Journal of the History of Economic Thought http://journals.cambridge.org/HET Additional services for Journal of the History of Economic Thought: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Buchanan and Musgrave on Public Finance and Public Choice: a Review Essay Warren J. Samuels Journal of the History of Economic Thought / Volume 22 / Issue 04 / December 2000, pp 499 507 DOI: 10.1080/10427710020006253, Published online: 11 June 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1053837200006659 How to cite this article: Warren J. Samuels (2000). Buchanan and Musgrave on Public Finance and Public Choice: a Review Essay. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 22, pp 499-507 doi:10.1080/10427710020006253 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/HET, IP address: 139.184.14.159 on 14 Sep 2015 Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Volume 22, Number 4, 2000 BUCHANAN AND MUSGRAVE ON PUBLIC FINANCE AND PUBLIC CHOICE: A REVIEW ESSAY BY WARREN J. SAMUELS James M. Buchanan and Richard A. Musgrave, Public Finance and Public Choice: Two Contrastin g Visions of the State (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999) vii, pp. 272, $27.50. ISBN 0262024624 . The subtitle of this unusual but fascinating and valuable work tells the story of the different views of the two protagonists , James M. Buchanan and Richard A. Musgrave: two contrasting visions of the State. The story will be of interest to specialists in public nance, the history of economic thought, and the economic role of government. Among other things, the story demonstrates conclusively the important consequences of one’s preconceptions in the development of both theory and policy. Both men insist on that, and it is true. The book derives from and in effect records a 23–27 March 1998 conference centering on discussion s between the two giants at Ludwig-Maximilians University in Munich. The book also includes a record of each day’s discussion—comments and questions from the audience that are generally insightful and stimulating —plus a Foreword and a Summary by Hans-Werner Sinn. The text accordingly is divided into ve days. The Day One papers examine the sources of each man’s thinking. Buchanan’s origins include his early Tennessee life, his training at Chicago, his discovery of Wicksell and the Italian public nance tradition, and his reaction to the upheavals of the 1960s. His anti-statism and pessimism seems due less to his studies with Knight than to the residue of loss “as a member of a defeated people” in the Civil War (p. 15); Knight served to reinforce his antipathy to pro-nationalist sentiment. Musgrave’s origins include his early European education, his emigration to the United States, his training in the public sector economics (e.g., public goods theory) of Pareto, Wicksell, Lindahl, Samuelson, and Arrow, and his concerns with ethical aspects of public nance. His acceptance of the U.S. political system as “an integral part of a multifaceted socioeconomic order” (p. 31) may well derive from its having provided a haven from Nazi persecution; for him the U.S. system of government represented freedom, not oppression. Day Two has Musgrave addressing the tasks of public nance, and Buchanan’s response. Musgrave defends much of the growth of the public sector ISSN 1042-771 6 print; ISSN 1469-9656 online/00/040499-0 9 Ó DOI: 10.1080/1042771002000625 3 2000 The History of Economics Society 500 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT and surveys the means and ends of each of his tripartite domains of public nance: af rmative policies for production of public goods, transfers for relief of poverty and social insecurity, and macroeconomic scal policy, as well as tax reform. Buchanan decries overproductio n of public goods, says he cannot understand Musgrave’s notion of merit goods, distinguishe s between desirable distributio n and political redistribution , and emphasizes Congressional marketing of tax loopholes. He would justify governmental expenditures for education as promoting equal opportunity , not as producing public goods. Political redistribution (“once you allow politics to get into the distributiona l element” (p. 85)—as if politics is not involved willy nilly in distributio n from the “beginning,” e.g., through providing “protection for property and contract” (p. 83)) is denigrated. He, not inappropriately , says that “if you throw transfers or redistribution s openly into the political arena, you are almost going to guarantee class con ict or the churning state, and you are not necessarily going to get the distributio n going from the rich to the poor or whatever you might like” (pp. 85–86). Buchanan insists that Musgrave “trusts politicians ” whereas he distrusts them, stressing constitutiona l constraint on politicians against Musgrave’s more tolerant and permissive “European” attitude (p. 88). On Day Three, Buchanan presents a brilliant concise exposition of the logic and role of constitutiona l constraints on political action. The constraints are of two types: procedural, such as voting rules, for him ideally unanimity; and domain, limiting the range of legislative choice (“ordinary politics”). Buchanan insists that majority rule leads to “natural discrimination” (though neglecting the power of hold-outs to unanimity etc.). He laments the popular equation of democracy with majoritarianism (though not fully appreciating the role of special interests in any constitution-formation) . Musgrave’s response notes that correlative to the problem of checking the power of government are those of enabling the exercise of power by government and of government checking the power of private interests. His main concern, however, other than to cite changes in Buchanan’s position (“cracks in the armor” (p. 132)), is to defend majority rule, emphasizing the af rmative case for it, the power which anything like unanimity gives to small minorities, the role of coalitions in social cohesiveness, the stability of majority-rule systems, how vote trading may lead to de cient as well as excessive budgets (with no independent test of either), and the place of redistributio n in the budget. Day Four commences with a brilliant policy analysis of scal federalism by Musgrave. Using his tripartite model, he examines taxation and expenditure in unitary, federated, and cooperating independent states, neatly identifying the issues. Among other points, Musgrave says that ef cient spatial arrangements depend upon “the basket of public goods that are demanded and their spatial characteristics” (p. 157) against the backdrop of consideration s of economic ef ciency in juxtapositio n to those of retaining or surrendering national autonomy (p. 155); the limits of the Tiebout model of intergovernmenta l competition (pp. 158ff; see also 188, 193–194), including the point that the “spatial allocation of service functions does not come about automatically but must be implemented by policy design” (p. 160); that distributiona l concerns “must be met largely, if not entirely, at the central level” (p. 161); and that the “structure of federalism BUCHANAN AND MUSGRAVE 501 depends upon the relative desires of member units for independence and diversity and for a more closely knit union” (p. 163). Buchanan’s response emphasizes what he calls the “larger ef ciency” due to limiting the power of government; he calls this political philosoph y as opposed to scal economics, though Musgrave might classify it among the various sensibilitie s that must be accommodated (as above). Buchanan has a sensible dual insight: that federation limits the power of local politicians to impose costs on citizens while enabling more monolithic centralized authority to direct and manage more and more (pp. 180–83), “So federalism is a kind of equilibrium ” (p. 183). He also notes the objective circumstances that in uence a sense of community and loyalty at the level of the nation-state (p. 183). Once one adjusts for his particular antagonism toward the State, Buchanan’s analysis is not so different from Musgrave’s—but that antagonism is pure Buchanan and a central part of the story of both this book and modern public nance, Buchanan’s “public choice” largely emphasizing that antagonism. The question arises, does Buchanan appreciate that his approach is functional less as Truth and more as a particular sensibility , itself serving as a check on government at all levels? In any event, consideration s of competition among governments and exit from a jurisdictio n are important to both men. On Day Five, Buchanan addresses the combined topics of morals, politics, and institutiona l reform. He feels that institutiona l reform to “restore” political order and people’s con dence therein is needed. Such reform must be focused on moral rather than economic-ef ciency considerations . The possibilitie s for helpful reform are limited, but institutiona l modi cations can be made that “facilitate the genuine transformations in behavior patterns that must occur” (p. 206). Buchanan is a sensible constructivist with his own activist agenda. He does not shirk from what has been called the high priest role. He has his own diagnosis of and prescription for society’s supposed ills (for an example of an opposite , and equally presumptuous and tendentious diagnosis, see Isserman and Kazin 1999, the subject of a perceptive critique in Staples 2000; for a more or less comparable diagnosis but a less constructivis t prescription, see Sowell 1999). Buchanan nds that modern society has manifested “an erosion of moral standards” (p. 211) and that this “moral anarchy” is the result of greater opportunitie s for scal redistributio n generating increasingly narrowly de ned and opportunisti c self-seeking in politics (p. 209). Alas, Buchanan (1) downplays how much erosion of “historical traditions” (p. 210, but see 239) is due to markets and market-trained behavior; (2) ignores how much opportunis m etc. exists in relation to non-speci cally redistributiv e governmental activity, e.g., in providing and, of necessity, changing the legal foundations of the economy; (3) minimizes the role of legal change of law and moral change of morals; and (4) either neglects or rejects the fact that modern democratic governments have been, or seemed to have been, increasingly responsive to a wider range of interests, i.e., more than the monarch and his/her courtiers, etc. The logical results of Buchanan’s analyses, now as earlier, are, rst, the maintenance of status quo law and, second, the establishment of a relatively narrow elite. Substantively, however, he is both more permissive and more democratic. 502 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT Buchanan’s pessimism, expressed in part in Cold War terms (individualis m versus collectivism), is rampant. But he is manifestly on target when, rst, he queries, “What is the raison d’etre of the nation-state, as it exists? Simple honesty forces us to acknowledge, in 1998, that little other than history itself ties citizens of national political communities together …” (p. 212)—I ignore the role of national governments as an instrumental means of collective action, e.g., in providing the legal foundations of economy and society—and, second, his af rmation of, “the deliberate organization of federalized structures that embody devolution of authority to units that are suf ciently small to command personal allegiance but that, at the same time, do not evoke tribal urges, de ned broadly to include those based on ethnic, racial, or religious boundaries” (p. 212; see also 222). Perhaps easier said than done, but thus does Buchanan transcend some or much of his seeming neglect of social control along non-market lines—though he does not confront the role of “historical traditions” in fomenting aggression based on “tribal urges.” In this respect I may be more pessimistic than Buchanan. Buchanan appreciates that the classical liberalism of the Enlightenment and Classical political economy is caught in a dilemma. It recognizes the role of markets, under suitable legal and moral conditions , in channeling behavior toward mutually bene cial ends. It also recognizes the need to constrain opportunisti c behavior. But it is threatened in part by the communitarian sentiments that enable law and morals, and in part by a perceived moral anarchy—though the latter, Buchanan rightly (in my view) believes, is preferable to absolutist moral systems of enforced “revealed truth” (pp. 212–16; see also 222). Indeed, he opposes any system in which people have authority that they enjoy exercising by making others subservient (p. 241). Buchanan moves on to institutiona l reform wherein his concern is to reduce the “exaggerated size of the public sector relative to the total economy,” i.e., puncture the “bloated welfare-transfer state” (p. 217). This he would seek by two constitutiona l rules: one limiting the share that public spending bears to GDP at, say, twenty- ve percent, the other requiring that all taxes and spending programs be subject to a generality requirement, the latter to reduce incentives for majoritarian rent seeking (p. 219). Buchanan is convinced that existing spending levels have been generated by a “biased decision process” (p. 218) that permits sequences of majority coalitions to create both higher spending and vast external diseconomies while advancing their own interests. A non-exaggerated level of government spending is a function of and tautologica l with certain political institutions . “Exaggerated” is political rhetoric clothed in the language of institution-dependen t economic-ef ciency analysis (pp. 218–19). Buchanan is not optimistic that such reforms will suf ce to regenerate liberal society—because of what he perceives to be the destruction of social capital: This capital has been eroded only to be replaced by attitudes that embody irresponsibility, dependency, differential exploitation, opportunistic advantage seeking, short-run hedonism, legal trimming, litigation, mistrust, and intolerance, especially for the “politically incorrect” (pp. 220–21). BUCHANAN AND MUSGRAVE 503 Buchanan’s formulaic solution is that, “Ronald Reagan’s evocation of the American Puritans’ promise of a ‘shining city on a hill’ must become more than a romantic dream” (p. 221). Alas, this is but a deployment of myth. Puritan society was not entirely friendly to commercial, market society; it had its own absolutist moral system of revealed truth; and it had its shares of dysfunctiona l “tribal urges.” It is a shame that Buchananite political and moral philosoph y is given voice through a political slogan perpetrating a myth. But given Buchanan’s own mix of freedom and control, continuity and change, and hierarchy and equality, perhaps there is not much deep philosophy with which to work. Buchanan seeks “a stable secure sociopolitica l order” (p. 222), but one that perpetuates his notion of order; classical liberalism is more open than that. The rub comes, in part, when Buchanan says he prefers governments everywhere acting “as instruments of citizens rather than as exploiting agents for rent-seeking coalitions” (p. 222). The problem is, how does one distinguish between the two? In his response, Musgrave challenges in some detail Buchanan’s gloomy assessment of the twentieth century in general and in the United States in particular. Tellingly, Musgrave points to political actions in matters of race, women and other minorities that had arguably bene cial impacts on attitudes, behavior, and morality. He rejects Buchanan’s use of Weberian ideal types (his model of “moral order”) as “states of affairs among which we must choose,” i.e., as desirable or available (p. 226). He rejects Buchanan’s speci c moral order in its pure form as “amoral at best” (p. 226). And he pointedly chastises Buchanan and his spiritual cohorts for acting irresponsibly , “Reforms are needed, but matters have not been helped by the continuous pounding given to government by Professor Buchanan and other critics, thereby adding to the very disrespect for government they seek to reduce (p. 229; Musgrave also notes that “pious Pilgrims burned their witches” (p. 228)). Musgrave thinks Buchanan is part of the problem. Buchanan obviously thinks likewise of Musgrave. Thus, “two contrasting visions of the state.” Yet both men favor liberal market economies; their differences must be seen in a larger perspective. The remaining pages of Musgrave’s response present a warm but friendly indictment of Buchanan’s diagnosis and cure. Musgrave reminded his audience that government has responded to problems in a democratic fashion, that puritan morality cannot solve all problems and, inter alia, that justice is not found only in markets, and that the tragedy of the Samaritan cannot preclude helping those truly in need and “creating institution s wherever possible that preclude such need” (p. 230). One thing that neither Musgrave nor Buchanan consider is the degree to which received law and received morality have been the products of elitist control of society. If, for Buchanan, moral anarchy is preferable to moral absolutism , a wide distributio n of the opportunit y to seek rents may be preferable to a narrow one. But rent-seeking is largely only another name for seeking to change the law. Some instances are clearly disreputable but the general phenomenon is neither disreputable nor unnecessary. Moreover, why should Buchanan et al. be the only ones to program legal change? 504 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT Sinn points out in his introductio n that Musgrave has a “consistentl y favorable view of the bene cial functions of the government sector” whereas Buchanan “has been consistent in his suspicious views of the government” (p. 6) and unwilling “to acquiesce in the conventional presumption that the state, or collectivity , was everywhere benevolent, or, at least, that it may be presumed to be so for the purpose of analytical exercise” (p. 17). Thus stated, the difference is misleading. Certainly Musgrave does not endorse every action of government (otherwise the juxtapositio n of “favorable” to “bene cial” could amount to a tautology), and Buchanan neither opposes all collective action nor rejects the inevitable politicizatio n of the legal framework of markets. Musgrave wants to put government to good use, along allocative, distributional , and stabilizationa l lines, i.e., to enrich and empower the exercise of political choice; whereas Buchanan wants to limit and constrain political choice. Musgrave has a generally af rmative view of government as an institutio n of collective action, whereas Buchanan has a generally hostile view, and this difference almost wholly governs their work. Because Musgrave accepts the inevitably activist state as a factual matter, he has been able to argue that “the proper size of the public sector is, to a signi cant degree, a technical rather than an ideological issue” (Musgrave and Musgrave 1973, p. 5). However, other writers, no less accepting of inexorable governmental activism, nd “no conclusive principle” to govern the size of government (Burkhead and Minor 1971, pp. 98–99). Buchanan has a different quest. As he once wrote to me, he is in search of rules and analyses to provide an invincible intellectual fortress with which to check the power, i.e., activism, of government. In this activity he has been exceptionally imaginative and creative, in part using the power of deduction, combined with his particular ideology, to generate models and results seemingly dispositive of the issues he addresses, yet, in my view, by no means conclusively so. Both men operate within neoclassical economics, Musgrave on its “left” ank and Buchanan on its “right.” Both, for example, accept methodologica l individualism (though Musgrave posits a social welfare function), and both use some form of a voluntary exchange approach in analyzing government. But whereas Buchanan found in Knut Wicksell a unanimity principle, Musgrave found concern about prior distribution . Whereas Buchanan decries the exercise of public choice, Musgrave sees it as an inherent part of the scal state (pp. 39, 49, and passim). Both men stress the need for knowledge of the predictable consequences of particular government policies. Buchanan started out as “a committed ‘libertarian socialist’.” Study with Frank Knight at Chicago converted him to a “libertarian advocate of laissez-faire within limits.” The original position, he relates, was “libertarian in my conviction that politicized restrictions on individual liberties should be minimized” and “socialist in my judgment that only political action could break up and control the power concentrations that directed economic life.” The later position stressed “the coordinating properties of markets” (p. 16). This is the Chicago position that markets are inherently competitive or power diffusing. But what happened to the nominally private concentrations of power that form and manipulate both BUCHANAN AND MUSGRAVE 505 markets and the legal foundations of markets? Buchanan has read Vilfredo Pareto’s sociologica l work but came away seemingly with only the obscurantist narrow slice of “Pareto optimality” and left behind the rest of the master’s model of mutual manipulation —at the stages of both constitution and legislation. This is particularly egregious because Buchanan’s adoption of Wicksellian unanimity, or approximate unanimity, amounts to both building in past use of power at both stages—violating Wicksell’s requirement that existing distribution have approval—and gives to a minority a veto over change of law. Buchanan’s ostensible libertarianism seems to have trumped his socialism. Buchanan faults John Rawls’s use of procedural justice to generate a speci c result (p. 57). But something lies behind and trumps Buchanan’s affection for markets and protection of the individual against social control: His vision of a good society and the dangers to it that he perceived in the 1960s. He writes of how his “own attitudes toward both the vulnerabilit y and viability of the American socio-economic-politica l order were dramatically modi ed,” of how “Methods, manners, morals and standards were cavalierly tossed on the junk heap of history” (p. 22)—all in addition to the perceived “ scal irresponsibil ity” generated by “Keynesian nostrums” (p. 23). Buchanan is caught on the horns of the objectivity versus advocacy dilemma. He writes that neither he nor Musgrave “approaches the subject matter ideologically, in the ordinary meaning of the term. Neither of us start from some preconceived political-philosophica l stance, and neither of us has been associated closely with this or that political party, movement, or cult” (p. 14; he does acknowledge that they have different “visions,” p. 14). He describes his own modeling of revenue-maximizing government as “precautionary” rather than descriptive (p. 24), but his prescriptive work clearly assumes such a state in his effort to limit majoritarian democracy—and to do so in ways that “do not seem to undermine majoritarianism” (p. 26). One problem is that government must willy-nilly choose between competing interests and no principle of generality, such as “the rule of law,” will avoid this problem (pp. 26–27, 41). But Buchanan’s dif dence is belied by the strong policy prescriptions he draws from his ostensibly “precautionary” models: It has long seemed to me that he has chosen and developed his models to both give effect to his vision and promote the policy conclusions to which they “lead”/which are built into them. Musgrave’s work, of course, does more or less likewise, though without the more evident strident vision—representing a contemporary version of the old German approach to managing the scal household, now under democratic rather than monarchical conditions . (My own view is sympathetic to both anarchic libertarianism and criticisms of elite use of government while stressing the descriptive and interpretive importance of social control and governmental choice in all systems and how both Buchanan’s and Musgrave’s approaches constitute an agenda for government.) Buchanan does recognize the critical relationship between the performance of the public sector and political structure (p. 19 and passim) and this is something that Musgrave insists upon. It is the basis of his explicit resort to the concept of a social welfare function, whereas Buchanan has only an implicit one in his 506 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT prescriptions about structure and whose preferences get to count in public choice. Musgrave’s positivis m lies not in any ultimate focus on description but in his search for the most ef cient and effective means to achieve allocative, distributive , and stabilizatio n ends. But it is predicated upon the acceptance—at least in part, if not large part—as “legitimate” (p. 64) of the growth of the public sector in the twentieth century; it is neither optimal nor un awed but necessary (p. 65). He accepts cost-bene t analysis as a policy tool notwithstandin g its limitations. Both men invoke “ef ciency” in the public sector as if it were more or less an objective matter. Both of them prefer ef ciency-enhancing to ef ciency-reducing policies but do not acknowledge that ef ciency is a matter of whose interests are to count and that that is very much what politics is all about—even if one decries the “churning” state. Both of them tend, therefore, to act as high priests, especially perhaps Buchanan, who is very much alert to the need to manipulate public opinion, for example, emphasizing the challenge of making sure that ostensibly ef ciency-enhancing political institution s “be seen as such by participants in the inclusive collective enterprise” (p. 126; see 205–23). Alas, there are no more unique ef cient institution s than unique ef cient resource allocations. Pervading these discussion s are the consequences of the problem of seeking nondiscriminator y policy in a world of inequality. Harold M. Groves emphasized the paradox that treating unequals equally is to treat them unequally, whereas treating unequals unequally may be the only way to treat them equally. One problem, of course, is to determine what is the operative inequality, another is how to deal with it, and still another is how to pay for it. What does/can “equal opportunity” mean in a world of material inequality— not only of wealth but of access to government? Both minorities and majorities have captured and used state power to abuse and take advantage of others, in part by structuring markets in ways that bene t them. Patriotism, morality, and religion have been the bastion of many types of scoundrels. There are no easy solutions to the putative problems and failures of collective action. I say “putative” because most problems have roots deeper than the government policy under immediate discussion , because purported and actual objectives vary, because gains and costs are correlative and subject to selective perception, and because creation and destruction, and freedom and control/repression always co-exist, typically for different people. All this, in part, is what politics is all about. One thing is very clear: Both Buchanan and Musgrave have given their disciples the analytical tools and agendas with which to advance their respective visions or ideologies, and careers. The tension between their respective approaches has simultaneousl y marked public sector economics since the 1950s and comprised a microcosm of the legal-economic world around them. Whereas Musgrave’s work is more prosaic than Buchanan’s, but surely exasperating to those who share Buchanan’s world view, Buchanan’s may be more stimulating but no less exasperating to those who would take a less ideological and less obscurantist view of the economic role of government—especially the anarchist who nds selective state activism in both men’s systems. BUCHANAN AND MUSGRAVE 507 A question occurs to me: Both are decent men. Has Buchanan failed and Musgrave succeeded in internalizing their respective relations to authority, i.e., resolving the con ict of adolescence between freedom and security? Or is the matter different? Musgrave, for his part, has witnessed Nazi and U.S. authority; it is not surprising that he is prepared to accept in principle the latter, warts and all. Buchanan, on the other hand, carries with him, at least in part, the burden of his family’s Civil War heritage and an acquired ideology. For all of Buchanan’s emphasis on individual liberty, he rejects, rebels against, and deeply resents the “anarchistic” challenges to established authority and culture that took place in the 1960s and the extension of access to government that transpired over two centuries. Surely more is going on in his mind than the mechanics of public choice, as anti-government as is his version thereof. One feels sorry for his pain caused by his sour attitude toward the system of government to which so many elsewhere have sought to migrate from abroad; one sympathizes with his, and Musgrave’s, identi cation of its warts. Buchanan’s contribution s may be more stimulating and Musgrave’s more prosaic but both scholars are too involved with either current events, selectively perceived developments, and/or partisan issues. Neither gives enough attention to what I consider empirical legal-economic fundamentals and what public nance and public choice as social control are, at bottom, all about. Each is too involved with policy congruent with their respective visions of the world. For example, some elaborate unbiased attention should be given to a set of problems, pertaining to the welfare state, raised in the discussion: pressure on its cost during periods of unemployment, when the needs increase; the greater dif culty of raising money from mobile factors in a global economy, when the needs also increase; and so on (pp. 237, 242). Both men, therefore, are activist and directed to reform. That their respective orientations (ideologies, visions) , general agendas, and substantive proposals vary does not obviate this fundamental point. For each man “positive” analysis is subordinate and instrumental to being the power behind the throne, to enjoying the social role of the expert, the man of knowledge. So much for doing away with, or limiting, the power of the throne, even in the form of representative democracy. But that is what the history of public- nance—and public choice— thought is largely all about, in a world in which experts participate in but do not substitut e for the process of working things out. Accordingly, this book provides splendid history of and insight into contemporary economic thought. It is especially valuable when the ideas of the two contestants are held at arm’s length—as dif cult as that may be. REFERENCES Burkhead, Jesse and Jerry Miner. 1971. Public Expenditures. Chicago: Aldine, Atherton. Isserman, Maurice and Michael Kazin. 1999. America Divided: The Civil War of the 1960s. New York: Oxford University Press. Musgrave, Richard A. and Peggy Musgrave. 1973. Public Finance in Theory and Practice. New York: McGraw-Hill. Sowell, Thomas. 1999. The Quest for Cosmic Justice. New York: Free Press. Staples, Brent. 2000. “Blaming Nixon.” New York Times Book Review, January 20, p. 10.