the intermediate situation. on affection and time in michel

Anuncio
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y vida, 23-37.
e-ISSN: 1885-1088
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION.
ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
LA SITUACIÓN INTERMEDIA.
SOBRE LA AFECCIÓN Y EL TIEMPO EN MICHEL HENRY
John David Barrientos
Fenomenología y Filosofía Primera/
Universidad Pontificia de Comillas, España
[email protected]
Abstract: When we go back -by means of the
epoché of the world, following Michel Henrytowards the originary “how” of all manifestation
(videor), we stumble once and again upon the
phenomenological situation of the body. The
body is, then that originary hinge by means of
which I manifest world in a continuous resistance. It will be, as well, within my own body
where I am always aware of oneself, according
to my own affection (self-affection, not previously constituted). Thus, the material condition
of the body will be that of my internal body, or
subjective body -as Henry initially read in Maine
de Biran- or that of my flesh, as Henry himself
would later say. Bearing all this in mind, the
intermediate situation of one’s own affection, of
this body of mine, with regard to the world and
the videor, turns out to be an appropriate medium to attempt a preliminary study of the
problematic situation of the internal time of
affection. For this purpose, we shall revise the
analysis offered by Michel Henry in Material
Phenomenology and in Incarnation, indicating
possible aporias, as well as alternatives to these last ones.
Resumen: Cuando, siguiendo a Michel Henry,
retrocedemos en una epoché hacia el “cómo”
originario de toda manifestación (videor), tropiezamos una y otra vez con la situación fenomenológica del cuerpo. El cuerpo es, pues, esta
bisagra originaria a través de la cual yo manifiesto el mundo en continua resistencia. También será dentro del propio cuerpo donde uno
será siempre autoconsciente, de acuerdo con la
propia afección (autoafección, no constituida
previamente). Por eso, la condición material del
cuerpo será la de mi cuerpo interior o cuerpo
subjetivo, de acuerdo con la lectura inicial que
Henry hace de Maine de Biran; o de mi carne,
como dirá el mismo Henry más tarde. Teniendo
en cuenta todo ello, la situación intermedia,
situación de la afección propia y la de mi cuerpo
en relación con el mundo y el videor, resulta ser
un medio apropiado para emprender un estudio
preliminar de la problemática situación del
tiempo interno de la afección. Para ello, revisaremos el análisis que Michel Henry ofrece en
Material Phenomenology y en Incarnation, indicando las posibles aporías, así como posibles
alternativas.
Key Words: Body, Michel Henry, Self-Affection,
Time.
Palabras clave: Cuerpo, Michel Henry, autoafección, tiempo.
Through our reading of Michel Henry and following his epoché -which goes
from the world to the essence of manifestation-, we find in his approach of time
24
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
the turning point which places us before the following alternative: either we go
with him to the end, that is, to his considerations on absolute Life, or either we
pay more attention to the richness that time can hold in my life. We believe
that this last option is possible if we approach it at the same time that we approach self-affection.
The possibilities would be: either we follow the epoché till we affirm the
phenomenal basis of all manifestation in absolute Life (in what follows: Life) or
either we suspend this step and we explore the situation of subjective tension
of time as self-affection. Here we try to go through the way of the second possibility. Our main reason is that this would allow us to suggest ways that make
us glimpse and take notice of another form of manifestation of my life, that is,
that of a sense that comes to me. Therefore, it is not either a matter of ascribing the foundation of absolute manifestation exclusively to the ek-stasis itself
(as Henry would do); in any case, however, it may not be necessary to absolutely exclude the object as ek-stasis presented to consciousness, since we will
still have to study more closely the manifestation of the “duration” of temporal
objects within time consciousness and through the intentional matter. We will
speak thus of the intermediate situation -hinge- of subjectivity, that is: my finite life “finitising” itself (if I may use the expression) at each moment in my
finite action and according to the corporeal subjective whole which is inner subjective body (Biran) or my flesh (Henry).
1
Let us go right to the heart of the matter. For this purpose, let us pay attention to the question repeatedly posed by Michel Henry about the “how” of all
that appears. With this question, he tries to avoid any path that would divert
him from the origin of manifestation, that is, ultimately, Life. He has arrived to
Life, the essence of manifestation (after the epoché) through self-affection.
Self-affection is initially affection (feeling) of oneself; it is feeling oneself in order to be later pathos of my life as well as vital matter of Life, which is primordially manifested by the pathos as pleasure-pain. Let us point out that it is precisely this pathos that guarantees that we will not fall in the infinite questioning
about the “how”, since it will be a question with material content and bound
24
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
25
within material immediateness, and not an intentional presentation of sense and not at all a representation-.
Let us continue what we have just said. If we ask ourselves “What is manifested?”, we would answer “Phenomena” (advancing what follows: lived world,
my life). Let us see why. If we pay attention to the method, we see that the
question is focused on the “what” of what is manifested. This “what” is necessarily related to a movement characterized as “to” (towards), since a “what”
manifested in the question contains an intentional “something”. This is so even
if we ask ourselves “what is a 'what' that is manifested?”, as it is a movement
that allows us to direct the question to a possible “what”. But it is not an empty
question, for it involves that I take for manifested something that manifests
itself: one or several possible “what”, evident phenomena, about which there
would remain much to say regarding its manifestation.
However, this intentional condition, the “what” of phenomena, is such because I can speak of it manifesting its evidence. Otherwise, I would be completely blind to the question itself. In fact, once the question would be posed
and once we would have considered the possibility that it contains, that would
be no place for such blindness. Therefore, if we speak about the possibility of
giving an answer concerning “a” something manifested (“a” something-here,
“a” something-there, or “some” somethings there, etc.), then I already have a
certain determination of this something. Such determination exists whether it is
an exploration of something partially determined (of the “something manifested” sort) or whether it is the question itself, “What is manifested?” In both cases, we refer to phenomena and we expect to specify their particular kind.
At first it seems that asking “what is manifested?” is possible only because
there are things that are, entities: all that is outside there before me; this includes me and all the others like me, all and everyone, being in something like
the “world-space”. However, if I am really coherent with what it seems to be
manifested, I have to pay attention to the first and immediate doubt (doxa) by
virtue of which this outside-world comes as a question. Through this doxa, I
reflexively take notice of the world to which I seem to address my questions;
but at the same time I see that the doubt itself was already within me, before
this outside so outside, exterior to me, that simultaneously seems so mine.
Therefore, my natural “to say” -that is, the “to say” of the many- about all this
outside had already a deadly wound. Already in the first moment in which this
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
25
26
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
question about this outside of knowledge emerges -which I take for naturalthere is no way back; for what I thought it was natural and seemed real is already doomed to irreality, if we understand “reality” in terms of entities among
entities. Therefore, the phenomenon itself demands us to deepen into its manifestation as manifested phenomena.
Nevertheless, we also see that even if we try to introduce from the beginning terms like “phenomenon” and “manifestation”, they seem to resist being
understood in the terms of being and entity. This is due to the fact that, next to
the affirmation of the phenomenon (the first answer to the “What is manifested?” question), we are submerged in our own doubting, a doubting of immediate apperception (M. Biran). In this doubt, I am before the manifestation of a
world external to me, transcendent, with a duration that does not seem to be
mine; here too manifest themselves “appearings” to which attention is paid, as
well as “appearings” that are supposed, felt, suggested, imagined, dreamed,
etc. within a duration that seems to be mine.
We then ask ourselves, “How is all this possible?” or better, “How is it possible that everything is manifested the way it seems to be manifested?” Here
we are before the beginning of an option, of a bet: start from an epoché, elimination of the outside, the most outside of the world, and postponing the answer
to the question “What is manifested?” till we are on our way back, when the
possible answer, “phenomena are manifested” will reach as much as the answer to the question “How they are manifested?”1 can reach. Perhaps we may
be allowed to keep here this reserve, as its starting point is the collapse of the
truth of the world, and the manifestation of phenomena paradoxically depends
on giving a supposed world (not lived) the exclusivity of every possible truth, as
Henry would say.
So far we have focused on what could be manifested and on the possible
question about an appearing of something that we call phenomenon; we are
not dealing here with a physical world in the sense of the external to me in an
exteriority that is such not only regarding me, but an exteriority that seems
alien to me in a space that belongs to it, a space founded by the things them-
1
Concerning the object of phenomenology as the “object in the mode of the 'how'”, cf. Michel Henry,
Phénoménologie matérielle, Paris, PUF, 1990, p.26 —in what follows quoted as PM—.
26
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
27
selves, a space previous to all appearing which is possible as a phenomenon.
That is, we speak about the world of mere things.
On the other hand, if we pay attention to the mode of the manifestation,
we see that we are immediately referred to an appearing to me of the phenomenon. As we can see, the path we have so far followed goes from the worldphenomenon to the ego. However, to say ego meaning “me” means “lived ego
(me) living world (phenomena)”. That is, phenomena are manifested as being
lived by me, since otherwise I could not say anything of them and they could
not manifest to me as lived by me; even less could we suggest a predicative
judgement that said anything of them; and even less could we communicate
this judgement with a minimal distance from the very manifestation of the phenomenon. In this last case, in which we speak about phenomenological distance, we would already be suggesting a judgement in a new Erlebnis -this time
presented by my lived ego- on the basis of the first Erlebnis, the one of a lived
phenomenon experienced in the mode of Erlebnis [erlebt], in the immediateness of its manifestation.
2
Let us stop and analyse this very issue following this other path, that is, the
“lived ego – living world”, that deepens into –and even founds- the initially indicated relationship in terms of ego-world, which in the end will reveal itself to be
a situation, as we shall see.
The manifestation of myself takes place in my most radical immanence, in
an individual immediate apperception of me and to me. This manifestation occurs particularly –it seems- by virtue of myself. The manner how this “ego living itself” manifests itself is possible within reflection as power of my ego: that
is, reflection as power of my subjectivity, as studied by Henry in Philosophie et
phenomenologie du corps2. We would be speaking, then, of my ego living itself
and at the same time conscious of this, of my ego present to itself and present
from itself. This reflection, a reflection that itself appears and that manifests my
subjectivity in immediate apperception, is already equipped with its own and
2
Michel Henry, Philosophie et phénoménologie du corps. Essai sur l'ontologie biranienne, 5ª édition,
PUF, Paris, 2003.
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
27
28
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
first movement (power) within the complex of my subjective body; this is called
by Henry “inner transcendental experience”.
When we turn to immediate apperception we see that it manifests itself,
apparently, as a perception addressed to itself: a taking notice of oneself living,
being, perceiving oneself. But in its very appearing, this apperception is manifested as immediate consciousness that assists in person or gives originarily the
manifestation of all appearing; the difference is that now this manifestation
speaks of itself, and of apperception itself, according to consciousness in the
temporal flux of oneself. That is to say, now the originary situation of apperception occurs in the consciousness of living myself in the continuum of Erlebnis,
that is, in “time consciousness” (as Husserl would say) or in the “living present”
(Henry).
In this sense, according to Henry’s critique, Husserl’s consciousness –as far
as it is impression- would initially be self-impression, and its analysis would not
have been consequently followed till the last and originary phenomenal effectuations in the material (hylé) line of apperception. For Husserl, intentionality referred to the quality of the object of intention3 –noematically given- had more
importance than the possibilities of originary impression4. Nevertheless, as we
shall see, the difficulty lies here not only in the relationships of consciousness,
perception, impression and distancing –or the lack of it- with regard to sensations; in fact, all this problem must be analysed along with the analysis of lived
time in its manifestation, in time consciousness, since it is there that the answer to the “Originary ‘how’ of manifestation”, could find its possible horizon.
3
Once we are situated in the self through immediate apperception, we see
that it appears as being constituted in the impression, affected in immediate
experience. That is, the self, before it is subject of itself, is lived self in its immediateness, a self that assists to its own manifestation in the passage (in du-
3
Husserl's text from Ideen, 339, quoted and commented by Henry (Michel Henry. Incarnation. Une
philosophie de la chair, Paris, Seuil, 2000, p. 72 — in what follows quoted as I—).
4
However, we would still have to come back to the hyletic situation of intentionality and the material
object. In this task, we would have to refer to the first edition of the Logische Untersuchungen and to
the reading of the fifth investigation proposed by Miguel García-Baró. Cf. Miguel García-Baró, Teoría
fenomenológica de la verdad. Comentario continuo a la primera edición de Investigaciones Lógicas de
Edmund Husserl, Madrid, Universidad Pontificia de Comillas, 2008, p. 118.
28
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
29
ration) of impressive apperception. Michel Henry sees in the centrality of impression -with regard to the “how” of the manifestation of oneself, as well as
that of the manifestation of the world- a point in which to meet Husserl. However –says Henry- this centrality later disappears and instead of it we have the
centrality of phenomenological distance, a distance set by intentional consciousness within time consciousness, in the retentions and protentions; here,
Henry sees the ek-stasis of time in which the arch-impression decays.
Let us focus on this last point. In the distance of intentional consciousness with regard to its intentional basis5-, the situation of the flux of manifestation of
time consciousness is revealed. This distance, which is the distance of the temporal flux in its condition of a “before” retained in the “now” (retention) and a
“now” disclosing what is coming (protention), is in Henry the breaking point in
which the ek-stasis of manifestation is established, and the ek-stasis of manifestation is finally that of the world and its nothingness. That is, the material
component of manifestation, the originary impression, is set as put by consciousness and exiled in a temporal flux that does not contain it. Here, manifestation does not deepen into the manifestation within the living present, but it
gives in before the temporal flux of temporal points in the course of time consciousness.
Now we can see that what we called “self” does not present so much a constituted or manifested condition as it seems. In fact, if we remained in the confirmation of the manifestation of oneself as a self, we would have two aspects
to consider: the affection of oneself in immediate apperception as impression of
oneself; and the temporal course of the manifestation of oneself as affection. It
is between these two aspects that the bet for the radicalisation of affection as
the pathos of life is decided. Likewise, we are set before the difficult situation of
considering whether the temporal ek-static course of an object is always materially emptied or not.
4
Speaking of each phase in the temporal flux, Husserl says that “the constant form is always once again full of ‘content’ and the content is nothing that
5
In this article "basis" corresponds to "fondo" in Spanish.
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
29
30
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
comes to fit from outside”6. Thus, the fact that the form is once again filled with
content does not mean that the form of the flux, at a certain moment, can be
empty of any content. Although an objectivation of the flux –in the mode of
geometry7 - can show abysses of nothingness between the temporal phases–
like, for example, between the “now” and the retained phase-, this does not
happen in impression. The temporal form impression in the immanence of its
manifestation is the “continuum” of a whole (if the expression is allowed): an
“at the same time” of the manifestation of time as a flux.
Situated in subjective time, retention and protention are “material contents” that fill the current of the flux in a way that is different from that of the
sole “now”: protention is a “coming to the ‘now’”, it is not a simple “is coming”,
it is an expectation gerund (a “seeing something coming”) and this gerund is
filled in the impression, it is either letting down or fulfilling in immediate apperception; and retention is the “now” leaving in the arch-impression. As for the
passage, that is, the lived as already passing, is tied to a “now” that is
impressional and affective. We can call it affective memory, which would have a
double condition: a) that of a new content filling my “now” and “modifying” it;
and b) that of being the possibility of a new “now” manifested by the evocation
of what has been lived.
Husserl came to the temporal form in the Lessons8 along with the study of
temporal objects, in which he explains the originary form of the flux, since for
6
The full quote reads as follows: “Verbleibend ist vor allem die formale Struktur des Fluffes, die Form
des Fluffes. D. h. das Fließen ist nicht nur überhaupt Fließen, fondern jede Phase ist von einer und
derselben Form, die beständige Form ist immer neu von ‘Inhalt’ erfüllt, aber der Inhalt ist eben nichts
äußerlich in die Form Hineingebrachtes, fondern durch die Form der Gesetzmäßigkeit bestimmt: nur so,
dass diese Gesetzmäßigkeit nicht allein das Konkretum bestimmt. Die Form besteht darin, dass ein jezt
ist konstituiert durch eine Impression und dass an diese ein Schwanz von Retentionen ist angliedert und
ein Horizont der Protentionen." Edmund Husserl, Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren
Zeitbewusstseins hrsg. von Martin Heidegger, Niemeyer, Halle, 1928, p. 467.
7
Concerning this issue and that of continuous time, García-Baró states: "El tiempo debe quedar libre de
toda atadura con la interpretación en términos de continuo, cuando por tal se está entendiendo, como
era evidentemente el caso en Brentano y en el joven Husserl, tan discípulo suyo, el tipo de ser que pertenece al espacio idealizado de la geometría. Esa interpretación espacializante e idealizadora puede muy
bien ser la que abre, en el fondo, la puerta a todo empirismo, porque permite ensayar a entender el
presente de la vida de la conciencia como un punto o límite, en el que luego puede uno pensar que cruzan sus fuerzas, estáticamente, una interpretación y un reducido o grande acervo de contenidos representantes de las cosas externas. No tiene, sin embargo, por qué haber nada de esto en la conciencia".
Miguel García-Baró, Vida y mundo. La práctica de la fenomenología, Editorial Trotta, Valladolid, 1999, p.
274.
8
We refer to the Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (in what follows quoted
as VPIZ). We have taken much into account the introductory study by Agustín Serrano de Haro to the
spanish translation that has been translated and prepared by him. (Cf. Edmund Husserl, Lecciones de
fenomenología de la conciencia interna del tiempo —traducción, introducción y notas de Agustín Serrano
de Haro—, Madrid, Editorial Trotta, 2002). I have also taken into account Manuel Abella's paper about
this book (Cf. Manuel Abella, "Edmund Husserl: Génesis y estructura de las Lecciones de fenomenología
30
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
31
this objects its matter (hylé) is in their temporal form. In their manifestation,
they are not tied to a temporal form given by intentional consciousness 9 and
later materially filled by the impression as –for example- a phenomenon –
sound. Rather, the sound10, in its manifestation, allows the affirmation of the
ontological difference11 and its temporality, that is: when we follow in its living
flowing (Consciousness) the temporal flux of impression (this would be the
videor “side” of the difference) about the sound, there is “simultaneously” the
manifestation of the sound as such sound in its form-matter of temporal flux
(this would be the videre mundum “side” of the difference). Likewise, the temporal flux of arch-impression –that initially seems to be “the object consciousness that itself is not object”- is announced as self-affection lived in the temporal flux: “originary impression”12, on one side, and on the other side remains
the question about how it is given what makes possible the reflection by virtue
of which I can go to each continuous point of the manifestation of sound13.
All this is in contrast with Henry’s capital critique of Husserl14, which is precisely about the manifestation of impression at the expense of the intentional
de la conciencia interna del tiempo", ∆αι´µων. Revista de Filosofía, nº 34 (2005), 143-152 —Versión
digital en: http://digitum.um.es/xmlui/handle/10201/9105—).
9
VPIZ, 464. "lch kann auf irgend eine Phase diefer Erscheinung achten: Erscheinung ist hier der
immanente Ton oder die immanente Tonbewegung, abgesehen von seiner ‘Bedeutung’. Das ist aber
nicht das letzte Bewusstsein. Dieser immanente Ton ‘konstituiert’ flieh, nämlich kontinuierlich mit dem
jeweiligen Ton jetzt haben wir auch die Tonerschattungen, und zwar stellt fich in diesen die Strecke der
Tonvergangenheiten, die zu diesem jetzt gehören, dar."
10
Once the form of the flux is determined by impression, once the protentions and retentions are their
permanent form, and once we have the change of the proto-fact of “the consciousness of the change of
impression into retention, as continuously we have once again an impression”, says Husserl, we arrive to
“the question about time consciousness in which the time of time consciousness of the phenomenasound is constituted” ("Wir kommen bei dieser Flussfassung also - wie schon früher angedeutet - auf die
Frage nach dem Zeitbewusstsein, in dem flieh die Zeit des Zeitbewusstseins der Tonerscbeinungen
konstituiert." VPIZ, 467).
11
We assume here the formulation that García-Baró makes of the ontological difference in terms of
Videre video mundum (I see –it appears- that I see world) in his introductory study to the Spanish
translation of Phénoménologie matérielle.
12
Husserl speaks about the originary impression and its relationship with conciousness as follows: "Die
Urimpression ist der absolute Anfang dieser Erzeugung, der Urquell, das, woraus alles andere stetig flieh
erzeugt. Sie selber aber wird nicht erzeugt, sie entsteht nicht als Erzeugtes, sondern durch genesis
spontanea, Sie ist Urzeugung. Sie erwächst nicht (sie hat keinen Keim), sie ist Urschöpfung. Heißt es:
stetig bildet fich an das Jetzt, das sich zum Nicht- Jetzt modifiziert, ein neues Jetzt an, oder es erzeugt,
es entspringt urplötlich eine Quelle, so find das Bilder. Es kann nur gefragt werden: Bewusstsein ist
nichts ohne Impression." VPIZ, 451.
13
Cf. Husserl, Beilage VI of VPIZ, 469: "Wir haben also ein stetiges Bewusstsein, von dem jeder Punkt
ein stetiges Kontinuum ist. Das ist aber wieder eine Zeitreihe, auf die wir achten können. Also geht das
Spiel von neuem los. Fixieren wir irgendeinen Punkt dieser Reihe, so scheint dazu ein
Vergangenheitsbewusstfein gehören zu müssen, das sich auf die Serie der vergangenen Reihen bezieht
usw", likewise, I think that Husserl helps us seeing the importance of this issue in VPIZ §36. Der
zeitkonstituierende Fluß als absolute Subjektivität.
14
PM, 39.
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
31
32
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
form of the temporal flux, which eventually is ek-stasis of the world15. This last
point is considered by Henry because he sees retention and protention as empty points of present without impression, without phenomenal matter. The distance is established by intentional consciousness in its passive syntheses which,
passive as they may be –phenomenally speaking-, have this component which
we could characterise as “respective”; here, what is coming to the present is
not still living present, and what is passing to an already lived point is not living
present either; in no one of these cases we have the filled “now” of impression.
There would be no way either to ask about the originary manifestation (the
“how”) of impression, since in any case the impression would escape through
the form of the temporal flux. There would remain just “the so called present
phase, which is only an ideal limit between two abysses of nothingness”16. Being fair with regard to this last quotation, Henry says that Husserl, from this
intentional phase of present, passes to a “now” constituted by impression;
however, Henry adds that this “now” is in Husserl incapable of answering to the
question about the originary “how” of impression, since this impression is
thrown to the already mentioned temporal intentional flux.
Thus, we do not take into account the strength that belongs to the living
present in impression as originary impression, that will later be for Henry impression of oneself manifest as subjective flesh and corporeality which gives
world within continuous resistance.
Thus, although “in the flux fundamentally nothing that is not not-flux can
enter”17 –and thus we can say that the phenomenological distances of the flux
are extremely shortened, without them becoming totalised as present and
without them being alien to the originary impression-, this would not be, according to Henry, the capital problem. Following this, we place the beginning of
the first alternative in a first moment; here, the issue Henry deals with is where
the impression comes from and how it takes charge of us.
15
In PM, 109, Henry places the problem of the ek-stasis in the cogitatio, the life, and its corresponding
absence as it is placed in the past (following his critique of Husserl). Thus, the situation of life -or rather,
of its absence- is identified with the situation of the world and its ek-static nothingness (as the manifestation is erroneously made dependent of this situation of the world)
16
I, 78.
17
VPIZ, 466. (also quoted by Henry in I, 77.)
32
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
33
5
Thus, this situation makes us eventually make the option of analysing selfaffection, my “feeling myself”; there is here the guarantee given by the adjustment of immanence and immediateness of manifestation in the form of present affection -lived in each “now”, without any distance, without escape, without intentionality-; this would be the path of no return of Appearing of appearance, that is: the transcendental hyletic basis to which must point the answer
to the question about the “how” of manifestation, the “how” of impression, the
originary and founding “how”. Furthermore, this phenomenal basis is, in Henry,
something prius with regard to time18.
What we call originary impression is harboured in what is studied by Henry
as the “subjective body” of Maine de Biran. It is our own body that gives the
first horizon of impression as self-affection; it is the immediate and immanent
“feeling myself”. In this feeling, two senses of manifestation could be read –and
simultaneously keeping the ontological difference-:
a) That of subjective corporeal whole, corporeity, that reveals world as it
lives this world within continuous resistance. This resistance is given by the
body and its complex of sensations, categories (faculties), movement, memory,
habit, etc.19. This is so whether I refer to my own felt itching or to bug that in
me and of me (of my body) is made manifest as bug within resistance -in this
case, its manifestation would be, for example, that of “my lived world of a-bugthat-bites-me” or “lived world of the knowledge of the bugs that bite”. We may
say that the last formulation corresponds to the most “ek-static” situation in
manifestation -situation of distance- that we find in Henry, that is: the situation
that would be about “transcendent world” and its manifestation, where material-substantial reality appears in corporeity as continuous resistance according
to the already mentioned bodily complex and clearly apart from the noematic
that is intentionally constituted.
18
This topic is analysed in my paper “Logos de mi carne viva. Acerca de la relación vida-lenguaje en
Encarnación de Michel Henry", Cuadernos CANELA, Vol. XXI (2010), 61-76. (on-line:
http://www.jdbarrientos.com/logos-de-mi-carne-viva).
19
On the resistent continuum and this bodily complex, cf. my paper "Cinco datos fenomenológicos: preliminares para una ontología de la subjetividad a partir de Michel Henry lector de Maine de Biran" Research Bulletin (Nihon University), 60 (2008), 29-54. (on-line: http://www.jdbarrientos.com/cinco-datosfenomenologicos)
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
33
34
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
b) The other sense lies also in the same bodily complex, but now -and accordingly with what we studied in the previous section (4) about impressionwe do not pay attention to any constitution whatsoever or to passive syntheses
of time consciousness in originary manifestation of subjective life. When we
dealt with the flux of “originary impression”, we spoke about the “proto-fact of
change of time consciousness” in Husserl, as here the focus is placed on the
radicalisation of impression in its subjective corporeal immanence. It is radicalisation until we see living the most passive basis, the only possible one. It is the
basis that Husserl points to in the constituting flow and which is characterised
as a “river”; even if we refer to it “according to the constituted”, “it is nothing
'objective' in time”; it is “absolute subjectivity”:
It is absolute subjectivity and it has the absolute properties of what in image has to be characterised as “flux”, “river”, as something that springs in a
point of actuality, a point which is a primordial source, etc. In the Erlebnis of
actuality we have the point which is the primordial source and a continuity of
echo-moments. For all this we lack names20.
As we mentioned earlier, this flux has no place in the primordial horizon of
Life that -in Henry's research- previously founds the manifestation of everything. Life as well is prius to the flux in which there is no place for non-flux
moments, even in the case that this flux can open to the deepening of this very
flux in terms of absolute subjectivity in the Erlebnis of actuality. However, concerning the living present in Henry -referred to self-affection and in contrast to
the flux that we have explained following Husserl-, there are two points that
are halfway between the living present and the flux -even if it is almost only in
this moment of the epoché of inner time-: a) the present of self-affection, on
Henry's side and the “now” of the Erlebnis of actuality in Husserl; b) also in
both cases, the material immanent “component” that impression is -although,
as we can see, with different scopes in their phenomenal basis-.
20
"Es ist die absolute Subjektivität und hat die absoluten Eigenschaften eines im Bilde als ‘Fluß’ zu
Bezeichnenden, in einem Aktualitätspunkt, Urquellpunkt, ‘Jetzt’ Entspringenden usw. Im
Aktualitätserlebnis haben wir den Urquellpunkt und eine Kontinuität von Nachhallmomenten. Für all das
fehlen uns die Namen." VPIZ, 429.
34
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
35
6
We have then a present, an “each now”, that we can say it is full in
originary impression. Its condition of present is manifested in my subjectivity
and from my subjectivity; here we would be on the side of videor with regard to
originary manifestation and we would be entering the most previous side of
ontological difference, of what we initially called -somehow incorrectly- ego
manifested. Thus, if we keep Henry's initial bet for the power of the subjective
body as reflexive movement, we do not have an empty distance of oneself, that
would present subjectivity to oneself. Rather, we keep an “intentional-material
quasi-distance” that as self-affection fills subjectivity, and simultaneously reveals it as finite life and subjective body.
This is so if we hold to the manifestation of subjectivity according to the
subjective body in the form of self-affection and giving as a whole (and at the
same time), within affective immediateness, the categories (faculties). All this
according to the movement of reflective immanence which does not get to, and
does not find the power to substantialise21 the subjective life into Life; therefore, it can be spoken about originary passivity open from finitude. This indigence, which is lived within originary passivity and which, from my finitude,
announces a basis, is due precisely to the finitude of self-affection, lived in my
“now”, in my living present.
However -and in spite of the pathos that this “living in self-affection” of
mine may contain-, its vital immanent power is not even remotedly enough for
me to extend the situation of indigence (primordially lived as pleasure-pain) of
my finite life -manifest in an initial basis of actual absolute Erlebnis- to an Absolute basis that is prius of time and which is characterised -owing to the vital
finite pathos- as Life that pervades everything.
This situation of manifestation that we have just indicated is the path of
Appearing of appearance, it is the intermediate situation we mentioned at the
beginning of this paper. It manifests itself as the dawn of my freedom. It could
be even said that in this situation -and before the originary basis of
phenomenality- my freedom is always manifested as problematic: “I will do this
21
Concerning this possibility of substantialisation of finite life into Life, cf. my paper “Pasividad y
sustancia en Filosofía y fenomenología del cuerpo de Michel Henry", Phenomenology 2010, Vol. 3:
Selected Essays from the Euro-Mediterranean Area —Edited by Ion Copoeru, Pavlos Kontos, and Agustín
Serrano de Haro—, Bucharest: Zeta Books / Paris, Arghos-Difusion, 2010.
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
35
36
JOHN DAVID BARRIENTOS RODRÍGUEZ
or that”, “I will have to do this or that”, or this that I present to myself as what
will be this or that. There I take notice of different ends -or I immediately assist
to them- that are present in what moves my subjective life (causal movements)
and which can be declared or not. Thus, on the side of philosophical experience
in the intermediate situation, it is manifested this sense of the absolute of myself that has come to me, that we can initially call “more 'I' than I myself”22.
Such coming to me is partially given by me as far as I expect, but it is not
put by me. It is longer mainly about my pleasuralbe-painful life, without phenomenological distance, but we are pulled -in the intermediate situation- by
sense23. All the “other than myself” pulls my freedom: the world of the others,
the apparent neutrality of the world and my own situation of an always problematic freedom. It seems that it is only me who has to weave the basis of this
tissue of senses, or teleological basis of manifestation, even if I have to risk my
life for the sake of its good. This is due to the fact that this Good of the others
and their world -which is obviously also mine- is above all an expectation given
within myself as a good of myself24, hoped by me; it is my hope, it is an expectation that I cannot let down because here my life is strictly at stake, because it
is my life. In fact, maybe from all this -and as it came only from all this-, in my
finitude, this material basis of good that can sustain the sense of all the other
than myself can be woven. The other possibility would be letting down the expectation of that “more 'I' than I myself”, this absolute of myself; and it would
mean conferring to carelessness -or to that situation of indifference with regard
to problematic freedom- the first meaning of the good over all the other than
myself.
22
"Más yo que yo mismo" or "más tú que tú mismo" is frequently used by García-Baró in his papers and
conferences.
23
The sense establishes a phenomenological distance with regard to something, with regard to the
manifestation of all that is other than me, and with regard to The Absolute. But more than being mere
sense, this situation is teleological. That is so as I am thrown to this “being pulled” by the Enigma in the
extreme indigence of my finite life, within a necessary distance from the teleological basis. The distance
seems to be given by an emptying of infinitude into finitude, pulling my finite life to it; thus, I am redeemed in its teleological basis at the expense of this problematic freedom.
24
We use here “good of myself” and not “my good” to stress the fact that we are referring to something
that does belong to us but that simultaneously I do not contain entirely as a good.
36
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
THE INTERMEDIATE SITUATION. ON AFFECTION AND TIME IN MICHEL HENRY
37
BIBLIOGRAPHY
ABELLA, M. “Edmund Husserl: Génesis y estructura de las Lecciones de fenomenología de la
conciencia interna del tiempo”, ∆αι´µων. Revista de Filosofía, nº 34 (2005), 143-152.
BARRIENTOS, J. D. “Pasividad y sustancia en Filosofía y fenomenología del cuerpo de Michel
Henry”, Phenomenology, 2010, Vol. 3: Selected Essays from the Euro-Mediterranean
Area, I, in COPOERU, P. KONTOS, and A. SERRANO DE HARO (Eds), Paris, Ed.
Bucharest: Zeta Books , Arghos-Difusion, 2010.
― “Cinco datos fenomenológicos: preliminares para una ontología de la subjetividad a partir
de Michel Henry lector de Maine de Biran”, Research Bulletin (Nihon University), 60
(2008),
29-54.
(on-line:
http://www.jdbarrientos.com/Filosofia/cinco-datosfenomenologicos)
― “Logos de mi carne viva. Acerca de la relación vida-lenguaje en Encarnación de Michel
Henry”,
Cuadernos
CANELA,
Vol.
XXI
(2010),
61-76.
(on-line:
http://www.jdbarrientos.com/Filosofia/logos-de-mi-carne-viva).
GARCÍA- BARÓ, M. Vida y mundo. La práctica de la fenomenología, Valladolid, Editorial Trotta, 1999.
HENRY, M. Phénoménologie matérielle, Paris, PUF, 1990.
― Incarnation. Une philosophie de la chair, Paris, Seuil, 2000.
― Philosophie et phénoménologie du corps. Essai sur l'ontologie biranienne, 5ª édition, Paris,
PUF, 2003.
HUSSERL, E. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins hrsg. von
Martin Heidegger, Halle, Niemeyer, 1928.
Investigaciones Fenomenológicas, vol. Monográfico 4/I (2013): Razón y Vida.
37
Descargar