematically, or better said, programmatically, in what follows I highlight some issues that call for further research, of the like that might start filling in the theoretical void I have diagnosed. These are: i) the position of children’s rights research within the wider interdisciplinary field of childhood studies (the need to take interdisciplinarity seriously); ii) the necessity to move from children’s participation to children’s citizenship; iii) the normative uncrc. It attracts our attention to the fact that there is a gap between children’s formal liberties (rights) and their real freedom (capability) (2014: 1). Now, it must be underscored that a proper theory of implementation cannot restrict itself to discuss the implementation of one legal body, be it the crc or whichever. 4 The sociology of childhood has conclusively shown that childhood is a social construction. By hegemonic childhood (also minority or Western childhood) I refer to the construction of childhood that has achieved a prevailing standing in the social, legal, psychological and educational discourses about children, first in the West, and then, through globalisation, more and more worldwide. This hegemonic childhood conceives children as becomings, not-yets, citizens-in-the-making, developing, socialising, belonging to the world of play (not of work), immature, needy, vulnerable, dependent, incompetent, irrational … (see section 2.4, below). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 288 CORDERO Arce (il)legitimacy of the (international) system of children’s rights; iv) the consideration of children’s rights as a branch of antidiscrimination law; and v) the (uneasy) relationship between children’s rights and children’s “sciences”. I do not assert that these are all the relevant issues that need be engaged with and theorised, but I do think that all of them are fundamental, that none has received the proper theoretical treatment, and that they require to be treated together because all of them tend to engage with a theory that understands children’s rights from children, with children and of children. Also, I say programmatically because I do not make a thorough development of each issue; rather, I make a theoretical outline that, hopefully, might hint to future, deeper, developments. Lastly; some scholars have proposed to speak of “children’s rights studies” (Hanson, 2014); I think it is more proper to speak of ­children’s legal studies, because it helps us part with the understanding that merges children’s rights research with research bounded by the crc, because it is reminiscent of other critical, committed approaches such as feminist legal studies and critical legal studies5 and because it helps to start delimiting still blurry disciplinary boundaries, as we will see in the discussion of the first issue. Let us go directly to it, necessary to begin with because of a methodological priority. 2 (Some) Issues which Must be Addressed The Position of Children’s Rights Research within the Wider Interdisciplinary Field of Childhood Studies: Taking Interdisciplinarity Seriously Freeman (2012: 29) thinks that there has been little dialogue between the sociology of childhood and children’s rights scholarship. I would be more specific, and say that there has been little interdisciplinary dialogue, little theoretical dialogue. Let us see: a search in the main journals in the field of the sociology of childhood or, more widely framed, childhood studies, shows that the ­concept “children’s rights” appears in 210 articles of Childhood (founded 1993), 85 articles of Children’s Geographies (founded 2003) and 329 articles of Children & Society (founded 1987).6 So, childhood studies’ scholars speak almost omnipresently of children’s rights, or, put another way, have incorporated children’s rights’ talk to their dialogues and discourses. However, the issue is to discern what they are talking about when they so do. Is it more than a projection of the 2.1 5 I say “reminiscent” because I do not necessarily share all the viewpoints of these approaches, especially in the case of the critical legal studies movement. 6 As of 23 October 2014. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 289 crc, as I warned in the previous section? Is there any theoretical depth to the concept, other than a conception that either reproduces the crc or too often sounds like a loose moral ideal? And of course, the answer is that given the severely under-theorised status of children’s rights research itself, it is very difficult for those who are meant to “drink” from it to use a minimally developed concept of children’s rights. What I want here is to warn of the dangers of uncritical interdisciplinarity, for childhood studies in general, and for children’s rights research in particular. I think it is irrefutable that, as put by Buck-Morss (2009: 22), ‘disciplinary boundaries allow counterevidence to belong to someone else’s story’. This speaks of the necessary openness of the disciplines that encompass the field of childhood studies, of the “scientific” need of porosity and interfecundation, of the political need of endangering ‘venerable narratives’ and even ‘the entrenched academic disciplines that (re)produce them’ (Buck-Morss, 2009: 23). And, as we are well aware, in the wide field of childhood studies there are ages-old narratives that need to be endangered (see section 2.5, below). But, if interdisciplinarity implies the interdependence of a wide array of disciplines, it also implies a d­ isciplined way of putting those different disciplines into play.7 As Prout (2005: 146) says, interdisciplinarity does not mean abandoning disciplinarity, but acknowledging the coming and going between disciplines, and he calls for childhood studies to be the ‘meeting place of disciplines’. Precisely because of disciplinarian reasons (the risk of pretending some kind of “­meta-disciplinarity”), Cook (2010) prefers to speak of multi-disciplinarity, rather than of interdisciplinarity. I have spoken of childhood studies, the sociology of childhood and children’s rights scholarship, and said that childhood studies is a wider frame than the sociology of childhood. I think it is also wider than children’s rights research. Using Adrian James’ (2010: 492) helpful metaphor, I think children’s rights research, or to be more precise and start shedding weight, children’s legal studies, should be understood as ‘a thread of the fabric of childhood studies’, alongside the sociology of childhood, the history of childhood, childhood geographies, the anthropology of childhood, child psychology, the philosophy of childhood, etc. With this, children’s legal studies also assumes the vocation of helping to understand ‘what “childhood studies” is, so that the childhood studies project can integrate [it] into the fabric of childhood studies as a whole’, that is, “drink” from it. 7 This also means that the kind(s) of inter-disciplinary relationships have to be analysed, because of the inevitable political/normative dimension of the relevant disciplines (developmental psychology, sociology of childhood, children’s legal studies, etc) (see section 2.5, below). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 290 CORDERO Arce This use of the word ‘fabric’ is carefully considered, since I want to use the analogy of weaving in order to suggest a way in which the different threads that separately contribute to what we refer to as childhood studies can be woven together and integrated into a single piece of cloth, the basic dimensions of which are bounded by the recognition of children as set-aside-from-adults but which incorporate, and therefore enable us to focus on, analyse and understand, both the commonalities and the diversities around which childhoods proliferate. Ad. James, 2010: 492 But, and this is the relevant question for us here, what is the nature of the thread of children’s legal studies? Allison James (2010: 216) says that interdisciplinarity always stems from an anchor discipline: ‘the discipline a researcher hails from should … provide the tools and concepts with which to study children and childhood’. So, what are the tools and concepts offered by children’s legal studies to the wider study of children and childhoods? We know, for example, that the sociology of childhood has granted us with rich useful concepts such as children’s agency,8 childhood as a social construction, or childhood as a variable of social analysis (see Prout and James, 1997: 8). And child psychology granted us with the extremely contentious, but important, concept of development (see section 2.5 below). However, as is followed from the argument in the introduction, it seems that concerning children’s legal studies those tools and concepts are still in the making. Conversely, and trying to start digging into children’s legal studies, we must also enquire as to what are the tools and concepts for the study of children’s rights themselves. I just said that throughout childhood studies’ publications we can find various references to children’s rights, that is, that children’s rights as a concept knows of no disciplinary borders. But, if we are committed to put some disciplinary order into childhood studies, should we not also ask whether there are some disciplines better fit to study children’s rights as children’s rights? I think it is fairly uncontroversial to say that the tools and concepts to study, for example, children’s minds, are, at least (though not exclusively), those developed by psychology – including critical and cross-cultural psychology, psychiatry –including critical and cross-cultural psychiatry, neuroscience, etc; that the tools and concepts to study children’s and childhood’s place in 8 When children’s rights’ researchers speak of participation they generally do so starting from this concept of agency, but under the paternalistic constraint of article 12, crc (on participation, see section 2.2, below). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 291 society are at least (though not exclusively), those developed by sociology, geography, anthropology, etc; that the tools and concepts to study children’s learning are at least (though not exclusively), those developed by the diverse pedagogical theories, anthropology of learning, etc., and so on and so forth. But, there seems to be less agreement on the fact that the tools and concepts to study children’s rights should be at least (though again not exclusively), those developed by legal theory, jurisprudence, sociology of law, political ­science, etc. It seems, thus, that the crc has colonised childhood studies (the fabric), while at the same time evading or even emptying children’s legal scholarship (the thread). As source and framework of “theory”, the crc has flooded the other threads of the fabric of childhood studies, while drying out the thread to which it most properly belongs, namely children’s legal studies. Put another way, the crc’s pervasiveness has bleached the thread of children’s legal studies, and with it has decoloured the whole fabric of childhood studies. Somehow, then, children’s rights are now everywhere, being really nowhere. The treatment of the issues that follow might help start (re)rooting children’s legal studies, and refilling, from a critical and committed standpoint, the theoretical void produced by the crc, as well as being an attempt to provide reasoned positions, from within children’s legal studies as one of its threads, to the big fabric of childhood studies. The Necessity to Move from Children’s Participation to Children’s Citizenship I said above that there has been a lot of research on participation. This research, as can easily be seen by revising the literature, is generally undertaken within the framework of Article 12, crc, which allegedly is the international legal recognition of children’s right to participation. There is an explicit agreement amongst researchers, practitioners and policy-makers on the fact that children’s participation is enshrined in Article 12. But this emphasis on participation raises at least two questions. First, what is its meaning and reach when used in research, policy and practice? And second, why the emphasis on “participation”? As for the first question, and just summarising some of the various critiques of the concept as per Article 12 (see Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press), there is participation when, previous adult assurance that children are capable of forming their own views, they are allowed by those adults to express those views freely in matters that, according to those adults, affect them, the views thus expressed being given the weight that adults deem they should have, according to the adult diagnosis of those children’s development and maturity 2.2 international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 292 CORDERO Arce (Art. 12, crc).9 So, it is crystal clear that children do not have the last word as to their participation, which is modeled and modulated by adults; but, neither did they participate in the drafting of their (participation) rights, the crc being an exclusive product of adult representatives of States’ parties. Besides this, unicef (swc–2003 [2002]) and the Committee on the Rights of the Child (gc 12), have very qualified concepts of children’s participation (see Skelton, 2007); children’s participation in international conferences concerning their rights is limited – at best – and tokenistic – at worst (White and Choudhury, 2007; Ennew, 2008 and Saadi, 2012); and the final text of the Optional Protocol for a Communications Procedure – meant, amongst other things, to strengthen children’s participation – is very restricted and restricting (Egan, 2013). So, participation results in a spurious, paternalistic and oxymoronic protected participation. We must jump then to the second question, and ask why the emphasis on such children’s participation – Art. 12, crc being termed the linchpin of the crc by noted scholars (Freeman, 1998: 438) and the Committee on the Rights of the Child (gc 12: par. 86) – if it is such a flawed concept? What is the value, the good, that the crc wants to enshrine with such an emphasis? In a clear departure from mainstream interpretation, Percy-Smith (2014) conceives participation as ‘the democratic process of decision making’, as well as ‘the social practice of active citizenship’ Milne (2013: 38), going further, criticises that child participation tends … to be a distraction and to move the issue away from citizenship …. The contemporary pro-child participation view tends to suggest separatism. Accordingly, children generally make decisions addressing the issues of children and are allowed to have a degree of opinion but no real political influence. There is certainly no real decision making capability in the world generally where adults are best placed to decide for them. In other words, children are allowed only partial citizenship through a veneer of playing a role in their part of civil society. So, should we not stop talking of children’s participation and start talking about their citizenship? I think so, and a brief overlook at some examples might help us to take this step. To begin with, the protected “participation” of Article 12 has no room to fit in the struggles, from and for citizenship, of majority world working children’s associations (nats), who demand the right to work and rights at work and 9 For critical appraisals of Article 12, see also: Boyden, 1997; Freeman, 1998; Archard, 2004; Milne, 2005; Liebel, 2006; Smith, 2007 and Alderson, 2008. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 293 who, organised at a local, national and global level, have conquered a wide array of social and legal changes in favour of them, their families and their communities (Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press). “Participation”, as well, cannot express all the richness of the struggle of Chilean secondary students who, as put by Monckeberg (2008: 9–10), with a strength and determination not seen in other social actors during the past 20 years, waved flags against a system they deemed unfair and exposed the inequalities that afflict Chilean society despite the macroeconomic achievements and existing spaces of freedom …; this massive group of secondary students managed to raise awareness and show the unrest accumulated during the years of transition to democracy. “Participation” is also too narrow to fit in the struggles of the students of Oakland, usa, organised as Youth Power, who through their struggles ‘fundamentally changed their school landscapes’, amongst other achievements, ‘radically altering their school’s depoliticised and divided multicultural celebrations of diversity’, and too narrow to fit in the struggles of the students of Portland, usa, organised in Students Rise Up, who orchestrated city-wide student sit-ins and walkouts, lobbied adult voters and put pressure on the mayor in order to achieve a better funding of public (state) schools, while taking ‘the lead in organizing a community-wide free school to fill the educational gap that would be left by early school closures’ (Gordon, 2010: 199). “Participation” is also flawed to conceptualise the struggle of the children of Loxicha, Mexico, who participated hand in hand with their families and community in the struggle for the release of their unjustly (so they claimed) arrested friends and relatives. In 1996, police and military units swept through the region and arrested 150 men, accusing them of belonging to the Popular Revolutionary Army (Ejército Popular Revolucionario). So, in 1997 the women and children of Loxicha set up a protest camp in Oaxaca City’s Zócalo (central plaza) where they remained for four and half years. During that time, ‘the children … played a key role in their community’s struggle—going on marches, and participating in sit-ins and hunger strikes’ (Smith, 2007: 33). But they would also play, and work, and go to school. As Smith (2007: 51) says, ‘the ways in which the Loxicha children take part in their community’s political lucha perhaps are discounted because they are unpalatable to the pundits of “nice” participation, in particular those working within the boundaries of ngo agendas’. “Participation” does not work to explain the struggles of Greek students in the heyday of austerity rule, which meant that as recently as 2011 there were more than 700 public (state) schools occupied by children who were protesting against the drastic international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 294 CORDERO Arce cuts in funding (Pechtelidis, 2014). Lastly, “participation” is also useless to explain the active and lucid resistance of children that would rather go to jail than school in Toronto, Canada. As Nelsen (1985: 148) puts it: Jailing truants is obvious evidence that the authorities … consider skipping school to be a serious activity. It is serious because these skippers are refusing to permit the school authorities, on behalf of the larger culture, to define and standardize them. But it’s even more than this: for the most important part of this negation is their refusal to subordinate self – to depersonalize their unique subjectivity in favour of the traditional rules, regulations and standardized operating procedures of the larger socio-­economic system. They are not willing to cooperate in their own ­bureaucratization – a ­processing which is, as I have argued, at the very heart of school socialization. In brief, unlike the thoroughly schooled individuals, these deviant “holdouts” refuse to cooperate with school authorities in taking an increasingly heavier hand, at each successive school level, in processing their own “adjustment” to prevailing socio-economic arrangements. The children of these examples are certainly not “participating” (as in Art. 12, crc). No, instead, these children have used their freedom of expression, seeking and imparting information and ideas (Art. 13, crc); their freedom of thought and conscience (Art. 14, crc); their right to freely associate and assemble (Art. 15, crc); and their right to resist arbitrary interferences with their privacy (in Toronto) and their families (in Loxicha) (Art. 16, crc).10 10 It must be noted that there need be no formal struggle in order for a child to transcend the narrow frame of “participation”. The history, sociology, ethnography and anthropology of childhood are full of examples of children that are already protagonists of their life, that is, who have a leading, not secondary role in their own lives, and concerning whom it is absurd to say that they merely “have a say” in “the matters that affect them” (amongst many, Punch, 2003; Liebel, 2004; Katz, 2004; Corsaro, 2005; Cunningham, 2005; Hewlett and Lamb, 2005; Bolin, 2006; Lancy, 2008; Levine and New, 2008 and Konner, 2010). These children’s realities cannot be interpreted through the minimising lens of controlled participation. Even more, in some cases to talk of these children’s citizenship is probably also equivocal, because the word itself implies an urban, bureaucratic setting which is alien to many of those children’s realities. But it is necessary to keep them in mind when discussing citizenship, to retain perspective and relativise the crc’s claims to universality and, more importantly, to understand that children’s secondary role in our societies is not a fact of nature, but the result of a social adultist structure (see section 2.4, below, and Cordero Arce, in press). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 295 Actually, if the concern is with children’s voices, as expressed by many scholars that carry out research on participation, then the real loudspeaker of children’s voices lies not in Article 12, crc (which rather than a loudspeaker is an opaque filter), but in the freedoms of expression, thought, conscience, association and assembly enshrined in Articles 13, 14 and 15, crc. Now, I am not saying that those articles talk about citizenship, even less that they develop a concept of children’s citizenship, but I do think we can build or borrow from them in order further to conceptualise children’s citizenship. It is surprising, and very symptomatic of an adultist reading of the crc, that even though both Articles 12 and 13 talk about the right or freedom of expression, we adults have decided that the place of children’s participation lies in the Article that puts more qualifications and restrictions on children’s expression, and thus participation, because, somehow, it is assumed that a child’s expression has to be validated by an adult in order to be “proper” participation (see also Milne, 2013: 179). Thus, it must be emphasised that the references to the crc and Articles 13, 14, 15 and 16 are not made as if resorting to some sort of source and/or framework of theory, but to a tool that children can use and abuse to the advancement of their rights (adults abuse it the other way round all the time11). In other words, even if we are not theoretically bounded by the crc, given its hegemonic standing we have to explore its emancipatory possibilities, which necessarily means exposing its contradictions. As Roche (1999) put it in another context, children – and us with them – have to begin where they are at, and that means making spaces of their own in spaces not of their making. And whether we like it or not, the legal space that children are currently inhabiting is the crc. So, the challenge is, in Gramsci’s (1971: 321–377) terms, to 11 Thus Langlaude (2010: 1) argues explicitly that Article 12 ‘does a better job at encapsulating the child’s right’ to freedom of expression than Article 13; concluding that ‘the child’s right is very much based on the positive obligations of the state, in contrast with the traditional international law on freedom of expression’. That is, she reconducts freedom of expression to a protected and controlled freedom of expression. She also argues that the main interest behind this right is children’s development (‘developing through freedom of expression’; p. 4). Only later would the child engage ‘in activities such as protests, marches or writing to newspapers. Thus, children have an interest in participating in society and imparting their views, which complements their interest in developing through freedom of expression’ (p. 4). And Thorgeirsdóttir (2006: 19) comments that ‘freedom of expression, if properly protected, will enable the child to develop its mind and its self in society with others and grow into a citizen participating in public life’: as usual, developmentalism acting as the frame through which every right should be read, no matter how much that right gets twisted by such a reading (see section 2.5, below, and Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 296 CORDERO Arce c­ onstruct “good sense” (children’s emancipation) from common sense (the crc), that is, as put by Hunt (1990: 313–314), to rework or refashion ‘the elements which are constitutive of the prevailing hegemony…, to “supplement” that which is already in place; to add or extend to [the] existing discourse’, in order to be able then to ‘open up its silences’ and introduce elements which transcend the hegemonic discourse. The challenge is, thus, to embrace the political nature of children’s legal theory. An example might help to further explain this: let us imagine a mother who gives a ball to her son as a birthday present because she wants him to play football. Upon receiving the ball, it happens that the son chooses to use it as a canvas on which to paint a smiling face. Seeing this, the mother might well say: “No, son! The ball is meant for kicking, not for painting!”, complaint to which the son could legitimately reply: “Mom, you gave me the ball as a present; now let me do as I wish with it”. The crc was a gift of adults to children, and of course, as a gift, has deep inconsistencies (see section 2.3, below, and Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press), but the point I want to make here is that it is a gift that must be conceived to be, now, in children’s hands, at their disposal. Rights are political predicates, that is, ‘open predicates: they open up a dispute about what they exactly entail and whom they concern in which cases’ (Rancière, 2004: 303). So rights are positions to be occupied, and ­children’s rights are positions to be occupied by children (see also Hanson and Nieuwenhuys, 2013: 10, 20). It is from this understanding that we, as researchers, should construct. Now, if our concern is children’s citizenship, it must be acknowledged that we cannot talk seriously about it without talking, also, about normative legitimacy. The Normative (Il)legitimacy of the (International) System of Children’s Rights Political theorists use various concepts to acknowledge the legitimacy of rights inside democratic societies. Habermas (1996: 120) says that ‘the idea of selflegislation by citizens … requires that those subject to law as its addressees can at the same time understand themselves as authors of law’. Young (2000: 6) says that the normative legitimacy of a democratic decision, amongst which we need to include the norm-creating decisions, depends on the ‘degree to which those affected by it have been included in the decision-making processes and have had the opportunity to influence the outcomes’. Rawls (2001: 41, my italics) states that ‘political power is legitimate only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution (written or unwritten) the essentials of which all citizens … can endorse’. And he terms this the liberal principle of l­ egitimacy. 2.3 international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 297 To sum up, Preuss (1998: 326) says that ‘the democratic character of the law’ implies ‘that no political rule is legitimate if it is not grounded on the consent of those subject to it’. In the previous section I said that, as a gift of adults to children, the crc has deep inconsistencies, and now we can develop on that. The main inconsistency of the crc is that it lacks legitimacy vis-à-vis children. First, in its ­origin, because it was drafted for children, without children: there was no self-­ legislation (Habermas), nor inclusion (Young), nor endorsement (Rawls) of children in the coming to be of the crc. As Cockburn (2013: 372) ­acknowledges – including, but speaking in wider terms than the crc, ‘the current social contract has completely written out children from it’, which puts a huge question mark on the crc’s normative legitimacy (see Nolan, 2010: 782). Secondly, in its implementation, because it is implemented, in the best case, just “listening” to some children (i.e. Art. 12, crc; see section 2.2 above). Of course, it is generally argued that it could not have been otherwise. As recalled by Adam Lopatka, Chairman of the un Working Group on the crc, children were deemed weaker than the rest, and thus in need of special rights (Lopatka, 1992: 48–49). And the crc conceives children not only as weaklings, but also as ignorant, private, needy, dependent, developing, innocent, incompetent, pre-social, becomings, and “not-yets” (Cordero Arce, 2012: 372–381, and in press), which explains why Lopatka thinks it is obvious that children did not participate in the drafting of the convention (ohchr, 2007: vol. 1: xl), that is, thinks it is obvious that the crc must lack normative legitimacy. In other words, children did not participate because they could not participate, because, it is argued, they are still not competent enough to do so; they are citizens-in-the-making, in short, becomings. That is why adults had to decide and legislate for them; that is why paternalism. I argued above that the debate on paternalism is probably the main theoretical debate concerning children’s rights, and criticised it because of its futility for the sake of the rights of children. But this does not mean that we can avoid it altogether. What it does mean is that we cannot keep engaging in it under the terms usually proposed by the debaters, that is, from the perspectives of the will theory versus interest theory, of children having or not having rights, and of children’s (in)competence and (ir)rationality (for a critique of paternalism under these terms, which stresses the massive evidence for children’s competence, see Cordero Arce, in press). So, to begin, and trying to sidestep the hegemonic perspective and debate, paternalism regarding children per se is flawed because it is theoretically indefensible to support the extension of paternalism to a whole class or international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 298 CORDERO Arce group – and not on a case-by-case basis- unless that group is pathologically defined as a group (see section 2.4, below).12 Secondly, the unanimous justification of paternalism is children’s alleged unknowingness: due to their supposed lack of reason and experience, children would not be the best judges of what is best for them, so adults, who are assumed to know better, must decide for children (see Rawls, 1971: 248–249; Scarre, 1980: 122–123; Campbell, 1994: 260 and Alemany, 2005: 288–292). In the case of norm-creation then, it is assumed that adults know better, thus, are enfranchised, and children know worse, and thus are disenfranchised. But this argument takes for granted that the justification of enfranchisement is knowledge (as it was once property, literacy or manhood), and this is not the case. Estlund (2008: 3, my italics) explains it as follows: The idea of democracy is not naturally plausible. The stakes of political decisions are high, and the ancient analogy is apt: in life-and-death medical decisions, what could be stupider than holding a vote? Most people do not know enough to make a wise medical decision, but a few people do, and it seems clear that the decisions should be made by those who know best? While it makes good sense for us to defer to someone who we have reason to think is a medical expert, the doctor’s right to make decisions and perform procedures on us comes mainly from our consent, not from the doctor’s expertise … It is important to see that authority does not simply follow from expertise. Even if we grant that there are better and worse political decisions …, and that some people know better what should be done than others…, it simply does not follow from their expertise that they have authority over us, or that they ought to. This expert/ boss fallacy is tempting, but someone’s knowledge about what should be done leaves completely open what should be done about who is to rule. You might be correct, but what makes you boss? So, as Estlund argues, we cannot search for democracy’s foundation in epistocracy, that is, in the rule of the “wise”. Now, as Leece (2009: 133) points out, 12 Developmentalism, with its emphasis on concepts such as “critical periods” and “developmental milestones”, is the main driving force behind the pathologisation of children’s lives, that is, behind the understanding of children as ontologically ambiguous beings (i.e. becomings) thus in need of permanent control, test, and over-protection (see section 2.5, below, and Henriques et al., 1984; Walkerdine, 1993; Morss, 1996 and Burman, 2008). Of course, paternalism owes deeply to developmentalism (see Cordero Arce, in press). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 299 Estlund deliberately chooses to omit children from the purview of his analysis. However, his arguments bear directly upon the question of children’s voting rights, because the case for excluding children from the franchise normally rests explicitly upon the premise that political authority should be knowledge-based, and it is this premise that Estlund attacks. And, goes on Lecce (2009: 135), on Estlund’s view, all adults are to have the same voting rights despite their being differentially endowed with political wisdom because such wisdom is not the basis of justified authority. Fine, but why should we deprive children of the vote on the basis of their relative epistemic deficits when similar deficits are not grounds for excluding adults? It must be underscored that citizenship cannot be reduced to enfranchisement (although in practice it is generally so reduced); nor can citizens’ participation in norm-creation be reduced to its institutional dimension, i.e. the mandate of citizens on representatives (though in practice it is also generally so reduced). But enfranchisement and the institutional dimension of citizen’s participation in norm-creation are decisive to a strong concept of citizenship. If, as Lecce says, one of the core ideas of democracy ‘is the collective authorization of laws by the people who are subject to them’, then ‘democracy is inseparable from voting’, and voting rights are one of the marks of democratic citizenship (Lecce, 2009: 134). And in order to vote in a democracy, no qualification is required, be it property, literacy, manhood, or knowledge. As Rancière (2004: 304) puts it, democracy is ‘the power of those who have no qualification for exercising power’. Paternalism, on the contrary, institutes epistocracy (the rule of the qualified, that is, the alleged “wise” or “competent”), which is just another form of aristocracy: the government of a privileged class or group composed, in our case, by none other than adults (see section 2.4, below). Epistocracy as adultocracy is further revealed in that, as commentators say, the usual benchmark of competence that paternalist standards require of children would, in general, not be met by a large number of the adult population (Jones and Basser Marks, 1994: 280; Lee, 2001: 9, 46 and Archard, 2004: 93–94). As Freeman (2007: 12) says, ‘most of the adult population cannot think rationally or think in such a way as to maximise benefit or minimise loss or reach a reasoned decision. If rights were to hinge on competence … few would have them’. Thirdly, a revision of the literature on paternalism towards children shows that the underlying motive for deciding on behalf of children is not their international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 300 CORDERO Arce alleged lack of reason. Actually, “reason” works much more as an excuse than as a reason. This is expressly acknowledged by children’s rights theorists: It is conceivable that a child might competently take a decision which is contrary to his or her self-interest … in terms of physical or mental wellbeing and integrity. It was suggested there that dynamic self-determinism [that is, abiding by the child’s decision] should be disapplied where this interest was threatened. One can imagine that a legal system might decline to recognize decisions of competent children in the same ­circumstances …. Eekelaar, 1994: 57, my brackets As communicated more crudely by a foster carer to Thomas and O’Kane (1998: 151): ‘so really it’s, they can make decisions as long as they don’t disagree with the adult views and perceptions of what’s going on; because if they do, then obviously they don’t understand the situation’. In the same vein, the 2013 Safer Internet Work Programme of the eu, whose axes are ‘protecting youth online – to prevent children from being exposed unnecessarily to harmful behaviours, contacts or content’ (para. 1.1.ii), says that its aims are ‘to bring stakeholders together to find ways of promoting a safer online environment and protecting children from content that … adults responsible for children consider harmful’ (para. 3).13 So, as these examples show, something or someone is reasonable, or unreasonable (i.e. harmful), when the adult in charge says so. We realise that ‘even when a child knows (i.e. is competent), and the adults know that the child knows, there are certain actions that when done by a child collide with the moral conscience of those very adults’ (Cordero Arce, 2012: 378); that adults object not really for being “unreasonable”, but for being a child’s. More than on children’s incompetence or irrationality then, paternalism rests on the craving of adults to protect, that is, control children. “The child” is thus protected because of either a future subject/citizen (a becoming, not-yet), or a present object/treasure (the ultimate, and most vulnerable, source of adult meaning) (see Cordero Arce, 2012: 377–378, and in press). So, of course adults give ­reasons for the exclusion of children from decision making but they are bad reasons or, better said, they are reasons that work for adults (present and future), in the same degree as they fail for children. As we see, there are major cracks in the argument for paternalism in general, and for paternalistically granting rights to children in particular (and as I said, I have not delved on the overwhelming evidence for agency, which is 13 EU Commission, C (2013) 1954, 11 April 2013. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 301 such that it has moved a leading sociologist of childhood to call researchers to a halt in their efforts to show, yet again, that children are competent agents: we all know that already! [Adrian James, 2010: 486]). Freeman (2007: 8) acknowledges that ‘it is hardly surprising that none of the rights we have were freely bestowed: they all had to be fought for’, and yet, does not engage with the possibility of children being a part of that struggle. The unavoidable question is what it makes of the rights of the crc that children did not fight for them, that the crc was ‘freely bestowed’. Even if we pretended those granted rights to be substantially emancipatory, or empowering, the issue is that the mere idea of “giving” rights to children (of rights flowing downhill, as pretended by Federle, 1994) is an oxymoronic one. First, because when adults give rights it is them who decide the frame within which those rights will be exercised, thus muting children’s voices in the design of their life-frames; and second, because “power” is not something one has but a position to do something or to influence others (Lukes, 2005), so it cannot possibly be given. If the supposed “giving” of rights is not accompanied by the outlawing of the position from where those rights are given, i.e. by a radical contestation of adultism, which means beginning to level the social field, then children’s rights will keep on being given (by adults) in a top-down manner, and “enjoyed” (by children) in a bottom-up fashion: contra Federle (1994), rights will keep on striking downhill (see Cordero Arce, in press). The struggle for a right is always a struggle for legal change, from a previous social change, legal change being the endpoint of that social change. You fight because you think law should acknowledge what you, those engaged in the struggle with you, and even a fair amount of society, already believe in, already are (Bloch, 2011 [1961]; Ferrajoli, 2000; Douzinas, 2000; Rajagopal, 2003; Stammers, 2009 and Hanson and Nieuwenhuys, 2013: 4). What I want to emphasise is that law and society are not separable realities, that legal solutions are always taken inside a social context; (legal) texts read within a (social) context. So when a right is just “given” – top-down – things change in order to remain basically the same: in an adultist social context the outcomes will generally be adultist legal solutions (see section 2.4, below). Thus, the importance of the struggle for law: legal change thus conquered also reflects the change of the social context within which legal solutions are reached. The overcoming of the paternalistic granting of rights to children, who currently just receive their supposed rights wrapped and packed by adults, can be theoretically found in children’s right to define their rights, and not to be defined (Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press). Briefly explained, this right stems from the fact that children are free and equal with the rest of humanity, as acknowledged by the udhr (Art. 1). Children have thus the right to have that international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 302 CORDERO Arce freedom and equality respected, i.e. the right to resist everything that denies that original freedom and equality. This right to resist de-humanisation was at the heart of the US Declaration of Independence of 1776, and of the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen of 1789 (Art. 2), and though currently unacknowledged by human rights charts, is the condition of possibility of each and every human rights chart, and has illuminated all the struggles for rights that have broadened, deepened and ultimately enriched the human rights discourse. To uphold the right to resist de-humanisation implies understanding human rights as ‘normative marks of revolutionary change’ (i.e. towards reclaiming freedom and equality), rather than as ‘defense mechanisms against the possibility of resistance and revolution’ (Douzinas, 2010: 93); it implies assuming the need to invigorate the emancipatory dimension of the human rights discourse, buried under the regulatory dimension (Santos, 2009), or dimension of control (i.e. crc). In the case of children, it means acknowledging their right to resist a set of rights (the hegemonic discourse of children’s rights as crystalised in the crc) conceived to discipline them (towards “proper” adulthood), infantilise them (literally, silence their voices) and minimise them (as sadly acknowledged by the former Chairperson of the Committee on the Rights of the Child, Yanghee Lee: “mini-rights” for “mini-humans”14). If children are human beings, free and equal with the rest of humanity, and have thus the right of revolutionary resistance, as of course they are and they have, then they have the right to define their rights (Santos, 2009), that is, to be autonomous (literally, to be governed by their own laws). But the right to define requires a conceptual space in which to elaborate and deploy those definitions, and a material space, in which to live them, it requires, thus, a right not to be defined (not to be “exactly described”, delimited, fixated), in other words, a right to opacity, because ‘it is impossible to reduce anyone, no matter who, to a truth he would have not generated on his own’ (Glissant, 1997: 194). Thus Burman (2008) talks about children’s right to silence; Ennew (2002) of the right of children that live on the streets not to be labelled; Strandell (2000) of children’s right to not have their play instrumentalised to serve the educational purposes of adults; Ehrensaft (2010: 56) of the need for children with gender nonconformity to have a neutral space in which to develop their own gender identity, a space of ‘“not knowing” … in an area, children’s gender status, which 14 As expressed during the meeting of the working group to draft the communications procedure under the uncrc, on 16 February 2011, in http://www.crin.org/resources/­ infodetail.asp?id=24180, accessed 25 February 2011. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 303 has conventionally had “knowing” as its bedrock’; and we may add children’s right not to be defined by science (see section 2.5, below), nor by adults bereft of definitions (Cordero Arce, in press). Of course, this line of argument leaves the crc in a very bad position. But, before throwing out the baby with the bathwater, which, as Milne (2005: 41) warns, would probably be the case if we outright rejected the crc, the question should be, following and deepening what we suggested in the previous section, how to make “good sense” of the crc’s legitimacy deficit, that is, how to engage with the child who wants to paint the “freely bestowed” ball, instead of kicking it; how to make a space for children’s definitions inside the crc, which is not a space of their making; how to, in sum, occupy the crc. So, what do we make of children’s right to define their rights and not to be defined within the narrow, even suffocating framework of the crc? Can the crc uphold this right to define? How can it welcome an apparently open resistance against itself? From where in the crc can we make such “good sense”? The issue is how to renovate and make critical this already existing and uncritical (and uncriticised) legal institution (Gramsci, 1971: 331), that is, how to prioritise those features which are new, effecting, with this, the exhaustion of the dominant elements (Hunt, 1990: 314). For this, and following Alan Hunt, I think we have to heed its Preamble, and, once again, Articles 13, 14, 15, and 16. Says Hunt (1990: 324): [T]he general field of political contestation … revolves around a reworking of, that is a re-articulation of, elements already present in popular discourses: democracy, freedom, equality, liberty (and a few other key symbols) constitute the whole territory of political discourse. What is decisive is the way in which concrete political discourses generate and mobilize re-combinations of these well-tried elements. I have already commented on Articles 13 to 16, crc, that enshrine children’s freedom of expression, thought, conscience, association and assembly, as well as their freedom from arbitrary interferences with their privacy and their families. To them, the Preamble adds the assertion about the ‘inherent dignity and … equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human Family’, and that ‘everyone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the International Covenants, without distinction of any kind’. So, as free and equal with the rest of humanity, free to think, express, associate and assembly, children have the right to define their rights, that is, to be autonomous (literally, to be governed by their own laws), as well as the right to the conceptual space in which to elaborate and deploy international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 304 CORDERO Arce those definitions, and to the material space, in which to live them, i.e. the right not to be defined, which gives a new dimension to Article 16, that protects children’s freedom from interferences (i.e. from unwarranted definitions).15 Theoretically speaking, the right to define and not to be defined emerges as children’s non- or pre-institutional reclaiming of normative legitimacy: the space where children can find the self-legislation, consent and inclusion that have been institutionally denied to them by the hegemonic discourse crystalised in the crc. But once the crc is rewritten and reread as just proposed, this non-institutional reclaiming takes a first step towards the institutional reclaiming as well. It becomes the place where children begin putting some good sense to the “common sense” represented by the hegemonic discourse; as we said in the previous section, it is children literally occupying the crc. I have argued that the overcoming of the paternalistic granting of rights to children can be theoretically found in children’s right to define. Let me illustrate now how this theory works in practice or, better said, how does practice legitimate this theory as children’s proper reclaiming of normative legitimacy, as bottom-up, grounded theory. To do so, I will paraphrase Rancière, writing on women’s struggle, but adapting his words to the struggle of the organised movements of working children and youth (nats) for the right to work with dignity: Children are making a twofold demonstration. They are demonstrating that they have been deprived of the rights that they have, thanks to the udhr. And they are demonstrating, through their public action, that they have the rights that the crc denies to them, that they can enact those rights. So they act as subjects of Human Rights … They act as subjects that do not have the rights that they have and have the rights that they have not.16 15 16 Again, I am not saying that the struggle of children to define their rights stems from the Preamble, Articles 13, 14, 15 and 16, crc; it stems from their inherent dignity, and equality with the rest of humanity, from their freedom of expression, thought, conscience, association and assembly, which, however defectively, are recognised by the Preamble and those articles. The quote by Rancière (2004: 34) is the following: ‘Women could make a twofold demonstration. They could demonstrate that they were deprived of the rights that they had, thanks to the Declaration of Rights. And they could demonstrate, through their public action, that they had the rights that the constitution denied to them, that they could enact those rights. So they could act as subjects of the Rights of Man in the precise sense that I have mentioned. They acted as subjects that did not have the rights that they had and had the rights that they had not’. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 305 This paraphrase shows another dimension of children’s rights to define and not to be defined. It is not (only) about re-writing the meaning of existing Articles (such as Articles 13, 14, 15, etc.), but about bringing to the fore excluded ones (of course, by acting from and through freedom of expression, thought, conscience, assembly, etc, as Hunt [1990] said). Thus, even if the udhr (Art. 23) enshrines everyone’s right to work with dignity, the crc, not explicitly denying children’s right to work, severely restricts it, and its official interpretation, its whole activity-meaning system, is straightforwardly against any such a right. However, on the other side, the public action of the nats, their public discourse and legal conquests, are beginning to show that children already have that right to work with dignity that the hegemonic discourse of children’s rights insists in denying them (see Cordero Arce, in press). Before moving to the next issue, it needs to be pointed out that the normative illegitimacy of the international system of children’s rights is inscribed in a wider legitimacy crisis of democracies under late capitalism, especially in the minority world (see Rosanvallon, 2010). As put by Rodríguez Palop (2003: 232): ‘this is a consequence of the inherent contradictions of the prevailing political model … because, though the welfare State of late capitalism founds its legitimacy on the principle of participation in decision-making (formal democracy), and social welfare (material democracy)’, both participation and welfare are increasingly belied by reality. As gloomily diagnosed by Sánchez Cuenca (2014), citizens, especially inside the European Union, seem to be facing a situation of “democratic impotence”, in which no longer can they change the policies, but just the politicians. I make this point just to emphasise that, as usual, children have to suffer a double illegitimacy: of the “democratic” system vis-àvis them, and of the “democratic” system vis-à-vis everyone. And we could ­perfectly well term this a double discrimination. Actually, the downgrading of children’s citizenship to mere “participation” (section 2.2, above), and the silencing of their voices (i.e. infantilisation) in the configuration of their regulated reality, discussed in this section, make it unavoidable to talk about ­antidiscrimination law. The Consideration of Children’s Rights as a Branch of Antidiscrimination Law There have been some shy efforts to understand children as a social category potentially discriminated against on an age basis. For example, Breen (2006) devotes a whole book to the issue of age discrimination and children’s rights. However, she begins her book by stating that the premise that children are rights-holders implies the recognition that, ‘although rights are accorded to the child, a lack of capacity may inhibit the child from exercising his or her rights. 2.4 international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 306 CORDERO Arce Accordingly, the notion of paternalism is an inherent part of any discussion regarding the exercise or practical effect of the accordance of rights to the child’ (2006: xi, my italics). So, for Breen, rights are “accorded”, i.e. granted, to children, never fought for, won or conquered by them, which inevitably implies conceiving children as receivers of adult donors; as I said above, of rights striking downhill. She also thinks it “inherent” to children’s rights discussion to talk about paternalism, thus reproducing all the problems and inconsistencies of paternalism that we discussed above. She then goes on to say that ‘the achievement of equality in rights protection between children and adults will have to recognise the difference between children and adults where such difference is based on the drawing of valid distinctions between the two groups’, which will make it possible to treat ­children ‘differently’ (Breen, 2006: 12). And when are distinctions valid? That is, when is differential treatment justifiable, and thus supposedly non-discriminatory? When ‘it can be established that the limitation is legitimate, proportionate, and necessary’ (2006: xiii); or when the ‘limits [on children’s rights] are rational and proportionate’ (2006: 41). The problems with “difference” have been acknowledged by other children’s rights scholars. Freeman (2012: 31) poses that primary concerns of the children’s rights movement are to ‘question the relevance of difference, to challenge discrimination’, and to ‘problematise the relationship between age, regarded at the least as a suspect category, and status’. I think we should stress what Freeman only suggests, that is, that difference leads to discrimination; that building antidiscrimination theories based on difference is tantamount to reproducing discrimination. Difference implies hierarchy because it is always difference with respect to those who define and name the difference, difference according to a norm (Glissant, 1997: 189–194), in this case, adult normality. In this hierarchy, children are below (waiting for rights to be accorded), and adults above (granting children with rights). So even when differential treatment claims to be founded on proportionate, legitimate and rational reasons, we have to ask, as Freeman (2011: 28) points out, what is meant by a good, rational, legitimate, proportionate, necessary reason. Gender and race, for example, now seem to be bad reasons in many parts of the world, but this has not been always the case, nor is it the case everywhere (Freeman, 2011: 28). The case of gender and race shows that “good reasons” tends to mean the reasons of the powerful. So, the relevant questions concerning the differential treatment of children are “good reasons” according to whom? And in which social context? And as we know from the previous section, in the minority childhood reasons are good when adults say so, and they are “reasoned” within an adultist social context. Freeman’s concern needs to be further developed because, as shown by the example of Breen’s approach – which is just a case of trying to justify international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 307 paternalism, not to overcome it – the theory on age-discrimination against ­children is ‘only in its infancy’ (Liebel, 2012: 97). My contention is that this development passes through the understanding of children’s rights as a branch of (proper) antidiscrimination law. And for that we have to begin by recognising children as an oppressed social group or minority (minority in terms of power, of being lesser or minor than). Young (1990: 44) says that a social group ‘is defined not primarily by a set of shared attributes, but by a sense of identity’, in the case of children, for example, arising from their belonging to a generation (Mayall, 2002 and Alanen, 2011), or from the awareness of being a collective set aside from adults (Qvortrup, 2008), which ­usually implies below than adults (Sutton-Smith, 1997; Lindquist, 2001; Thomas, 2004 and Corsaro, 2005). For Young (1990), a given social group is oppressed if it suffers any of the following “faces of oppression”: violence, exploitation, marginalisation, powerlessness, and/or cultural imperialism. Any of these will suffice for there to be an oppressed group, and in the case of children, usually more than one shows up (of course, this is an empirical question, so it will greatly vary across childhoods). The important issue is that oppression, says Young, does not necessarily refer to the result of a tyrant’s actions and intentions. It is, rather, a ‘systemic phenomena which exclude people from participating in determining their actions or the conditions of their actions’ (Young, 1990: 31). In this sense, it is structural, and not the result of a few people’s choices or policies. Its causes are embedded in unquestioned norms, habits, and symbols, in the assumptions underlying institutional rules and the collective consequences of following those rules … In this extended structural sense oppression refers to the vast and deep injustices some groups suffer as a consequence of often unconscious assumptions and reactions of well-meaning people in ordinary interactions, media and cultural stereotypes, and structural features of bureaucratic hierarchies and market mechanisms—in short, the normal processes of everyday life. Young, 1990: 41 So, where can we find these faces of oppression that, as Young says, are not necessarily the work of a ruthless tyrant, but might well be the result of the added actions of loving parents, well-intended politicians, committed schoolteachers, etc.? • Violence: ‘Many States continue to sanction corporal punishment in the name of discipline against [children] …. an action that may in fact amount to international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 308 CORDERO Arce criminal assault if perpetrated against an adult’.17 For example, in the uk it is legally allowed for parents to use violence towards children if it is a case of “reasonable punishment” and doesn’t leave a mark.18 However, we would reject with outrage the justification of an adult being “punished” with a smack, because we would think it is outright unreasonable to do such a thing. If it becomes reasonable to do something by default unreasonable, it can only be because the addressee of the punishment is, him or herself, unreasonable (deprived of reason) and, consequently, must be dealt with in his or her own “language” (or lack of it). In other words, you do not tame a horse by speaking to it. Actually, violence against women – a pervasive reality worldwide – can still be found to be justified under similar claims to lack of rationality (Harway and O’Neill, 1999). The bottom line under this perspective, for adultism and ­sexism, is that children and women only learn the hard way because they are, still “irrational”.19 • Marginalisation: Minority or hegemonic childhood has placed children at the lower margins of society. Children have to be socialized, that is, raised to the social, because they are deemed more of nature than of culture, just citizens-in-the-making (see Art. 29.1.d, crc); they have to develop or, better said, be developed (subjected to disciplinary developmentalism20) towards 17 18 19 20 In https://www.crin.org/en/home/what-we-do/crinmail/crinmail-1404, accessed 11 November 2014. Children Act 2004, in http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2004/31/contents, accessed 26 November 2014. The cedaw Committee has recognised that ‘gender-based violence’, that is, ‘violence that is directed against a woman because she is a woman or that affects women disproportionately’, ‘is a form of discrimination’ (un Doc. A/47/38 1992). And this form of violence is discrimination not only because it conspires against the individual enjoyment of rights on a par with men, but because it breaks the wider rule of intergroup equality (Barrère, 2008: 63). Now, even if the Committee on the Rights of the Child is critical of the legal systems that allow any kind of violence towards children, specifically mentioning the English common law (crc/ C/gc/8 2006, para. 31; and see crc/C/gc/13 2011, para. 24), it does not recognise that there is any such thing as age discrimination, that is, discrimination against a child because he or she is a child. So, it cannot consider that violence against children is undertaken by the mere fact of them being children. Thus, in its Concluding Observations on the fourth periodic Report by Norway, the Committee says that it just ‘takes note of the ongoing debate as to whether age discrimination of children should be included in the law and whether ­children should be given the right to file complaints if they are discriminated against due to their age’ but then goes on to express its ‘concern’ at information of children being discriminated on the basis of their ethnicity, disabilities, etc. (crc/C/nor/CO/4 2010, para.19, my italics). Morss (1996: 51) says that developmentalism ‘consists of the production of, and reliance on, explanatory statements concerning general natural regulation of changes in the human life-span’ (see section 2.5, below). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 309 proper adulthood, which is their goal as human becomings (see Art. 6, crc); children are infantilised, that is, their voices are literally muted, or at least filtered (Art. 12, crc; and see section 2.2 above). In sum, the children of the minority childhood head (or are headed) towards adulthood aside from, beneath, following and as per adults.21 • Powerlessness: This is closely entwined with children’s marginalisation. There is a structural adult power over children (which does not prevent the emergence of micro-powers of contestation, as described by Sutton-Smith, 1997: 111–126; Lindquist, 2001; Thomas, 2004 and Corsaro, 1995: 42–43). Children (in the hegemonic childhood) can be said to be, symbolically and materially, in adult hands. As Caselli (2010: 243) puts it: it is still culturally accepted (and not only in everyday language) to refer in passing to what children are and what we should expect them to do, while – fortunately – more than one eyebrow would be raised if we were to state confidently what women are or what they ought to do. Also, as I said above, paternalism implies the pathological definition of children as a group, that is, the definition of one group (children) as in need of another group (adults), and not vice versa, which is, apart from its symbolic violence, the enshrinement of powerlessness. The same happens when adults assume to be entitled to discuss whether children should be granted rights or not (which, put another way, is to discuss in which margin of the legal sphere should children be placed). • Exploitation: As I said above, currently children’s work is severely constrained by the hegemonic discourse of children’s rights, whose agenda leads to its complete banning. Children suffer the prohibition to create value for the sheer fact of being children, and no matter how much or how “competently” they raise their voices to the contrary (Woodhead, 1999; Leonard, 2004; Liebel, 2004, 2007 and Nieuwenhuys, 2011). Abolitionism amounts, thus, to ‘speaking the language of discipline and exclusion’ (Invernizzi, 2008: 139). This explicit denial of children’s economic agency leads to the implicit and inevitable denial of their political agency. It doesn’t matter what they say about their work, it does not matter if they express 21 A perfect example of children’s marginalisation is the Mosquito device. Very popular in the United Kingdom, it is a device that emits a high-pitch, unpleasant sound, inaudible for adults due to the hearing loss that comes with age, but perceptible for children, which makes it a perfect weapon against children in the “wrong” places, i.e. the non plus ultra of biopolitical technology and children’s marginalisation (see Lee and Motzkau, 2011). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 310 CORDERO Arce their will to work and their outrage towards abolitionism: children have nothing to say, nothing to participate in concerning their right to work (unless, of course, when they speak against such a right [Saadi, 2012]). Thus, children are conceived, by definition, as economic burdens, as unproductive dependents. However, and as a schizoid counterweight, children have been burdened with a superlative emotional value … for adults! Children, or better said, “the child” (that abstraction that can nowhere be found) has become ‘the final alternative to loneliness that can be built up against the vanishing possibilities of love’ (Beck, 1992: 118), the ‘integrative symbol for society’ (Pupavac, 2001: 97), adults’ most valuable treasure (see also Zelizer, 1994 and Meyer, 2007). Children thus suffer the adult exploitation of their forced unproductiveness (treasures must be protected, controlled, guarded), while being banned from leaving that unproductive status. • Cultural imperialism: As it has been thoroughly argued (Stephens, 1995; Cannella and Viruru, 2004; Kennedy, 2006; Burman, 2008 and Nieuwenhuys, 2013), the colonial project of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries and the developmental ­project whose primary “objects” are children are parts of one and the same project: African native population – and women – were infantilised and thus deemed in need to follow the authority of the already grown up and civilized, i.e. the male adult European conquerors. But cultural imperialism unfolds not only in intra-childhood oppression. It is already commonplace to talk about the social construction of childhoods, that is, of the existence of diverse childhoods throughout history and the world. From the Eurocentric midst of that diversity, and boosted by globalisation (Boyden, 1997), the hegemonic (Western, or minority) childhood exerts an overwhelming influence and ­pressure amongst the rest of childhoods, which can be very properly termed a case of cultural imperialism, that is, of inter-­childhood oppression (Pupavac, 2001; Ennew, 2002; Nsamenang, 2002; Cunningham, 2005; Pandya, 2005 and Cussiánovich, 2006). Some sociologists of childhood have resisted the consideration of children as a minority group. Thus, for James et al. (1998: 86) such an analysis amounts to unproblematically constituting children as separate and different from adults. But, it must be stressed, it is not the researcher who constitutes the children into such a minority, but the hegemonic childhood itself. It is children who, defined as dependents and subordinates, have been placed in the position of having to be led to adulthood because left to themselves could go astray (Rancière, 2010: 168); it is children who have been placed in a position to be defined, not to define; locked in times and spaces for them (not necessarily of them), such as the school and home, which ‘are organized around the power of international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 311 the adults to determine the character of children’s experience’ (Mayall, 2002: 20). It is children who suffer the allocation of an ambiguous and minimised ontology, which results in the paternalistic granting of rights. And it is also children who, precisely, are wary of such unproblematic arrangement of childhood and adulthood in watertight compartments. Usually the child who works has an inextricable link with the adults in her or his family, a link that makes her or him proud and that fills that work with meaning. This link is ever renewed through the work itself. Children acknowledge themselves as important members of the family (us) through collective work (Barlett, 1993; Invernizzi, 2003; Katz, 2004; Liebel, 2004; Miller, 2005; Bolin, 2006 and Leyra Fatou, 2012). And yet, it is the very prohibition of children’s work, merely because of being children, what curtails that deep bond, and pushes to construct the boundary that creates childhood as a separate and subordinate ­reality with regards to adulthood. As put by Mayall (2002: 9), children are ‘a minority social group, whose wrongs need righting’. Amongst children’s rights researchers, Onora O’Neill (1992: 37–39) also rejects the analogy of the situation of children with other oppressed groups. She argues that there are at least four dimensions that distinguish children’s dependency (subordination, lesser status) from the dependency of other oppressed groups. First, she says, children’s dependency is not artificially created; second, it cannot end merely by political or social change; third, children depend on those who do not depend on them, unlike, for example, slaves, whose owners also depended on their work and, last, the supposed “oppressors” of children usually want to end dependency. However, once we attend to the previous “faces of oppression”, especially to the oppression implied by the banning of child work, it becomes clear that the analysis of O’Neill is bounded and blinded by the hegemonic childhood. Because, and replying to her points, first, and as I have argued here, it is clear that the dependency created by the curtailing of children’s economic agency is artificial. Second, and because of this, a social and political change could certainly empower them, as children and as workers, and it is for that change that nats are struggling (nats, 2000; Liebel, 2003, 2004, 2008, 2012; Cussiánovich, 2006 and Cussiánovich and Méndez, 2008). Third, children who work are dependent on their families, just as these are dependent on them (Levine, 1999; Mayall, 2000; Invernizzi, 2008 and Leyra Fatou, 2012), and talking of (in)dependence is in itself highly misleading (Cordero Arce, in press).22 And at last, the position of the International Labour Organization (ilo) and of the h ­ egemonic discourse of children’s rights in 22 So, it is not that children are independent per se, which they are not, but that neither are adults, no matter how much adultism tries to construct them as such (see Cordero Arce, in press). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 312 CORDERO Arce general, is a clear proof that “the ­oppressors” do not want the dependency of children to end (Invernizzi and Milne, 2002; Liebel, 2007; Invernizzi, 2008; Morrow, 2010 and Nieuwenhuys, 2007, 2011). To sum up, children are a minority group subjected to the structural oppression of an adultist system (intergroup oppression). In other words, we can discern the axis of adultism crossing the diverse faces of oppression (see Barrère and Morondo, 2011: 23). Once acknowledged this, which, as said above, is an empirical issue and thus varies across childhoods, we have to enquire as to the answer of the hegemonic discourse of children’s rights, specifically the crc, to this reality. To do this it is helpful to look at other international human rights instruments which have minorities as their addressees. For example, we know that, from its title onwards, the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (cedaw) is an instrument conceived to fight back and eventually eliminate all forms of discrimination against women, as women (anything that impairs the recognition and enjoyment of human rights on a basis of equality of men and women [Art. 1, cedaw]); the same as the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (cerd) is an instrument conceived to fight back and eliminate all forms of racial discrimination, that is, for example, of black people being discriminated for being black people (anything that impairs the recognition and enjoyment of human rights on an equal footing [Art. 1, cerd]). But it can hardly be stated that the crc was conceived to battle the discrimination of children as children; merely for being children. The crc only protects children against being discriminated as poor children, black children, female children, aboriginal children, homosexual children, etc. (Art. 2, crc). This reveals a stark conceptual difference between cedaw and the cerd, on one side, and the crc, on the other, because more than to protect children against discrimination, the crc is just intended to protect children or, better said, to the adult protection of children; ‘simply to safeguard their survival’ (Lopatka, 1992: 49).23 So, if cedaw wants to fight back and eliminate sexism, and the cerd wants to fight back and eliminate racism, 23 I say there is a “conceptual” difference with cedaw and the cerd because, as MacKinnon (2006) notes, in practice reservations have watered down the implementation of cedaw. Further, Mackinnon claims that the very concept of women's rights in cedaw is not nearly strong enough, at least not when compared with instruments such as the cerd (MacKinnon, 2006: 6, 11). In the same vein, Donner (1994: 242) believes that the drafters of cedaw ‘created a document with much less protection against discrimination aimed at women than found in its prototype, the Racial Convention’. However, considering what has been explained so far, I believe that the comparison made by MacKinnon and Donner between cedaw and the cerd reveals a quantitative difference, whereas the comparison between those instruments and the CRC reveals a qualitative one: the international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 313 it cannot honestly be also said that the crc wants to fight back and eliminate adultism. We have insisted on the fact that law and society are not separable realities, that legal solutions are always taken within a social context. So, if there is structural oppression in society, law can never be neutral regarding it: it either works positively to overcome/subvert it (for example, through laws and policies of affirmative action), or is its accomplice. This complicity might manifest itself by omission, when the law enshrines an illusory formal equality belied by the substantive social inequality in which that law is applied (Barrère, 2008: 55). Or it may be manifested directly by action, as happens with the crc. As has been suggested above (sections 2.2, 2.3), the problem is not only that the crc functions inside an adultist social context, but that it is itself an adultist piece of legislation (see also Boyden, 1997; Milne, 2005, 2013; James, 2011 and Cordero Arce, 2012, and in press). So the challenge, once again, is to make good sense of the crc. If difference is not the path for this, as I said above, neither is sameness. Paraphrasing MacKinnon (1991: 85), the question we should engage with as children’s legal studies’ scholars is: “why should a child have to be the same as an adult to get what the adult gets simply because of being one?”. The challenge is thus to overcome the adult as the measure of all human beings, and more specifically, of the legal subject, just as feminists have been struggling for centuries to overcome man as that very measure (see MacKinnon, 1991). Now, we have also established that no emancipation will come from above, that downhill rights always strike, never just flow (contra Federle, 1994), that is, that it is not just a matter of changing the law to meet the challenge of a change that is also social. On the contrary, this is a challenge that can only be faced from below, from the “below” of children’s voices, struggles and commitment with their own emancipation. As previously suggested, and thoroughly argued elsewhere, nowadays that “from below” finds its most powerful expression in the struggles of the social movements of working children and youth, for whom adults are respectful collaborators – or, considering the criminalisation of child work, straightforward accomplices – of their struggles (Liebel, 2003, 2004, 2008; Cussiánovich, 2006; Cussiánovich and Méndez, 2008 and Cordero Arce, in press). If children’s rights are to be constructed as a branch of antidiscrimination law, that construction will take place from the periphery to the (Euro)centre. difference between protecting against discrimination (cedaw and the cerd) and simply protecting (crc). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 314 CORDERO Arce To conclude this section, it is necessary to go back to Article 2, crc, mentioned above, and engage in the intersectional approach that attends to every other variable of social analysis apart from age, such as gender, ethnicity, class, etc. (see Crenshaw, 1989, 1991). Children’s law as antidiscrimination law must visibilise, and feed back and boost the empowerment of, the gay in the boy, and the boy in the gay; the black in the girl, and the girl in the black; the working class child, and the working class child, etc. The (Uneasy) Relationship between Children’s Rights and Children’s “Sciences” Unlike children’s legal studies, children’s rights are not a discipline, in the sense of the threads of the big fabric of childhood studies we talked about in s­ ection 2.1. According to the approach advanced here, children’s rights should stem from children’s citizenship (section 2.2), that is, should emerge with the normative legitimacy of being from children, with children, and by children (section 2.3), and with the clear idea that, as a minority group, law is never a neutral endeavour regarding children (section 2.4). So, children’s rights stem from their equal freedom and dignity with the rest of humanity, as claimed by children’s own struggles for their rights (see also Hanson and Nieuwenhuys, 2013: 5). However, their endpoint in law is surely shaped by a wide array of disciplines. So, the question in this last section concerns the space that the diverse disciplines of the fabric of childhood studies should have in the shaping of children’s laws. Today, developmental psychology occupies a de facto monopoly of this space.24 Briefly speaking, developmental psychology studies/constructs a “child” whose telos is adulthood, who becomes an adult by walking through natural, universal, successive and pre-defined stages, from incompetence and dependence to competence and independence, and who is particularly sensitive to twists and deviations from this developmental path which, if to happen, will surely manifest themselves as adult pathologies.25 This understanding is what, as stated by White (1998), guides the law and justice of child welfare in the minority childhood configuring what he terms an authentic psycho-­ legalism. Thus, decisions about a child’s competence, her or his best interests, 2.5 24 25 It is certainly more than contentious to include developmental psychology in the current fabric of childhood studies, from the perspective of developmental psychology (Morss, 2002) and of childhood studies (Thorne, 2007 and Cordero Arce, in press). But, as said in section 2.1, child – if not developmental – psychology should have a place within childhood studies. For critical appraisals of developmental psychology, see Henriques et al., 1984; Walkerdine, 1993; Morss, 1996 and Burman, 2008. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 315 the amount of understanding necessary to determine her or his responsibility, or about when, who and by whom is adopted, are, all of them, left in the hands of developmental psychology (Burman, 2008: 9). This explicit reliance on developmental psychology is assumed by a vast number of legal scholars, many of whom are strong supporters of children’s rights (thus Wald, 1979; Campbell, 1992; Eekelaar, 1992; Freeman, 1992; Purdy, 1994; Buss, 1999; Brighouse, 2003; Fortin, 2005; Campoy, 2006 and Tobin 2013). So, for example, Wald (1979) holds that before ‘giving children a specific right it is necessary to determine whether children are likely to have the capacity to make the decision for themselves’ which implies determining ‘what types of skills a person needs to make a given decision and to what degree children of any given age possess the requisite abilities’, exploration which should begin ‘with the research regarding the intellectual, social and moral development of children’ (Wald, 1979: 273–274; and see also Freeman, 1992: 67). Freeman (1992) and Eekelaar (1992, 1994) also follow developmentalism when endorsing that children’s law, through ad hoc versions of paternalism, should collaborate in leading children to the doorsteps of an autonomous and rational adulthood (children as becomings and not-yets). Buss (1999) acknowledges and endorses developmental supervision of judicial decisions and even criticizes that legal scholarship concerning development has been restricted to ‘the development of logical reasoning skills’ (Buss, 1999: 897). She intends to widen this supervision referring to research on “socio-cognitive development” that would serve to discourage the initiatives to empower children during trials. According to her, ‘developmental literature suggests that a child’s immature conception of self, of the roles people play, and of his [sic] relationship to the people performing those roles will all pose serious obstacles to a lawyer’s achievement of the empowerment goal’ (1999: 899, my italics), and concludes that ‘because many children lack the capacity to appreciate their influence over their lawyers or the court, lawyers often will do children a considerable disservice if they premise their representation on the empowerment ideal’ (1999: 898, my ­italics). Similarly, Fortin (2005) affirms that ‘the evidence on developmental growth through childhood … establishes clearly that children are different from adults in development, behaviour, knowledge, skills and in their dependence on adults, most often their parents …’ and that ‘it seems clear … that the relatively slow development of children’s cognitive processes makes the majority of children unfit to take complete responsibility for their own lives by being granted adult freedoms before they reach mid-adolescence’ (2005: 5, my ­italics), because they ‘are obviously more prone than adults to limit their own future prospects by making unwise short-term choices’ (2005: 22, my italics). However, children ‘soon move out of dependence and into a developmental international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 316 CORDERO Arce stage where their capacity for taking responsibility for their lives needs encouraging’ (2005: 6, my italics). This reliance on developmental standards also permeates the crc (Art. 6, crc), which depicts a vulnerable, needy and dependent child; needy of and dependent on adults, which highlights children’s difference and otherness, concepts so dear to developmentalism. Further, the crc always depicts “the child” under the wing of a responsible adult, generally her or his parents, because “the child” is just getting ready to become responsible (Art. 29.1.d, crc). Even children’s “participation”, locked in Article 12 crc, is literally constrained by developmental standards, concerning what it means to be ‘capable of forming his or her own views’ and the evaluation of ‘the age and maturity of the child’ (see Smith, 2002: 75 and Cordero Arce, 2012: 372–378).26 So, here we find the first problem with allowing developmental psychology to enter the shaping of children’s laws, which is, as it can be inferred from what has just been said, the content of developmental psychology, what it says about children. According to mainstream developmental psychology, as reproduced by the hegemonic children’s rights discourse, children are in – but slowly overcoming – a state of becoming, immaturity, difference, dependence, ­ ­unfitness, lack of wisdom, neediness… The issue, then, is how to fit this depiction of children with the one advanced in the previous sections of this paper, and of course, it is impossible. The idea of rights from, for, with and by children, of children’s citizenship, of children defining their rights, and struggling for them, and of children enjoying their rights on an equal (not different) footing with adults, directly challenges the idea of the developing child enshrined by psycho-legalism or legal developmentalism. But there is a second, more fundamental problem with allowing developmental psychology to enter the shaping of children’s laws, and that is how and from where it gets to say what it says about children. Psycho-legalism is the result of the almost uncontested authority of developmental psychology, claimed by developmentalism itself on behalf of its alleged “scientific” nature. As put by Huber (1993: 225), ‘the rule of law is indeed a grand thing, but not half so grand as the rule of fact … Some part of those facts will depend on the laws of science, which … represent the highest law of all’. There is an appeal to science as a supposedly objective and neutral authority which can and must lead children to their ontological telos which is adulthood. Backed up by science, 26 For a thorough critique of developmentalism in the hegemonic discourse of children’s rights as enshrined in the crc, including, also, how it dispenses with children’s contexts, with children’s communitarian interdependencies, and with the rich diversity of childhoods, which even means proscribing alternative childhoods, see Cordero Arce, in press. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 317 developmentalism is not merely engaged in a descriptive mission, but also in a normative one: it says not only how children are, but how children should be. Thus its double disciplinary vocation, because it assumes the entitlement to define children, and to command them to abide by those definitions (Kessen, 1979; Walkerdine, 1993; Bloch, 2000; Castañeda, 2002; Cannella and Viruru, 2004; Burman, 2008 and Woodhead, 2011).27 As a result, legal developmentalism turns out to be not really about children’s right to develop, but about their duty to do so (see Cordero Arce, 2012: 387–395).28 This is the real problem with legal developmentalism; not only, or mainly, that it depicts children as incomplete beings, citizens in the making, needy, incompetent and unknowing, but that it claims the indisputable scientific authority to make such bold statements. In an effort to tone down the criticism on developmentalism, Woodhead (2011: 52) has said that within mainstream developmental psychology there has long been a concern with acknowledging children as active, competent and socially engaged, adding that the problem would just be the discourse about those agency and competence, which tends to objectify “the child”, that is, to narrate agency and competence as the agency and competence of a thing. But Woodhead does not attend to the reach of this objectivation of children, which highlights the problem we are dealing with here: no matter how much developmental psychology gets to acknowledge competencies in the child, for example, lowering the (st)age for the acquisition of certain logical skills, the very fact of doing so implies to keep on acting from a disciplinary position in which it is itself, developmental psychology, the one entitled to define and classify “the child” as such an (in)competent (see Walkerdine, 1993: 457). What developmental “science” does is to decide how much of a person, or what type of person, is a given person, or category of persons, in this case, a given child, 27 28 Serres (1974: 259) is certainly right when he says that ‘there is no pure myth except the idea of a science that is pure of all myth’ and he is especially right if we think of developmental psychology, which intends to lead children not to just any adulthood, but to a rational (i.e. abstract and formal reasoning), productive and self-regulating one, that is, to the adulthood of Western-based capitalist societies (Harré, 1984: 252; James et al., 1998: 17–18; Bloch, 2000: 258; Appel, 2009: 709). The authoritarian and colonial vocation of science has been highlighted also within the field of philosophy. Vattimo and Zabala (2011: 14) say that ‘in order to assure its progress within society, philosophy, through its metaphysical obsession with truth, dissolved into the sciences, that is, into the global organization of all beings within a predictable structure of causes and effects’; and then they warn that (p. 37): the desire for dominion often results in metaphysical thought, not the other way round (i.e. the desire to control children in the objective scientific knowledge/description of children). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 318 CORDERO Arce or children in general. So, as long as there are some people, in this case, hyperqualified adults mainly from the minority world, who regard themselves to be entitled to define who knows and who does not, who thinks well, and who does not, who is competent and who dependent, who is a pre-citizen, and who a citizen, the agency and independence that they acknowledge to others will always be the agency and independence of objects, that is, of things. As such a thing, or object, the representation of “the child” made by the psychologist in her or his lab will be perforce dissociated from the representation of children as actors, social agents, which has as its central feature the self-representation of children themselves (see Latour, 2007: 52–53). Therefore, although the approach that privileges certain kind of scientific research is important (for example, see Alderson, 2008: 155–156), because it shows a shift of trend within child psychology, towards more context-aware, ethnographic, qualitative approaches, it is still insufficient because it does not transcend the modern scientific framework that entitles some people (i.e. adults) to define (i.e. control) other people (i.e. children) (see Walkerdine, 1993: 457). Put another way, even if I am convinced that the statement is true and needs to be made, politically we do not seem to move ahead when saying that ‘almost everything that has ever been stated [about children’s incompetence] from a normative point of view, such as the egocentricity of the preschool child or their inability to be reliable witnesses, has been shown to be wrong and to have grossly underestimated children’s competence’ (Smith, 2002: 82, my brackets), because soon there appears someone waving other “science” that speaks to the contrary (as, for example, expressly does Fortin, 2005: 75–76). So, even if there are plenty of good reasons to support an understanding of children as competent agents, good reasons are not reason enough to give a legitimate shape to the rights and laws of children. The problem, then, lies not in developmental psychology as such, but more generally in making science the arbiter of children’s laws. Nelken (2009: xviii) has argued that law frequently disengages from the facts, understood as science: ‘law is more obviously subject to the play of political calculation which […] often leads to choices that are more concerned with what the public believe, expect and want, than what experts advise’. But the case is that children, with regards to their rights, are not yet a public entitled to influence legal policies. So, scientific supervision is in radical contrast with the idea of children as citizens, makers of their own laws (i.e. autonomous beings), rights’ definers. If children’s rights stem from children’s equal freedom and dignity with the rest of humanity, they can only be shaped by disciplines that respect and enhance equality, freedom and dignity; that engage in laws from, with, and for, children. In this sense, legal professionals who share the critical political commitment international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 319 we are advancing here are necessary in order to give ‘legal shape’ to children’s claims (Barrère, 2008: 66–67). I wrote in section 2.3 of children’s right to define and not to be defined. After the previous exposition, the right not to be defined emerges as children’s right to shape their rights as dikes to hold back science’s definitions. Before concluding, there is an issue that cannot be sidestepped when discussing children’s rights theory and the relation between children’s laws and science, and that is the theorising of age: the complex articulation of different types of temporality – his­torical, generational, chronological, phenomenological, developmental, b­ iological – should be central to the study of children and childhoods. Questions about individual growth and the shifting constitution of persons over time, which are central to the study of human development, have the potential to enrich the anthropology, sociology, geography and history of childhood. Thorne, 2007: 150 However, I have drawn attention to this only at the end, because all too often the question about age comes in too soon in the discussion, always resulting in the closing down of the rest of the questions; in the closing down of the silences we want to open up as critical committed scholars. This happens, first, at a theoretical level, with developmentalism acting as the guardian of time, conceived as one and the same for every child, clear and unproblematic as the numbers of a calendar. In this sense, Buck-Morss (2010: 68) states that if, as Adorno said, ‘history is in the truth’, that is, if in every truth there is history and every truth is historical, then ‘history, hence temporal change, is at play in the pragmatics of truth, which can never be understood as a foundational ground untouched by time’. That is why ‘it matters who owns time’ because its owners will also administer its meaning. Second, and because of the reach of developmentalism, it also happens in everyday life: the first two questions that a child from the minority childhood is usually asked by adults are: “what’s your name?” and “how old are you?”. By knowing the child’s age, the adults assume to know what that child can or cannot do, what that child needs or does not need, what that child must, or must not do. Maybe if we were to listen to what children say they want, need, like and dislike, we would realise, by the end of the conversation, that the question about age was not missed (see Freeman, 2007: 15). Theorising age then?, yes, but if rights are to stem from children and be shaped respectfully of that origin, we have to transcend the necessary, but still insufficient, scientific aim of developing ‘approaches to human development international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 320 CORDERO Arce [that] are more fully historicized, informed by meaningful attention to culture and social structure, and enriched by close attention to the ways in which children negotiate the process of growing older and participate in a range of social institutions’ (Thorne, 2007: 150). Children have the right not to have their times defined by science, that is, the right to be the owners of their time, to reclaim a time for themselves instead of having to comply with adult-defined developmental milestones; for example, a right to remain silent when asked about age, that is, about their “calendar time” (see Woodhead, 2011: 51–52). 3 Concluding Remarks Allison James (2010: 216) acknowledges that the “new” sociology of childhood began with a common intellectual agenda, fuelled by shared assumptions about the ontological status of both children and childhood … there was agreement, first, that children could – and should – be regarded as social actors; second, that childhood, as a biological moment in the life course, should nonetheless be understood as a social construction; and finally, there was methodological agreement about the need to access children’s views first hand. Another key assumption of the then “new” sociology of childhood was that ‘to proclaim a new paradigm of childhood sociology’ was ‘to engage in and respond to the process of reconstructing childhood in society’ (Prout and James, 1997: 8). This was, thus, a political engagement. In this paper I have argued that children’s legal studies have no “common intellectual agenda”, and elaborated on some issues and concepts that might prove fruitful to start advancing a shared critical intellectual agenda on children’s legal studies, which might help to engage in and respond to the political process of reconstructing children’s rights theory. The issues and concepts that I elaborated on, which I think need to be further and more thoroughly addressed, are, as explained above: (i) serious interdisciplinarity, which means thinking, discerning and strengthening the place of the thread of children’s legal studies inside the fabric of childhood studies; (ii) children’s citizenship, which means encouraging a steady move from the emphasis on “participation” to an emphasis on citizenship; (iii) normative legitimacy, which means understanding children’s rights and children’s laws as of and by children; (iv) children’s law as a branch international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 321 of antidiscrimination law, which implies conceiving children as a minority group, and adultism as the structural axis of the hegemonic childhood and the hegemonic children’s rights discourse; and (v) the independence of children’s rights from children’s “sciences”, which means assuming that children’s rights can only depend on children themselves (from, of, with, by children). These are some of the tools and concepts that children’s legal studies’ might offer to the wider study of children and childhood, and they may as well serve to deepen the study of children’s rights themselves (see section 2.1, above). In particular, they might prove to be helpful tools and concepts for children’s own struggle for their rights; they are tools and concepts to be used by children. However, as I said at the beginning, these are not all the issues that I think deserve (more) theoretical attention. Certainly, for example, everything that concerns interdependence, care and duties is important and still also undertheorised, but these issues represent a challenge to the theory of human rights as such, not only to children’s rights theory. These concepts defy the model of the allegedly independent and autonomous (adult) rights-bearer, so when dealing with them we have to talk about human interdependence, human need for care, and human rights’ inseparability from human duties. Here, I have tried to engage with children’s rights theory as children’s rights theory, which means trying to take children, their rights, and the theory about their rights, once and for all, seriously (Freeman, 1992, 2007). References Alanen, L. (2011), “Generational Order”, in J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro and M.-S. Honig, eds., The Palgrave Handbook of Childhood Studies, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Alderson, P. (2008), Young Children’s Rights, Jessica Kingsley Publishers, London. Alemany, M. (2005), “El Concepto y la Justificación del Paternalismo”, DOXA, Cuadernos de Filosofía del Derecho 28, pp. 265–303. Appell, A., R. (2009), “The Pre-political Child of Child-Centered Jurisprudence” Houston Law Review, 46, 703. Archard, D (2004), Children. Rights and Childhood, Routledge, London. Barrère, M. (2008), “Iusfeminismo y Derecho Antidiscriminatorio: Hacia la Igualdad por la Discriminación”, in R. Mestre i Mestre, Mujeres, Derechos y Ciudadanías, Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia, pp. 45–71. Barrère, M. and D. Morondo (2011), Subordiscriminación y Discriminación interseccional: Elementos para una Teoría Del derecho Antidiscriminatorio, Anales de la Cátedra Francisco Suárez 45: 15–42. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 322 CORDERO Arce Barlett, P. F. (1993), American Dreams, Rural Realities: Family Farms in Crisis, The University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC. Beck, U. (1992), Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity, Sage, London. Bloch, M.N. (2000), “Governing Teachers, Parents, and Children through Child Development Knowledge”, Human Development 43: 257–265. Bloch, E. (2011 [1961]), Derecho Natural y Dignidad Humana, Dykinson, Madrid. Bolin, I. (2006), Growing Up in a Cultures of Respect: Child Rearing in Highland Peru, University of Texas Press, Austin. Boyden, J. (1997), “Childhood and the Policy Makers: a Comparative Perspective on the Globalization of Childhood”, in A. James and A. Prout, eds., Constructing and Reconstructing Childhood: Contemporary Issues in the Sociological Study of Childhood, RoutledgeFalmer, London, pp. 190–229. Breen, C. (2006), Age Discrimination and Children’s Rights: Ensuring Equality and Acknowledging Difference, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Leiden. Brennan, S. (2002), “Children’s Choices or Children’s Interests: Which do their Rights Protect?”, in D. Archard and C.M. Macleod, eds., The Moral and Political Status of Children, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 53–69. Brennan, S. and R. Noggle (1997), “The moral status of children: Children’s rights, parents’ rights, and family justice”, Social Theory and Practice 23 (1): 1–26. Brighouse, H. (2002), “What Rights (if any) do Children Have?”, in D. Archard and D. Macleod, eds., The Moral and Political Status of Children, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 31–52. Brighouse, H. (2003), “How Should Children Be Heard?”, Arizona Law Review, 45: 691. Buck-Morss, S. (2009), Hegel, Haiti and Universality, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA. Buck-Morss, S. (2010), “The Second Time as Farce … Historical Pragmatics and the Untimely Present”, in C. Douzinas and S. Zizek, eds., The Idea of Communism, Verso, London. Burman, E. (2008), Deconstructing Developmental Psychology, Routledge, London. Buss, E. (1999), “Confronting Developmental Barriers to the Empowerment of Child Clients”, 84 Cornell Law Review, p. 895. Campbell, T. (1992), “The Rights of the Minor: as Person, as Child, as Juvenile, as Future Adult”, International Journal of Law and the Family 6: 1–23. Campbell, T. (1994), “Really equal rights? Some philosophical comments on ‘Why children shouldn’t have equal rights’ by Laura M. Purdy”, International Journal of Children’s Rights, Volume 2, Number 3, pp. 259–263. Campoy Cervera I. (2006) La Fundamentación de los Derechos de los Niños, Dykinson, Madrid. Cannella, G. S. and R. Viruru (2004), Childhood and Postcolonization, RoutledgeFalmer, New York. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 323 Caselli, D. (2010), “Kindergarten theory: Childhood, affect, critical thought”, Feminist Theory 11: 241. Castañeda, C. (2002), Figurations: Child, Bodies, Worlds, Duke University Press, Durham. Cockburn, T. (2013), “Authors of Their Own Lives? Children, Contracts, their Responsibilities, Rights and Citizenship”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 21: 372–384. Cordero Arce, M. (2012), “Towards an Emancipatory Discourse of Children’s Rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 20: 365–421. Cordero Arce, M. (in press), Hacia un Discurso Emancipador de los Derechos de las Niñas y los Niños, IFEJANT, Lima. Cook D. T. (2010), “The promise of an unanswered question: multi-/cross-disciplinary struggles”, Children’s Geographies, 8:2, 221–222. Corsaro, W. A. (2005), The Sociology of Childhood, Pine Forge Press, Thousand Oaks. Crenshaw, K. (1989), “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory, and Antiracist -olitics”, University of Chicago Legal Forum, pp. 139–67. Crenshaw, K. (1991), “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence against Women of Color”, Stanford Law Review 43(6), pp. 1241–1299. Cunningham, H. (2005), Children and Childhood in Western Society since 1500, PearsonLongman, Harlow. Cussiánovich, A. (2006), Ensayos sobre infancia: Sujeto de derechos y protagonista, IFEJANT: Instituto de Formación para Educadores de Jóvenes, Adolescentes y Niños Trabajadores de América Látina y el Caribe, Lima. Cussiánovich, A. y D. Méndez (2008), Movimientos Sociales de NATS en América Latina. Análisis histórico y balance político en los últimos treinta años, IFEJANT (funded by: Save the Children Sweden), Lima. Dembour, M-B. (2010), “What Are Human Rights? Four Schools of Thought”, Human Rights Quarterly, Vol. 32, Number 1, pp. 1–20. Dixon, R. and M. Nussbaum (2012), “Children’s rights and a capabilities approach: The question of special priority”, Cornell Law Review 97: 549–594. Donner, L.A. (1994), “Gender Bias in Drafting International Discrimination Conventions: the 1979 Women’s Convention Compared with the 1965 Racial Convention”, California Western International Law Journal 24, pp. 241–254 Douzinas, C. (2000), The End of Human Rights, Hart, Oxford. Douzinas, C. (2010), “Adikia: On Communism and Rights”, in C. Douzinas and S. Zizek eds., The Idea of Communism, Verso, London. Eekelaar, J. (1992), “The Importance of Thinking that Children Have Rights”, International Journal of Law and the Family 6: 221–235. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 324 CORDERO Arce Eekelaar, J. (1994), “The Interests of the Child and the Child’s Wishes: The Role of Dynamic Self-Determination”, International Journal of Law and the Family 8: 42–61. Egan, S. (2014), “The New Complaints Mechanism for the Convention on the Rights of the Child: A Mini Step Forward for Children?”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 22 (1): 205–225. Ennew, J. (2002), “Outside Childhood: Street Children’s Rights” in B. Franklin ed. The New Handbook of Children’s Rights, London, Routledge, pp. 388–403. Ennew, J. (2008), “Children as ‘Citizens’ of the United Nations (UN)”, in A. Invernizzi and J. Williams eds., Children and Citizenship, Sage, London. Ehrensaft, D. (2010), “ ‘I’m a Prius’: A Child Case of a Gender/Ethnic Hybrid”, Journal of Gay & Lesbian Mental Health, 15:1, 46–57, Estlund, D. M. (2008), Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework, Princeton University Press, Princeton. Federle, K.H. (1994), “Rights Flow Downhill”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 2, 343–368. Ferguson, L. (2013), “Not merely rights for children but children’s rights: The theory gap and the assumption of the importance of children’s rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 21: 177–208. Ferrajoli (2000), “El Acceso Negado. Derecho, Desarrollo, Diversidad. La Democracia Constitucional”, Responsa Iurisperitorum Digesta (Aquilafuente 10), Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca, pp. 75–90. Fortin, J. (2005), Children’s Rights and the Developing Law, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Freeman, M. (1992), “Taking Children’s Rights More Seriously”, International Journal of Law and the Family 6, 52–71. Freeman, M. (1998), “The Sociology of Childhood and Children’s Rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 6, 433–444. Freeman, M. (2007), “Why it Remains Important to Take Children’s Rights Seriously”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 15, 5–23. Freeman, M. (2011), “Children’ Rights as Human Rights: Reading the UNCRC”, in J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro and M.-S. Honig, eds., The Palgrave Handbook of Childhood Studies, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Freeman, M. (2012), “Towards a Sociology of Children’s Rights”, in M. Freeman, ed., Law and Childhood Studies, Current Legal Issues, Vol. 14, Oxford University Press, Oxford. GC 12 (2009) General Comment No. 12: The right of the child to be heard, Committee on the Rights of the Child, CRC/C/GC/12, 20 July, Geneva. Glissant, E. (1997), Poetics of Relation, University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor. Gordon, H. R. (2010), We Fight to Win: Inequality and the Politics of Youth Activism, Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, NJ. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 325 Gramsci, A. (1971), Selections from the Prison Notebooks, Lawrence and Wishart, London. Griffin, J. (2002), “Do Children Have Rights?”, in D. Archard and D. Macleod, eds., The Moral and Political Status of Children, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 19–30. Griffin, J. (2008), On Human Rights, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Habermas, J. (1996), Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, translated by William Rehg, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Hanson, K. (2013), Keynote Speech, at the Children’s Rights Erasmus Academic Network (CREAN) Conference, Children’s Rights Research: from Theory to Practice, held at the Universidad Complutense (Madrid), 24–25 September. Hanson, K. (2014), “‘Killed by Charity’ – Towards interdisciplinary children’s rights studies”, Childhood 21: 441. Hanson, K. and O. Nieuwenhuys (2013), “Living rights, social justice, translations”, in K. Hanson and O. Nieuwenhuys, eds., Reconceptualizing Children’s Rights In International Development: Living Rights, Social Justice, Translations, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 3–25. Harré, R. (1984), Personal Being: A Theory for Individual Psychology, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Harway, M. and J.M. O’Neill (1999), What Causes Men’s Violence Against Women?, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA. Henriques, J., W. Hollway, C. Urwin, C. Venn and V. Walkerdine, eds. (1984) Changing the Subject: Psychology, Social Regulation and Subjectiviy, Routledge, London. Hewlett, B. and M. Lamb, eds. (2005), Hunter Gatherer Childhoods. Evolutionary, Developmental & Cultural Perspectives, Transaction, New Jersey. Huber, P. (1993) Galileo’s Revenge: Junk Science In The Courtroom, Basic Books, New York. Hunt, A. (1990), “Rights and Social Movements: Counter-Hegemonic Strategies”, Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 17, No. 3, pp. 309–328. Invernizzi, A. (2003), “Street-Working Children and Adolescents in Lima: Work as an Agent of Socialization”, Childhood 10: 319. Invernizzi, A. (2008), “Everyday Lives of Working Children and Notions of Citizenship”, in A. Invernizzi and J. Williams, Children and Citizenship, Sage, London. Invernizzi, A. and B. Milne (2002), “Are children entitled to contribute to international policy making? A critical view of children’s participation in the international campaign for the elimination of child labour”, International Journal of Children’s Rights, Vol. 10, Number 4, pp. 403–431(29) James, Adrian (2010a), “Competition or integration? The next step in childhood ­studies?”, Childhood 17: 485. James, Allison (2010b),“Interdisciplinarity – for better or worse”, Children’s Geographies 8: 2, 215–216. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 326 CORDERO Arce James, A. (2011), “Agency”, in J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro and M.-S. Honig, eds., The Palgrave Handbook of Childhood Studies, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. James, A., C. Jenks and A. Prout (1998), Theorizing Childhood, Polity, Cambridge. Jenks, C. (2005), Childhood, Routledge, London. Jones, M. and L.A. Basser Marks (1994), “The Dynamic Developmental Model of the Rights of the Child: a Feminist Approach to Rights and Sterilisation”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 2, 265–291. Katz, K. (2004), Growing Up Global. Economic Restructuring and Children’s Everyday Lives, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis. Kennedy, D. (2006), The Well of Being. Childhood, Subjectivity and Education, State University of New York Press, Albany. Kessen, W. (1979), “The American Child and Other Cultural Inventions”, American Psychologist, Vol. 34 (10), pp. 815–820. Konner, M. (2010), The Evolution of Childhood, Harvard/U.P., Cambridge MA and London. Langlaude, S. (2010), “On how to build a positive understanding of the child’s right to freedom of expression”, Human Rights Law Review, Vol. 10, No. 1, pp. 33–66; Lancy, D. (2008), The Anthropology of Childhood, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Latour, B. (2007), Nunca Fuimos Modernos: Ensayo de Antropología Simétrica, Siglo XXI Editores, Buenos Aires. Lee, N. (2001), Childhood and Society. Growing Up in an Age of Uncertainty, Open University Press, Maidenhead. Lee, N. and J. Motzkau (2011), “Navigating the bio-politics of childhood” Childhood 18: 7. Leece, S. (2009), “Should Democracy Grow up? Children and Voting Rights”, Intergenerational Justice Review Volume 9, Issue 4, pp. 133–139. Leonard, M. (2004), “Children’s Views on Children’s Right to Work. Reflections from Belfast”, Childhood 11, 45–61. Levine, S. (1999), “Bittersweet Harvest: Children, work and the global march against child labour in the post-apartheid state”, Critique of Anthropology; 19; 139 Levine, R. A. and New, R., eds. (2008) Anthropology and Child Development – A Cross Cultural Reader, Blackwell, Malden. Leyra Fatou, B. (2012), Las Niñas Trabajadoras: El Caso de México, Los Libros de la Catarata, Madrid. Liebel, M. (2003), “Working Children as Social Subjects. The Contribution of Social Children’s Organizations to Social Transformations”, Childhood 10, 265–285. Liebel, M. (2004), A Will of their Own. Cross-Cultural Perspectives on Working Children, Zed Books, London. Liebel, M. (2006), Entre Protección y Emancipación. Derechos de la Infancia y Políticas Sociales, Las Monografías del Experto, Serie Teoría, N°1, Universidad Complutense de Madrid. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 327 Liebel, M. (2007), “Opinion, Dialogue, Review: The new ILO report on child labour: a success story, or the ILO still at a loss?” Childhood; 14; 279. Liebel, M. (2008), “Citizenship from Below: Children’s Rights and Social Movements”, in A. Invernizzi and J. Williams eds., Children and Citizenship, Sage, London. Liebel, M. (2012), Children’s Rights from Below: Cross-Cultural Perspectives, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Lindquist, G. (2001), “Elusive Play and its Relation to Power”, Focaal – European Journal of Anthropology 37, 13–23. Lopatka, A. (1992), “The Rights of the Child are Universal: The Perspective of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child”, in M. Freeman and P. Veerman, eds., The Ideologies of children’s rights, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht. Lukes, S. (2005), Power, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. MacCormick, N. (1976), “Children’s Rights: A test case for Theories of Right”, en Archiv fur Recht-und Sozialphilosophie 62: 305–316. Mackinnon, C. (1991), “Difference and Dominance: On Sex Discrimination”, in K.T. Bartlett and R. Kennedy eds., Feminist Legal Theory, Westview Press, San Francisco, pp. 81–94. Mackinnon, C. (2006), Are Women Human? And Other International Dialogues, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA and London. Mayall, B. (2000), “The Sociology of Childhood in relation to Children’s Rights”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 8, 243–259. Mayall, B. (2002), Towards a Sociology for Childhood, Open University Press, Buckingham. Meyer, A. (2007), “The Moral Rhetoric of Childhood”, Childhood 14, 85–104. Miller, P. (2005), “Useful and Priceless Children in Contemporary Welfare States” Social Politics 12: 3–41. Milne, B. (2005), “Is ‘Participation’ as it is described by the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) the Key to Children’s Citizenship?”, in A. Invernizzi and B. Milne, eds., Children’s Citizenship: An Emergent Discourse On The Rights 0f The Child?, special volume of Journal of Social Sciences No. 9, pp. 31–42. Milne, B. (2013), The History and Theory of Children’s Citizenship in Contemporary Societies, Springer, Dordrecht. Monckeberg, M. O. (2008), “Presentación”, en A. Domedel y M. Peña y Lillo, El Mayo de los Pingüinos, Ediciones Radio Universidad de Chile, Santiago de Chile. Morrow, V. (2010), “Should the world really be free of ‘child labour’? Some reflections”, Childhood 17: 435 Morss, J. R. (1996), Growing critical. Alternatives to Developmental Psychology, Routledge, London. Morss, J. R. (2002), “The several social constructions of James, Jenks, and Prout: A contribution to the sociological theorisation of childhood”, International Journal of Children’s Rights, Vol. 10, Number 1, pp. 39–54(16). international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 328 CORDERO Arce NATs (2000) Revista Internacional desde los Niños y Adolescentes Trabajadores, Year IV, N° 5 and 6. Nelken, D. (2009), Beyond Law in Context: Developing a Sociological Understanding of Law, Ashgate, Farnham. Nelsen, R. W. (1985), “Books, Boredom, and behind Bars: An Explanation of Apathy and Hostility in Our Schools”, Canadian Journal of Education/Revue canadienne de l’éducation, Vol. 10, No. 2, pp. 136–160. Nieuwenhuys, O. (2007), “Embedding the Global Womb: Global Child Labour and the New Policy Agenda”, Children’s Geographies, 5: 1, 149–163. Nieuwenhuys, O. (2011), “From Child Labour to Working Children’s Movements”, in J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro and M.-S. Honig, eds., The Palgrave Handbook of Childhood Studies, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Nieuwenhuys, O. (2013), “Theorizing childhood(s): Why we need postcolonial perspectives”, Childhood 20: 3. Nolan, A. (2010), “The Child as ‘Democratic Citizen’ – Challenging the ‘Participation Gap’” Public Law 4, pp. 767–782. Nsamenang, A. B. (2002), “Adolescence in Sub-Saharan Africa: an Image Constructed from Africa’s Triple Inheritance” in B. Bradford Brown, R. Larson and T. S. Saraswati eds., The World’s Youth: Adolescence in Eight Regions of the Globe, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 61–104. OHCHR (Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights) (2007), Legislative History of the Convention on the Rights of the Child, Vols. I and II, United Nations, New York and Geneva. O’Neill, O. (1992), “Children’s Rights and Children’s Lives”, International Journal of Law and the Family 6: 24–42. Pandya, V. (2005), “Deforesting among Andamanese Children: Political Economy and History of Schooling”, in B. Hewlett and M. Lamb, eds., Hunter Gatherer Childhoods. Evolutionary, Developmental & Cultural Perspectives, Transaction, New Jersey, pp. 385–406. Pechtelidis, Y. (2014), “The discursive formations around children’s political activism”, paper presented at the Mid-term Symposium of Research Network 4, Sociology of Children and Childhood, of the European Sociological Association, held at the University of Modena and Reggio Emilia (Italy), 21–23 May. Percy-Smith, B. (2014), “Theorising participation as a socially contextualised practice – Lessons from an (EU) study (and post-positivism?!)”, paper presented at the Midterm Symposium of Research Network 4, Sociology of Children and Childhood, of the European Sociological Association, held at the University of Modena and Reggio Emilia (Italy), 21–23 May. Preuss, U. K. (1998), “Communicative Power and the Concept of Law”, in Habermas on Law and Democracy: Critical Exchanges, Michel Rosenfeld and Andrew Arato, eds., University of California Press, Berkeley. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 329 Prout, A. (2005), The Future of Childhood, RoutledgeFalmer, Oxford. Prout, A. and James A (1997), “A New Paradigm for the Sociology of Childhood? Provenance, Promise and Problems” in A. Prout and A. James, eds., Constructing and Reconstructing Childhood, RoutldegeFalmer, London, pp. 7–33. Punch, S. (2003), “Childhoods in the Majority World: Miniature Adults or Tribal Children?”, Sociology, Volume 37(2): 277–295 Pupavac, V. (2001), “Misanthropy Without Borders: The International Children’s Rights Regime”, Disasters 25(2): 95–112. Purdy, L. (1994), “Why Children Shouldn’t Have Equal Rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 2: 223–241. Quennerstedt, A. (2013), “Children’s Rights Research Moving into the Future – Challenges on the Way Forward”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 21: 233–247. Qvortrup, J. (2008), “Diversity’s Temptation – and Hazards”, paper presented at ‘Re-presenting Childhood and Youth’, Centre for the Study of Childhood and Youth, University of Sheffield, 8–19 July. Rajagopal, B. (2003), International Law From Below: Development, Social Movements and Resistance, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Rancière, J. (2010), “Communists without Communism?”, in C. Douzinas and S. Zizek, eds., The Idea of Communism, Verso, London. Rancière, J. (2004), “Who Is the Subject of the Rights of Man?”, The South Atlantic Quarterly 103: 2/3, Spring/Summer. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Harvard Univ. Press , Cambridge, MA. Rawls, J. (2001), Justice As Fairness: A Restatement, E. Kelly, ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA. Reynaert, D., M. Bouverne-De Bie and S. Vandevelde (2009), “A review of children’s rights literature since the adoption of the United Nations convention on the rights of the child”, Childhood 16(4): 518–534. Reynaert, D., M. Bouverne-De Bie and S. Vandevelde (2012), “Between ‘believers’ and ‘opponents’: Critical discussions on children’s rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 20(1): 155–168. Roche’ J. (1999)’ “Children: Rights, Participation and Citizenship”, Childhood 6, 475–493. Rodríguez Pascual, I. (2007), Para Una Sociología de la Infancia: Aspectos Teóricos y Metodológicos, Centro de Investigaciones Sociológicas, Madrid. Rodríguez Palop, M.E. (2003), “¿Nuevos derechos a debate? Razones para no resistir”, Anuario de filosofía del derecho http://dialnet.unirioja.es/servlet/ejemplar?codigo =93145 20: 227–254. Rosanvallon, P. (2010), La Legitimidad Democrática, Paidós, Madrid. Ross, H. (2013), “Children’s Rights and Theories of Rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 21: 679–704. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 330 CORDERO Arce Saadi, I. (2012), “Children’s Rights as ‘Work in Progress’: The Conceptual and Practical Contributions of Working Children’s Movements”, in M. Liebel, Children’s Rights from Below: Cross-Cultural Perspectives, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Sánchez Cuenca, I. (2014), La Impotencia Democrática, Catarata, Madrid. Santos, B. de S. (2009), Sociología Jurídica Crítica, Madrid/Bogotá, Trotta/Ilsa. Scarre, G. (1980), “Children and Paternalism”, Philosophy 55 (211) 117–124. Serres, M. (1974), La Traduction (Hèrmes III), Minuit, Paris. Simon, T.W. (2000), “United Nations Convention on Wrongs to the Child”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 8: 1–13. Skelton, T. (2007), “Children, Young People, UNICEF and Participation”, Children’s Geographies, 5: 1, 165–181. Smith, A. B. (2002), “Interpreting and Supporting Participation Rights: Contributions from Sociocultural Theory”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 10, 73–88. Smith, A. M. (2007), “The Children of Loxicha, Mexico: Exploring Ideas of Childhod and the Rules of Participation”, Children, Youth and Environments 17 (2), 33–55. Stammers, N. (2009), Human Rights and Social Movements, Pluto Press, London. Steinberg, S.R. and J.L. Kincheloe, eds. (2004) Kinderculture. The Corporate Construction of Childhood, Westview Press, Boulder, CO. Stephens, S. (1995), “Children and the Politics of Culture in ‘Late Capitalism’”, in S. Stephens, ed., Children and the Politics of Culture, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. Stoecklin, D. and J.-M. Bonvin, eds. (2014), Children’s Rights and the Capability Approach: Challenges and Prospects, Springer, Dordrecht. Strandell, H. (2000), “What is the Use of Children’s Play: Preparation or Social Participation?”, in H. Penn, ed., Early Childhood Services: Theory, Policy and Practice, Open University Press, Berkshire. Sutton-Smith, B. (1997), The Ambiguity of Play, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. SWC-2003 (2002), The State of the World’s Children 2003, The United Nations Children’s Fund (UNICEF), New York. Taylor, A. (2011), “Reconceptualizing the ‘nature’ of childhood”, Childhood 18(4): 420–433. Thomas, J. T. (2004), “Child Poets and the Poetry of the Playground”, Children’s Literature 32, p. 152–177. Thomas, N. and O’Kane C. (1998), “When Children’s Wishes and Feelings Clash with their ‘Best Interests’”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 6, 137–154. Thorgeirsdóttir, H (2006), Article 13: The Right to Freedom of Expression, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Leiden. Thorne, B. (2007), “Editorial: Crafting the interdisciplinary field of childhood studies”, Childhood 14; 147. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331 Maturing Children’s Rights Theory 331 Tobin, J. (2013), “Justifying Children’s Rights”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 21: 395–441. Van Bueren, G. (1995), The International Law on the Rights of the Child, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Vattimo, G. and S. Zabala (2011), Hermeneutic Communism: from Heidegger to Marx, Columbia University Press, New York. Wald, M. (1979), “Children’s Rights: a Framework for Analysis”, University of California, Davis Law Review, Vol. 12, p. 255. Walkerdine, V. (1993), “Beyond Developmentalism?”, Theory & Psychology, 3: 451–469. White, S. (1998), “Interdiscursivity and child welfare: the ascent and durability of ­psycho-legalism”, The Sociological Review 46 (2), pp. 264–292. White, S. C. and S. A. Choudhury (2007), “The Politics of Child Participation in International Development: The Dilemma of Agency”, The European Journal of Development Research, Vol. 19, No. 4, pp. 529–550. Woodhead, M. (1999), “Combatting Child Labour. Listen to What the Children Say”, Childhood 6, 27–49. Woodhead, M. (2011), “Child Development and the Development of Childhood”, in J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro and M.-S. Honig, eds., The Palgrave Handbook of Childhood Studies, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke. Wyness, M. (2005), “Regulating Participation: The Possibilities and Limits of Children and Young People’s Councils” in A. Invernizzi and B. Milne, eds., Children’s Citizenship: An Emergent Discourse on The Rights 0f The Child?, special volume of Journal of Social Sciences No. 9, pp. 7–18. Young, I. M. (1990), Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton University Press, Pricenton, NJ. Young, I. M. (2000), Inclusion and Democracy, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Zelizer, V. (1994), Pricing the Priceless Child. The Changing Social Value of Children, Princeton University Press, Princeton. international journal of children’s rights 23 (2015) 283-331